Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-c654p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-01T17:49:45.984Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Supervenience and Computational Explanation in Vision Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Peter Morton*
Affiliation:
Department of Humanities, Mount Royal College

Abstract

According to Marr's theory of vision, computational processes of early vision rely for their success on certain “natural constraints” in the physical environment. I examine the implications of this feature of Marr's theory for the question whether psychological states supervene on neural states. It is reasonable to hold that Marr's theory is nonindividualistic in that, given the role of natural constraints, distinct computational theories of the same neural processes may be justified in different environments. But to avoid trivializing computational explanations, theories must respect methodological solipsism in the sense that within a theory there cannot be differences in content without a corresponding difference in neural states.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank G. Keith Humphrey, David Martens, and especially William Demopoulos for their helpful comments.

Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Humanities, Mount Royal College, Calgary, Alberta T3E 6K6, Canada.

References

Burge, T. (1986), “Individualism and Psychology”, The Philosophical Review 95: 345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Egan, F. (1991), “Must Psychology Be Individualistic?The Philosophical Review 100: 179203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1981), “Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology”. Reprinted in Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 225256.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1987), Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. A. and Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1981), “How Direct is Visual Perception? Some Reflections on Gibson's ‘Ecological Approach‘”, Cognition 9: 139196.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kitcher, P. (1988), “Marr's Computational Theory of Vision”, Philosophy of Science 55: 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marr, D. (1982), Vision. San Francisco: Freeman.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975), “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’”, in Philosophical Papers. Vol. 2, Mind, Language and Reality. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, pp. 215271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stabler, E. P., Jr, . (1987), “Kripke on Functionalism and Automata”, Synthese 70: 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ullman, S. (1979), The Interpretation of Visual Motion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar