Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-j824f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T12:04:00.375Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Causal Equations without Ceteris Paribus Clauses*

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Extract

Some writers have urged that evolutionary theory produces generalizations that hold only ceteris paribus, that is, provided “everything else is equal.” Others have claimed that all laws in the special sciences, or even all laws in science generally, hold only ceteris paribus. However, if we lack a way to determine when everything else really is equal, hedging generalizations with the phrase “ceteris paribus” renders those generalizations vacuous. In what follows, I propose a solution to this problem for the case of causal equations from classical population genetics. My proviso is generated on the basis of a couple of conceptual maneuvers, “tricks,” which should be usable elsewhere too.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

*

This article is the winner of the 2007 PSA Graduate Student Essay Award.

References

Ariew, Andre, and Matthen, Mohan. 2002. “Two Ways of Thinking about Fitness and Natural Selection.” Journal of Philosophy 99 (2): 5583.Google Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 1979. “Causal Laws and Effective Strategies.” Noûs 13 (4): 419–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, Nancy. 1999. The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christiansen, Freddy Bugge. 1975. “Hard and Soft Selection in a Subdivided Population.” American Naturalist 109 (965): 1116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cresswell, James E., and Sayre, Christopher F.. 1991. “Can Evolutionary Stable Strategies Exist?Oikos 60:382–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darden, Lindley, and Cain, Joseph A.. 1989. “Selection Type Theories.” Philosophy of Science 56 (1): 106–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Earman, John, and Roberts, John. 1999. “Ceteris Paribus There Are No Provisos.” Synthese 118:438–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Earman, John, Roberts, John, and Smith, Sheldon. 2002. “Ceteris Paribus Lost.” Erkenntnis 57 (3): 281301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry. 1991. “You Can Fool Some of the People All of the Time, Everything Else Being Equal.” Mind 100:2034.Google Scholar
Gale, Jeff 1990. Theoretical Population Genetics. London: Unwin Hyman.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gildenhuys, Peter. 2009. “An Explication of the Causal Dimension of Drift.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (3): 521–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillespie, John. 1998. Population Genetics: A Concise Guide. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Glymour, Clark, and Cooper, Greg, eds. 1999. Computation, Causation, Discovery. Cambridge, MA: American Association for Artificial Intelligence.Google Scholar
Glymour, Clark, Scheines, Richard, and Spirtes, Peter. 1993. Causation, Prediction, and Search. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hedrick, Philip W. 2005. Genetics of Populations. 3rd ed. Boston: Jones & Bartlett.Google Scholar
Hori, Michio. 1993. “Frequency-Dependent Natural Selection in the Handedness of Scale-Eating Cichlid Fish.” Science 260:216–19.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hulten, Geoff, Chickering, David Maxwell, and Heckerman, David. 2003. “Learning Bayesian Networks from Dependency Networks: A Preliminary Study.” Paper presented at the Ninth International Workshop on Artificial Intelligence and Statistics, Key West, FL, January 36.Google Scholar
Lange, Marc. 1993. “Natural Laws and the Problem of Provisos.” Erkenntnis 38:233–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lange, Marc 2002. “Who's Afraid of Ceteris Paribus Laws? Or, How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Them.” Erkenntnis 3:407–23.Google Scholar
Morreau, Michael. 1999. “Other Things Being Equal.” Philosophical Studies 96:163–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pearl, Judea. 2000. Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pietroski, Paul, and Rey, Georges. 1995. “When Other Things Aren’t Equal: Saving Ceteris Paribus Laws from Vacuity.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (1): 81110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rice, Sean. 2004. Evolutionary Theory: Mathematical and Conceptual Foundations. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Roughgarden, J. 1971. “Density-Dependent Natural Selection.” Ecology 52 (3): 453–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, Elliott. 1984. The Nature of Selection: Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott, and Lewontin, Richard C.. 1982. “Artifact, Cause, and Genic Selection.” Philosophy of Science 49 (2): 157–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walsh, Denis M., Lewens, Tim, and Ariew, Andre. 2002. “The Trials of Life: Natural Selection and Random Drift.” Philosophy of Science 69 (3): 452–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, James 2003. Making Things Happen. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zhang, Jiji, and Spirtes, Peter. 2008. “Detection of Unfaithfulness and Robust Causal Inference.” Minds & Machines 18:239–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar