Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-rvbq7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T07:15:58.544Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Explanatory Unification and the Problem of Asymmetry

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Eric Barnes*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Denison University

Abstract

Philip Kitcher has proposed a theory of explanation based on the notion of unification. Despite the genuine interest and power of the theory, I argue here that the theory suffers from a fatal deficiency: It is intrinsically unable to account for the asymmetric structure of explanation, and thus ultimately falls prey to a problem similar to the one which beset Hempel's D-N model. I conclude that Kitcher is wrong to claim that one can settle the issue of an argument's explanatory force merely on the basis of considerations about the unifying power of the argument pattern the argument instantiates.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1992 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful to the National Endowment for the Humanities for research support. For comments and criticisms on an early draft of this paper I am grateful to Paul Humphreys, Noretta Koertge, Douglas Ehring, Jonathan Kvanvig, Jesse Hobbs, and an anonymous Philosophy of Science referee. For extensive and insightful analyses of the Newtonian example I am particularly grateful to Todd Jones and Adolf Grünbaum.

Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, Denison University, Granville, OH 43023, USA.

References

Feigl, H. (1970), “The ‘Orthodox’ View of Theories: Remarks in Defense as Well as Critique”, in Radner, M. and Winokur, S., (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 4, Analyses of Theories and Methods of Physics and Psychology. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 316.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. (1974), “Explanation and Scientific Understanding”, Journal of Philosophy 71: 519.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grünbaum, A. (1963), Philosophical Problems of Space and Time. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Humphreys, P. (1989), The Chances of Explanation: Causal Explanation in the Social, Medical, and Physical Sciences. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1981), “Explanatory Unification”, Philosophy of Science 48: 507531.10.1086/289019CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1986), “Projecting the Order of Nature”, in Butts, R., (ed.), R. Butts, Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 201235.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1989), “Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World”, in Kitcher, P. and Salmon, W. C., (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 13, Scientific Explanation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 410505.Google Scholar
Koertge, N. (1989), “Explanation vs. Unification”. Reprinted in Weingartner, P. and Schurz, G., (eds.), Berichte des 13. Internationalen Wittgenstein-Symposiums. Vienna: Holder-Dichler-Tempsky, pp. 156159.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1978), “The Causal Structure of the World and the Difference between Past and Future”. Translated by E. H. Schneewind. in Reichenbach, M. and Cohen, R. S., (eds.), Hans Reichenbach: Selected Writings, 1909–1953, vol. 2. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 81119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. (1984), Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar