Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-8zxtt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-08T16:54:17.875Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Indices of Theory Promise

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Laurie Anne Whitt*
Affiliation:
Department of Humanities, Michigan Technological University

Abstract

Figuring prominently in their decisions regarding which theories to pursue are scientists' appeals to the promise or lack of promise of those theories. Yet philosophy of science has had little to say about how one is to assess theory promise. This essay identifies several indices that might be consulted to determine whether or not a theory is promising and worthy of pursuit. Various historical examples of appeals to such indices are introduced.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1992 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

A version of this paper was read at the Ninth International Congress for the Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science in Uppsala, Sweden, and to the Philosophy Department of the University of New Mexico at Albuquerque. I am grateful to members of these audiences, and to a referee for Philosophy of Science, for their comments.

Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Humanities, Michigan Technological University, 1400 Townsend Drive, Houghton, MI 49931, USA.

References

Boltzmann, L. (1964), Lectures on Gas Theory. Translated by S. G. Brush. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.10.1525/9780520327474CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boltzmann, L. (1974), Theoretical Physics and Philosophical Problems: Selected Writings. Holland: Reidel.10.1007/978-94-010-2091-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, R. (1979), “Metaphor and Theory Change: What is ‘Metaphor’ a Metaphor For?”, in Ortony, A. (ed.), Metaphor and Thought. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, pp. 356408.Google Scholar
Crosland, M. P. (1968), “The First Reception of Dalton's Atomic Theory in France”, in Cardwell, D. (ed.), John Dalton and the Progress of Science. New York: Barnes & Nobel, pp. 274287.Google Scholar
Dalton, J. ([1808] 1964), A New System of Chemical Philosophy. New York: Philosophical Library.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davy, H. (1840), The Collected Works of Sir Humphrey Davy. vols. 1–9. London: Smith, Elder & Co.Google Scholar
Duhem, P. ([1914] 1954), The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory. Translated by P. Wiener. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Farber, E. (1969), The Evolution of Chemistry: A History of Its Ideas, Methods, and Materials. 2d ed. New York: The Ronald Press.Google Scholar
Gardiner, M. (1979), “Realism and Instrumentalism in 19th Century Atomism”, Philosophy of Science 46: 134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gentner, D. (1982), “Are Scientific Analogies Metaphors?”, in Miall, D. (ed.), Metaphor: Problems and Perspectives. Brighten, Sussex: Harvester Press, pp. 106132.Google Scholar
Gentner, D. and Grudin, J. (1985), “The Evolution of Mental Metaphors in Psychology: A 90-Year Retrospective”, American Psychologist 40: 181192.10.1037/0003-066X.40.2.181CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanson, N. R. (1958), Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Harman, P. (1982), Energy, Force and Matter: The Conceptual Development of Nineteenth-Century Physics. New York: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511665394CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holmes, F. (1962), “From Elective Affinities to Chemical Equilibria: Berthollet's Law of Mass Action”, Chymia 8: 105145.10.2307/27757221CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. (1970), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2d ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. (1977), The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.10.7208/chicago/9780226217239.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1978), The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1977), Progress and Its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Maxwell, J. C. ([1892] 1904), A Treatise on Electricity and Magnetism. vol. 2. 3d ed. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Maxwell, J. C. ([1890] 1965), The Scientific Papers of James Clerk Maxwell. vol. 2. Edited by Niven, W. D. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
McMullin, E. (1976), “The Fertility of Theory and the Unit for Appraisal in Science”, in R. Cohen, P. Feyerabend, and M. Wartofsky (eds.), Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 39, Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos. Holland: Reidel, pp. 395432.10.1007/978-94-010-1451-9_25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merz, J. ([1907] 1912), A History of European Thought in the Nineteenth Century. vols. 1–2. London: William Blackwood & Sons.Google Scholar
Muir, P. (1884), A Treatise on the Principles of Chemistry. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nye, M. (1972), Molecular Reality: A Perspective on the Scientific Work of Jean Perrin. New York: American Elsevier.Google Scholar
Schelar, V. (1966), “Thermochemistry and the Third Law of Thermodynamics”, Chymia 11: 99121.10.2307/27757262CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thagard, P. (1978), “The Best Explanation: Criteria for Theory Choice”, The Journal of Philosophy 75: 7692.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thagard, P. (1988), Computational Philosophy of Science. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.10.7551/mitpress/1968.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Meisen, A. (1960), From Atomos to Atom: The History of the Concept Atom. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Whewell, W. (1847), The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, Founded upon Their History. 2d ed. London: J. W. Parker.Google Scholar
Whitt, L. A. (1988), “Conceptual Dimensions of Theory Appraisal”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 19: 517529.10.1016/0039-3681(88)90013-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitt, L. A. (1990a), “Atoms or Affinities? The Ambivalent Reception of Daltonian Theory”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 21: 5789.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitt, L. A. (1990b), “Theory Pursuit: Between Discovery and Acceptance”, PSA 1990, vol. 1. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 467483.Google Scholar
Wollaston, W. H. (1814), “A Synoptic Scale of Chemical Equivalents”, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society 104: 122.Google Scholar