Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-swr86 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-18T07:31:39.714Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Morgan's Canon Revisited

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

The famous ethological maxim known as ‘Morgan's Canon’ continues to be an object of interpretive controversy. I reconsider Morgan's Canon in light of two questions: First, what did Morgan intend? Second, is this, or perhaps some reinterpretation of the Canon, useful within cognitive ethology? As for the first issue, Morgan's distinction between higher and lower faculties is suggestive of an early supervenience concept. As for the second issue, the Canon, both in its original form and in various recent rereadings, offers nothing useful to cognitive ethology.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I would like to thank Elliot Sober, Collin Allen, and the anonymous referees at Philosophy of Science for helpful comments.

References

Allen, Colin, and Bekoff, Marc (1997), Species of Mind: The Philosophy and Biology of Cognitive Ethology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bekoff, Marc, and Allen, Colin (1997), “Slayers, Skeptics, and Proponents”, in Mitchell, R.W., Thompson, N., and Miles, L. (eds.), Anthropomorphism, Anecdotes, and Animals: The Emperor’s New Clothes? Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 313334.Google Scholar
Bickle, John (1998), Psychoneural Reduction: The New Wave. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Block, Ned (1981), “Psychologism and Behaviorism”, Psychologism and Behaviorism 90:543.Google Scholar
Boring, Edwin G. (1950), A History of Experimental Psychology. 2nd ed. New York: Appleton Century Crofts.Google Scholar
Burghardt, Gordon M. (1991), “Cognitive Ethology and Critical Anthropomorphism: A Snake with Two Heads and Hognosed Snakes That Play Dead”, in Ristau, C. A. (ed.), Cognitive Ethology: The Minds of Other Animals. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 5390.Google Scholar
Cartmill, Matt (2000), “Animal Consciousness: Some Philosophical, Methodological, and Evolutionary Problems”, Animal Consciousness: Some Philosophical, Methodological, and Evolutionary Problems 40:835846.Google Scholar
Costal, Alan (1993), “How Lloyd Morgan’s Canon Backfired”, How Lloyd Morgan’s Canon Backfired 29:113122.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald (1970), “Mental Events”, in Foster, L. and Swanson, J. W. (eds.), Experience and Theory. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 79101.Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. (1976), “Conditions of Personhood”, in Rorty, Amélie (ed.), The Identities of Persons. Berkeley: University of California Press, 175196.Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. (1987), The Intentional Stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
de Wall, Frans (2001), The Ape and the Sushi Master. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Dewsbury, Donald A. (2000), “On Misrepresenting Lloyd Morgan’s Canon: Comment on Thomas”, http://htpprints.yorku.ca/archive/00000044/00Dewsbury-on-Thomas.htm; accessed on 4/29/04.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (1999), “Not So Clever Hans”, Not So Clever Hans 21:1213.Google Scholar
Galef, Bennett G. Jr. (1996), “Historical Origins: The Making of a Science”, in Houck, Lynne D. and Drickamer, Lee C. (eds.), Foundations of Animal Behavior: Classic Papers with Commentaries. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 512.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon (1992), “‘Downward Causation’ in Emergence and Non-reductive Physicalism”, in Beckermann, Ansgar, Flohr, Hans, and Kim, Jaegwon (eds.), Emergence or Reduction?—Prospects for Non-reductive Physicalism. Berlin: de Gruyter, 119139.Google Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon (1993), “Supervenience as a Philosophical Concept”, in Kim, Jaegwon (ed.), Supervenience and Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 131160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon (1995), “Supervenience”, in Guttenplan, Samuel (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Basil Blackwell, 575583.Google Scholar
Kimler, William C. (2000), “Reading Morgan’s Canon: Reduction and the Unification in the Forging of a Science of the Mind”, Reading Morgan’s Canon: Reduction and the Unification in the Forging of a Science of the Mind 40:853861.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Robert W. (1986), “A Framework for Discussing Deception”, in Mitchell, Robert W. and Thompson, Nicholas S. (eds.), Deception: Perspectives on Human and Nonhuman Deceit. Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 340.Google Scholar
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1890), Animal Life and Intelligence. London: Edward Arnold.Google Scholar
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1892), “The Limits of Animal Intelligence”, in International Congress of Experimental Psychology, Second Session. London: 4448.Google Scholar
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1893), “The Limits of Animal Intelligence”, The Limits of Animal Intelligence 54:223239.Google Scholar
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1894), Introduction to Comparative Psychology. London: Walter Scott.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1903), Introduction to Comparative Psychology. 2nd ed. London: Walter Scott.Google Scholar
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1906), The Interpretation of Nature. New York: G. P. Putnam.Google Scholar
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1923), Emergent Evolution. London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1925), Life, Mind, and Spirit. New York: Holt.Google Scholar
Morgan, C. Lloyd (1932), “C. Lloyd Morgan”, in Murchison, Carl (ed.), A History of Psychology in Autobiography, Vol. 2. Worchester, MA: Clark University Press, 237264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Newbury, Edward (1954), “Current Interpretation and Significance of Lloyd Morgan’s Canon”, Current Interpretation and Significance of Lloyd Morgan’s Canon 51:7074.Google ScholarPubMed
Radick, Gregory (2000), “Morgan’s Canon, Garner’s Phonograph, and the Evolutionary Origins of Language and Reason”, Morgan’s Canon, Garner’s Phonograph, and the Evolutionary Origins of Language and Reason 33:323.Google Scholar
Radner, Daisie, and Radner, Michael (1989), Animal Consciousness. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Regan, Tom (1983), The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Rollin, Bernard E. (1989), The Unheeded Cry: Animal Consciousness, Animal Pain and Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Skinner, B. F. (1938), The Behavior of Organisms. New York: Appleton Crofts.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1988), Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evidence, and Inference. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1997), “Morgan’s Canon”, in Cummins, Denise and Allen, Colin (eds.), The Evolution of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 224242.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (2001), “The Principle of Conservatism in Cognitive Ethology”, in Walsh, Denis M. (ed.), Naturalism, Evolution and Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 225238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Roger K. (1998), “Lloyd Morgan’s Canon”, in Greenberg, Gary and Haraway, Maury M. (eds.), Comparative Psychology: A Handbook. New York: Garland Press, 156163.Google Scholar
Thomas, Roger K. (2001), “Lloyd Morgan’s Canon: A History of Misrepresentation”, http://htpprints.yorku.ca/archive/00000017/00/MCWeb.htm; accessed on 4/29/04.Google Scholar
Vauclair, Jacques (1996), Animal Cognition: An Introduction to Modern Comparative Psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wilder, Hugh (1996), “Interpretive Cognitive Psychology”, in Bekoff, Marc and Jamieson, Dale (eds.), Readings in Animal Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2945.Google Scholar