Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-rnpqb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-28T10:18:54.389Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Statistics, Pragmatics, Induction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Abstract

1. Deductive and Inductive Inference. Within the traditional treatments of scientific method, e.g., in (2) and (25), it was customary to divide scientific inference into two parts: deductive and inductive. Deductive inference was taken to mean the activity of deducing theorems from postulates and definitions, whereas inductive inference represented the activity of constructing a general statement from a set of particular “facts.” Deductive inference was relegated to the mathematical (formal) sciences, and inductive inference to the empirical (non-formal) sciences. As a consequence, the whole of science was split into two quite distinct parts: deductive science was conceived to start with precise axioms, postulates, and definitions, and its method consisted in drawing inferences from these “givens” in such a way that if the original assumptions are taken as true, then the theorems must be taken as true also. The obligation behind this “must” of the mathematical sciences was an obligation based on strict rules of deductive inference; in the earlier analyses, it was supposed that these rules were all aspects of the general theory of the syllogism, as it was described in an almost complete form in (2) but in later work the rules have been formalized in more general terms (17). Inductive inference, on the other hand, was supposed to start with observed facts; these facts, or “data,” were presumably given by the senses, and described particular aspects of the external world. If the facts were given in a certain way, then the empirical scientist could “infer” a generalized description; this generalization had the characteristic that if it were granted as true, then all the facts could be deduced as consequences. The inductive process admittedly does not lead to unique generalizations (no more than the deductive process leads to unique theorems), and the philosopher of science searched for other defining characteristics of good inference, such as “simplicity” and “convenience.” These empirical generalizations were taken to be “descriptions of the phenomenal world of the scientist”; a further inductive step might be taken by constructing a set of very general principles out of the more specialized generalizations within specific research problems. These “higher” inductive inferences were regarded as “theories,” which could be studied by themselves within the method of deductive inference. The scientist was then described as “checking” theory by determining whether or not the predicted consequences deduced from theory actually hold in the phenomenal world.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1948

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

This paper is based in part on material contained in (11) and (13).

References

1. Allport, G. W. Personality: A Psychological Interpretation. Henry Holt. (1937).Google Scholar
2. Aristotle. Organon.Google Scholar
3. Brown, G. W., and Tukey, J. W. Some Distributions of Sample Means. An. Math. Stat., XVII (1946), 1.Google Scholar
4. Carnap, R. On Inductive Logic. Phil. Sci., 12 (1945), 72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
5. Carnap, R. On the Application of Inductive Logic. Phil. and Phen. Res. VIII (1947), 133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
6. Carnap, R. Probability as a Guide in Life. J. Phil., XLIV (1947), 141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
7. Carnap, R. Reply to Nelson Goodman. Phil. and Phen. Res., VIII (1948), 461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
8. Church, A. Introduction to Mathematical Logic. Princeton University Press (1944).Google Scholar
9. Churchman, C. W. The Consumer and His Interests in Measurement of Consumer Interest. Ed. by Churchman, C. W., Ackoff, R. L., and Wax, M.. Univ. of Penn. Press (1947).Google Scholar
10. Churchman, C. W. Theory of Experimental Inference. Macmillan 1948.Google Scholar
11. Churchman, C. W. Logic of Statistical Tests. Bulletin of the Institute of Experimental Method, I, No. 3 (1947), 12.Google Scholar
12. Churchman, C. W., and Ackoff, R. L. Psychologistics. Phila. Pa. (1947), (mimeographed).Google Scholar
13. Churchman, C. W., and Ackoff, R. L. Footnote to the “Logic of Statistical Tests.” Bulletin of the Institute of Experimental Method, I, No. 4 (1947), 21.Google Scholar
14. Churchman, C. W., and Ackoff, R. L. Varieties of Unification. Phil. Sci., 13 (1946), 287.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
15. Churchman, C. W., and Ackoff, R. L. An Experimental Definition of Personality. Phil. Sci., 14 (1947), 304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
16. Churchman, C. W., and Epstein, B. Tests of Increased Severity. J. Amer. Stat. Assoc., 41 (1946), 567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
17. Curry, H. B. Some Aspects of Mathematical Rigor. Bulletin Amer. Math. Soc., 47 (1941), 221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
18. Dewey, J. Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. Henry Holt (1938).Google Scholar
19. Ferris, C. D., Grubbs, F. E., and Weaver, C. L. Operating Characteristics for the Common Statistical Tests of Significance. An. Math. Stat., XVII, (1946), 178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
20. Geiger, G. R. Philosophy and the Social Order. Houghton Mifflin (1947).Google Scholar
21. Goodman, N. A Query on Confirmation. J. Phil., XLIII, (1946), 383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
22. Hempel, C. G. A Purely Syntactical Definition of Confirmation. J. Sym. Logic, VIII, (1943), 122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
23. Lepley, R. Verifiability of Value. Columbia Univ. Press (1944).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
24. Lundberg, G. A. Social Research. Longman's Green, (1946)Google Scholar
25. Mill, J. S. A System of Logic. Ratiocinative and Inductive. Harper Bros. (1846).Google Scholar
26. Mosteller, F. On Some Useful ‘Inefficient’ Statistics. An. Math. Stat. XVII, (1946), 377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
27. Neyman, J., and Pearson, E. S. On the Problem of the Most Efficient Tests of Statistical Hypotheses. Phil. Trans. Roy. Soc. of London, Ser. A. 231, (1933), 289.Google Scholar
28. Oppenheim, P., and Helmer, O. A Syntactical Definition of Probability and Degree of Confirmation. J. Sym. Logic. 10, (1945), 25.Google Scholar
29. Oppenheim, P., and Hempel, C. G. A Definition of “Degree of Confirmation.” Phil. Sci., 12, (1945), 98.Google Scholar
30. Peirce, C. S. Collected Works. Ed. by C. M. Hartshorne and P. Weiss. Harvard University Press (1931-5).Google Scholar
31. Poincaré, H. The Foundations of Science. The Science Press (1921).Google Scholar
32. Quine, W. V. Mathematical Logic. W. W. Norton Co. (1940).Google Scholar
33. Singer, E. A. Philosophy of Experiment. The Symposium, 1, (1930), 149.Google Scholar
34. Singer, E. A. Experience and Reflection. To appear.Google Scholar
35. Thurstone, L. L. Primary Mental Abilities. Univ. of Chicago Press (1938).Google Scholar
36. Von Neumann, J. Zur Hilbert Beweistheorie. Math. Zeitschr., 26, (1927), 1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
37. Wald, A. On the Principles of Statistical Inference. Notre Dame Math. Lectures, (1942).Google Scholar