Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-c9gpj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-09T04:59:16.195Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

“Truer”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

D. Goldstick
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy University of Toronto
B. O'Neill
Affiliation:
Department of Industrial Engineering Northwestern University

Abstract

When can one say that a new theory is truer than the old one it contradicts, even though neither is absolutely true? We are primarily concerned with the case in which the conflicting theories offer answers to the same questions, and so we do not introduce considerations of “logical width”. We propose that part of the new theory is truer than part of the old one when the former part gets right whatever the latter part got right while the former does not make any new mistakes. Pragmatic considerations will determine the relative importance of whatever new mistakes the new theory does make as a whole. To avoid artificial counterexamples, we restrict the parts compared to those that are “convex”. A “convex” theory is one that holds in all cases intermediate between any two cases in which it holds.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1988 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Cunningham, F., and Goldstick, D. (1979), “Marxism and Epistemological Relativism”, Social Praxis 6: 237253.Google Scholar
Goldstick, D. (1980), “Cognitive Synonymy”, Dialectica 34: 183203.10.1111/j.1746-8361.1980.tb00773.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hattiangadi, J. N. (1983), “A Methodology Without Methodological Rules”, in R. S. Cohen and M. W. Wartofsky (eds.), Language, Logic and Method. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, volume 31. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 103151.10.1007/978-94-009-7702-0_4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hilpinen, R. (1976), “Approximate Truth and Truthlikeness”, in M. Przełęcki, K. Szaniawski and R. Wójcicki (eds.), Formal Methods in the Methodology of Empirical Sciences. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 1942.10.1007/978-94-010-1135-8_2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1973), “Pierce and the Trivialization of the Self-Correcting Thesis”, in R. N. Giere and R. Westfall (eds.), Foundations of Scientific Method: The Nineteenth Century. Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, pp. 275306.Google Scholar
Miller, D. (1974), “Popper's Qualitative Theory of Verisimilitude”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25: 166177.10.1093/bjps/25.2.166CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, D. (1975), “The Accuracy of Predictions”, Synthese 30: 159191.10.1007/BF00485304CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1978), “Truthlikeness: Comments on Recent Discussion”, Synthese 38: 281329.10.1007/BF00486154CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1979), “Verisimilitude, Theory-Change, and Scientific Progress”, in I. Niiniluoto and R. Tuomela (eds.), The Logic and Epistemology of Scientific Change. Acta Philosophica Fennica 30(1978): 243264.Google Scholar
Oddie, G. (1981), “Verisimilitude Reviewed”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32: 237265.10.1093/bjps/32.3.237CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oddie, G. (1986), Likeness to Truth. Dordrecht: Reidel.10.1007/978-94-009-4658-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oddie, G. (1987), “The Picture Theory of Truthlikeness”, in T. F. A. Kuipers (ed.), What is Closer-to-the-Truth? A Parade of Approaches to Truthlikeness. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, vol. 10, pp. 2545.Google Scholar
Pearce, D. (1983), “Truthlikeness and Translation: A Comment on Oddie”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34: 380385.10.1093/bjps/34.4.380CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1963), Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. London: Routledge Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1972), Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Priestley, J. (1775), The History and Present State of Electricity, With Original Experiments. volume 2, 3d ed. London: pp. 1516.Google Scholar
Tichý, P. (1974), “On Popper's Definitions of Verisimilitude”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25: 155160.10.1093/bjps/25.2.155CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tichý, P. (1976), “Verisimilitude Redefined”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27: 2542.10.1093/bjps/27.1.25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tichý, P. (1978), “Verisimilitude Revisited”, Synthese 38: 175196.10.1007/BF00486149CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tuomela, R. (1978), “Theory-Distance and Verisimilitude”, Synthese 38: 213246.10.1007/BF00486151CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Urbach, P. (1983), “Intimations of Similarity: The Shaky Basis of Verisimilitude”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34: 266275.10.1093/bjps/34.3.266CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vetter, H. (1977), “A New Concept of Verisimilitude”, Theory and Decision 8: 369375.10.1007/BF00141535CrossRefGoogle Scholar