Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-xq9c7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-08T13:47:59.655Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Some Difficulties in Utilitarianism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  25 February 2009

Pamela M. Clark
Affiliation:
University of Liverpool

Extract

Utilitarianism has had an unfortunate history. Its most influential exponents, Bentham and John Stuart Mill, set it out in such a way as to expose it to facile criticism and even to ridicule, and it has never fully recovered from this ill-omened start. In spite of the criticism and the ridicule, however, it still bulks large in ethical studies, and many people still have a hankering sympathy with it.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1954

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 245 note 1 Nic. Ethics 1095 a 18. He actually defines “the good” as “happiness.”

page 245 note 2 See below.

page 245 note 3 See Stevenson, Ethics and Language, p. 82.

page 245 note 4 Buddhism, as I understand it, seems to be an exception.

page 245 note 5 Principles of Morals and Legislation, Ch. I, para. III.

page 246 note 1 To save space and unnecessary complication I usually omit reference to unhappiness and pain when speaking of their opposites, but such reference is implied where it is relevant. Later I shall consider whether pleasure and pain are equally important, but I do not wish to raise this point here.

page 246 note 2 For a different approach, see Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind, pp. 107–10.

page 247 note 1 Cf. John Stuart Mill's complaint that the Utilitarians are much misunderstood (Utilitarianism, Ch. I). In this he passes continually from “happiness” to “pleasure” and back again.