Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-g78kv Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-27T22:53:46.119Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Taking War Seriously

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 August 2018

Abstract

Just war theory − as advanced by Michael Walzer, among others − fails to take war seriously enough. This is because it proposes that we regulate war with systematic rules that are comparable to those of a game. Three types of claims are advanced. The first is phenomenological: that the theory's abstract nature interferes with our judgment of what is, and should be, going on. The second is meta-ethical: that the theory's rules are not, in fact, systematic after all, there being inherent contradictions between them. And the third is practical: that by getting people to view war as like a game, the theory promotes its ‘aestheticization’ (play being a central mode of the aesthetic) such that those who fight are encouraged to act in dangerous ways. And war, it goes without saying, is already dangerous enough.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 In Spaulding, Susan Thompson and Spaulding, Francis Trow (eds), Open Gates: A Book of Poems for Boys and Girls of Junior High School Age (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1924), 17Google Scholar.

2 See, for example, Searle, John R., Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 3342CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 See von Clausewitz, Carl, On War, eds and trans. Howard, Michael and Parat, Peter (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1976), bk. 1, ch. 1, § 24Google Scholar.

4 See Clausewitz, op. cit. note 3, bk. 1, ch. 1, § 21, 23.

5 See Clausewitz, op. cit. note 3, bk. 1, ch. 1, § 3.

6 Walzer, , Just and Unjust Wars: A Moral Argument with Historical Illustrations (New York: Basic Books, 1977), 287Google Scholar.

7 Walzer, , ‘Emergency Ethics’, in Arguing About War (New Haven, CN: Yale University Press, 2004), 33Google Scholar; see also Walzer, op. cit. note 6, ch. 16.

8 Walzer, op. cit. note 6, 131.

9 See Walzer, op. cit. note 6, 34.

10 Rawls, , A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999, rev. ed.), 462Google Scholar; see also Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), 204Google Scholar.

11 Walzer, op. cit. note 6, 25.

12 Walzer, op. cit. note 6, 27; see also 35.

13 See my ‘Taking Politics Seriously – But Not Too Seriously’ (forthcoming).

14 See my On the Minimal Global Ethic’, in Patriotic Elaborations: Essays in Practical Philosophy (Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen's University Press, 2009)Google Scholar.

15 I first distinguished between ‘expressive’ rules and those that I call ‘regulative’ in my Shall We Dance? A Patriotic Politics for Canada (Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen's University Press, 2003), chs 1–2Google Scholar.

16 See my Dirty Hands: The One and the Many’, The Monist 101(2) (Apr. 2018): 120Google Scholar.

17 Margalit and Walzer, ‘Israel: Civilians and Combatants’, New York Review of Books, 14 May 2009, 21–22.

18 See Kasher, and Yadlin, , ‘Assassination and Preventive Killing’, SAIS Review 25(1) (Winter-Spring 2005): 41–57, 5051CrossRefGoogle Scholar; as well as Kasher, ‘The Ethics of Protective Edge’, Jewish Review of Books, Fall 2014.

19 See Walzer, op. cit. note 6, ch. 9.

20 Margalit and Walzer, op. cit. note 17, 21.

21 Margalit and Walzer, op. cit. note 17, 22.

22 Walzer, op. cit. note 6, 36. Walzer is even more explicit in a later article where he writes that in a just war it is, from a strictly moral perspective, only ‘the civilian deaths that should bother us’. Walzer, , ‘Responsibility and Proportionality in State and Nonstate Wars’, Parameters 39(1) (Spring 2009): 4052, 51Google Scholar.

23 Manchester, , Goodbye Darkness: A Memoir of the Pacific War (London: Little, Brown, 2002), 67Google Scholar.

24 Grossman, , On Killing: The Psychological Cost of Learning to Kill in War and Society (New York: Little, Brown, 1996), 196Google Scholar.

25 Grossman, op. cit. note 24.

26 Walzer, op. cit. note 6, 144.

27 See Walzer, op. cit. note 6, 34–41.

28 Quoted in Grossman, op. cit. note 24, 174; see also 109.

29 Grossman, op. cit. note 24, 156–57.

30 For some comments from soldiers expressing their feelings of guilt about killing, see Grossman, op. cit. note 24, 88–89.

31 Walzer, op. cit. note 6, 143.

32 See Walzer, op. cit. note 6, 138–43.

33 In Bishop, Poems (ed.) Hamilton, Saskia (New York: Farrar Straus and Giroux, 2011), 4344Google Scholar.

34 See Thomas Harding, ‘Forgotten SAS diary reveals mission to capture Rommel’, The Telegraph, 23 September 2011.

35 See Walzer, , ‘Response to McMahan's Paper’, Philosophia 34 (2006): 4345CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

36 Margalit and Walzer, op. cit. note 17, 21.

37 See Dudziak, Mary L., ‘Law, War, and the History of Time’, California Law Review 98(5) (Oct. 2010): 16691709Google Scholar.

38 Mégret, Frédéric would disagree: ‘War and the Vanishing Battlefield’, Loyola University of Chicago International Law Review 9(1) (Fall/Winter 2011): 131–55Google Scholar. Unsurprisingly, at 133, Mégret welcomes the idea that ‘there is more than a passing analogy between the battlefield and the fields on which sports are played’.

39 Margalit and Walzer, op. cit. note 17, 22.

40 Walzer, op. cit. note 6, 296–97.

41 Jeff McMahan has presented a different argument against the possibility of keeping jus in bello separate from jus ad bellum in his The Ethics of Killing in War’, in Kasher, Asa (ed.) Ethics of War and Conflict, vol. 2: Just War Doctrine (New York: Routledge, 2014)Google Scholar. Essentially, McMahan's claim is that combatants who fight justly in the sense of targeting only other soldiers nevertheless cannot be described as fighting defensively, and so justly, if they do so as part of an unjust surprise attack on another country.

42 See Grossman, op. cit. note 24, 169. He quotes an Israeli tank gunner: ‘You see it all as if it were happening on a TV screen… It occurred to me at the time; I see someone running and I shoot at him, and he falls, and it all looks like something on TV. I don't see people, that's one good thing about it.’ Grossman, op. cit. note 24, 170.

43 See Grossman, op. cit. note 24, 164–67.

44 Berlin, , ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’, in Liberty: Incorporating Four Essays on Liberty (ed.) Hardy, Henry (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 217CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Berlin is quoting Joseph Schumpeter.

45 See Walzer, ‘The Triumph of Just War Theory (and the Dangers of Success)’, in Arguing about War, op. cit. note 7, 12.

46 See Kennedy, David, Of War and Law (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006), ch. 3Google Scholar.

47 Walzer, op. cit. note 22, 42.

48 Walzer, , ‘Political Action: The Problem of Dirty Hands’, in Thinking Politically: Essays in Political Theory (ed.) Miller, David (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2007), 286Google Scholar.

49 Rawls, , The Law of Peoples: with ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited’ (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1999), 98Google Scholar; Rawls, , ‘Fifty Years after Hiroshima’, in Collected Papers (ed.) Freeman, Samuel (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 57Google Scholar, where the full sentence reads: ‘Without the crisis exemption, those bombings are great evils.’ With it, presumably, one can keep one's hands clean.

50 See Lerner, Melvin J., The Belief in a Just World: A Fundamental Delusion (New York: Plenum Press, 1980)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

51 The latter has been described thus: ‘Football is about making your opponent think you are going to pass rather than run, run here rather than there, throw to this receiver rather than that one. Receivers develop moves to fake out defenders.’ Miller, William Ian, ‘Deceit in War and Trade’, in Martin, Clancy (ed.) The Philosophy of Deception (New York: Oxford University Press, 2009), 50Google Scholar.

52 Bruce Dowbiggen has even suggested that there's something hypocritical about Canadians celebrating our country's invention of peacekeeping (peacekeepers are often portrayed on Canadian currency) and yet continuing to support violence in hockey. See Dowbiggen, , The Meaning of Puck: How Hockey Explains Modern Canada (Toronto: Key Porter Books, 2008), 22, 102Google Scholar.

53 Hedges, Chris, War Is a Force that Gives Us Meaning (New York: Public Affairs, 2002), 3Google Scholar. Evidently, Hedges finds war meaningful in an aesthetic, because sublime, sense. Kant would agree: Even war, if it is conducted with order and reverence for the rights of civilians, has something sublime about it.Critique of the Power of Judgment (ed.) Guyer, Paul, trans. Guyer, and Matthews, Eric (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 5:263Google Scholar.

54 David Shields even identifies ‘playground’ as one of the themes adhered to by New York Times war photographers. See his War Is Beautiful: The Times, New York Pictorial Guide to the Glamour of Armed Conflict (New York: powerHouse Books, 2015)Google Scholar.

55 Hedges, op. cit. note 53, 171–72.

56 See Kierkegaard, , ‘The Present Age’, in Two Ages: The Age of Revolution and the Present Age, A Literary Review (eds and trans.) Howard, V. and Hong, Edna H. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978), 9496Google Scholar. For a more contemporary take on this schadenfreude, see Epstein, Joseph, ‘The Culture of Celebrity’, in In A Cardboard Belt! Essays Personal, Literary, and Savage (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2007)Google Scholar.

57 Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (ed.) W.B. Todd (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976), bk. 5, ch. 3.

58 Not that there is anything new about the attractions of spectacular violence. See, for example, Fagan, Garrett G., The Lure of the Arena: Social Psychology and the Crowd at the Roman Games (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011)Google Scholar. More generally, see Goldstein, Jeffrey (ed.) Why We Watch: The Attractions of Violent Entertainment (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998)Google Scholar.

59 Baudrillard's, Whence Jean complaint that The Gulf War Did Not Take Place, trans. Patton, Paul (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1995)Google Scholar.

60 As I have tried to do regarding the conflict between Israel and its neighbours in my ‘Going Rabin One Further’, in Patriotic Elaborations, op. cit. note 14.

61 See, for example, Noam Chomsky, ‘The Responsibility of Intellectuals’, New York Review of Books, 23 February 1967.

62 My thanks to Asa Kasher, Françis Douville Vigeant, and Michael Walzer for comments on previous versions of this paper.