Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-c9gpj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-13T22:03:26.787Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Assessing Inductive Logics Empirically

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Howard Smokler*
Affiliation:
University of Colorado

Extract

Philosophers of science have recently been urged by Arthur Fine to collaborate with physicists and with other scientists in constructing scientific theories.2 What I am proposing is a collaboration at the other pole of scientific activity; the pole of experiment.

I consider this effort to be part of a tendency within philosophy to naturalize epistemology. The banner of naturalistic epistemology has attracted such men as Quine and Goldman. I consider the effort as one small part of that program which involves not only theoretical integration of at least portions of the two corpuses of knowledge, but the employment of methodologies which are common to them both.

The theory of inductive logic today is in stasis. A number of highly ingenious and very sophisticated theories of inference vie for primacy. As in the case of many philosophical theses, no closure seems in sight.

Type
Part IX. Belief, Cause and Induction
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1990

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I wish to express my appreciation to Jonathan Dancy and Allan Franklin for encouragement and criticisms. None of the errors however are their responsibility.

References

Cohen, L.J. (1977), The Probable and the Provable. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L.J. (1981)“Can human irrationality be experimentally demonstrated,Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4: 317333.10.1017/S0140525X00009092CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Daston, L. (1988), Classical Probability in the Enlightenment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.10.1515/9781400844227CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwards, W. (1967), “Conservatism in a Simple Probability Inference Task,” in Decision Making, Edwards, W. and Tversky, A. (eds.). Harmondsworth: Penguin, pp. 239254.Google Scholar
Goodman, N. (1984), Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, 4th Edition. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Howson, C. and Franklin, A. (1985), “Newton and Kepler: A Bayesian Approach,Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 18: 425431.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. (1983), “Extensional vs Intuitive Reasoning, The Conjunctive Fallacy in Probability Judgement”, Psychological Review 90:293315.Google Scholar
Kyburg, H.E. Jr., (1983), Epistemology and Inference. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Levi, I. (1978), “Confirmational Conditionalization”, Journal of Philosophy 75: 730739.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levi, I. (1980)The Enterprise of Knowledge. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Levi, I. (1984), Decisions and Revisions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. (1984), Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Schum, D. and Martin, A. (1987), Unconstrained Probabilistic Belief Revision: An Analysis According to Bayes, Cohen, and Schafer, Tech. Report 9, Center for Computational Statistics and Probability, George Mason University.Google Scholar
Smokler, H. (1989), “Are Theories of Rationality Empirically Testable?Synthese, 81: 297306.Google Scholar
Stich, S. (1988), “Replective Equilibrium, Analytic Epistemology, and the Problem of Cognitive Diversity,Synthese 74, pp. 391413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stich, S. and Nisbet, R. (1980), “Justification and the Psychology of Human Reasoning”, Philosophy of Science 47: 188202.10.1086/288928CrossRefGoogle Scholar