Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-c9gpj Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-13T21:18:03.795Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Backward Induction without Common Knowledge

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Cristina Bicchieri*
Affiliation:
Carnegie-Mellon University

Extract

Game theory studies the behavior of rational players in interactive situations and its possible outcomes. For such an investigation, the notion of players’ rationality is crucial. While notions of rationality have been extensively discussed in game theory, the epistemic conditions under which a game is played — though implicitly presumed — have seldom been explicitly analyzed and formalized. These conditions involve the players’ reasoning processes and capabilities, as well as their knowledge of the game situation. Game theory treats some aspects of information about chance moves and other players’ moves by means of information partitions in extensive form games. But a player's knowledge of the structure, for example, of information partitions themselves is different from his information about chance moves and other players’ moves. The informational aspects captured by the extensive form games have nothing to do with a player's knowledge of the structure of the game.

Type
Part XI. Decision and Game Theory
Copyright
Copyright © 1989 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aumann, R. J. (1976), “Agreeing to disagree”, The Annals of Statistics 4: 12361239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bacharach, M. (1987), “A theory of rational decision in games”, Erkenntnis 27: 1755.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bacharach, M. (1985), “Some extensions of a claim of Aumann in an axiomatic model of knowledge”, Journal of Economic Theory 37: 167-55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernheim, D. (1984), “Rationalizable strategic behavior”, Econometrica 52: 10071028.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bicchieri, C. (1988), “Strategic behavior and counterfactuals”, Synthese 76: 135169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bicchieri, C. (1988a), “Common knowledge and backward induction: a solution to the paradox”, in Vardi, M. (ed.) Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning about Knowledge. Morgan Kaufmann Publishers, Los Altos.Google Scholar
Bicchieri, C. (1989), “Self-refuting theories of strategic interaction: a paradox of common knowledge”, Erkenntnis 30: 6985.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, K. (1987), “Modeling rational players I”, Economics and Philosophy 3: 179214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, K. (1988), “Modeling rational players II”, Economics and Philosophy 4: 955.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, K. and Brandenburger, A. (forthcoming), “Common knowledge and game theory”, Journal of Economic Perspectives.Google Scholar
Bonanno, G. (1987), “The logic of rational play in extensive games”, Disc. Paper no. 16, Nuffield College, Oxford.Google Scholar
Brandenburger, A. (forthcoming), “The role of common knowledge assumptions in game theory”, in Hahn, F. (ed.) The Economics of Information, Games, and Missing Markets, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Brandenburger, A. and Dekel, E. (1985a), “Common knowledge with probability”, Research Paper no. 796R, Graduate School of Business, Stanford University.Google Scholar
Brandenburger, A. and Dekel, E. (1985b), “Hierarchies of beliefs and common knowledge”, Research Paper no. 841, Graduate School of Business, Stanford University.Google Scholar
Gilboa, I. (1986), “Information and meta-information”, Working paper no. 30-86, Tel-Aviv University.Google Scholar
Gilboa, I. and Schmeidler, D. (1988), “Information dependent games”, Economics Letters 27: 215221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halpern, J. and Fagin, R. (1988), Modelling knowledge and action in distributed systems. Technical Report, IBM.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halpern, J. and Moses, Y. (1987), “Knowledge and common knowledge in a distributed environment”, IBM Research Report RJ 4421.Google Scholar
Harper, W. (1988), “Causal decision theory and game theory”, in Harper, and Skyrms, (eds.), Causation in Decision, Belief Change and Statistics, Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, J. (1967-68), “Games with incomplete information played by ‘Bayesian’ players”, Parts I, II, and III. Management Science 14: 159182, 320-332, 468-502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, J. (1975), “The tracing procedure: a Bayesian approach to defining a solution for n-person non-cooperative games”, International Journal of Game Theory 4: 6194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, J. and Selten, R. (1988), A General Theory of Equilibrium Selection in Games. The MIT Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. (1962), Knowledge and Belief. Cornell University Press, Cornell.Google Scholar
Kaneko, M. (1987), “Structural common knowledge and factual common knowledge”, RUEE Working Paper no. 87-27, Hitotsubashi University.Google Scholar
Kuhn, H.W. (1953), “Extensive games and the problem of information”, in Kuhn, H.W. and Tucker, A.W. (eds.) Contributions to the Theory of Games. Princeton University Press, Princeton.Google Scholar
Lenzen, W. (1978), “Recent work in epistemic logic”, Acta Philosophica Fennica 30: 1219.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1969), Convention. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Luce, R. and Raiffa, H. (1957), Games and Decisions. Wiley, New York.Google Scholar
Mertens, J.-F. and Zamir, S. (1985), “Formulation of Bayesian analysis for games with incomplete information”, International Journal of Game Theory 14: 129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parikh, R. and Ramanujam, R. (1985), “Distributed processes and the logic of knowledge”, Proceedings of the Workshop on Logics of Programs: 256268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pearce, D. (1984), “Rationalizable strategic behavior and the problem of perfection”, Econometrica 52: 10291050.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reny, P. (1987), “Rationality, common knowledge, and the theory of games”, Working paper, Department of Economics, University of Western Ontario.Google Scholar
Samet, D. (1987), “Ignoring ignorance and agreeing to disagree”, mimeo, Northwestern University.Google Scholar
Selten, R. (1975), “Re-examination of the perfectness concept for equilibrium points in extensive games”, International Journal of Game Theory 4: 2255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shin, H.S. (1987), “Counterfactuals, common knowledge and equilibrium”, mimeo, Nuffield College, Oxford.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. (1989), “Deliberational dynamics and the foundations of Bayesian game theory”, in Tomberlin, J. E. (ed.) Epistemology. Ridgeview, Northridge.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. (1986), “Deliberational equilibria”, Topoi 1.Google Scholar
Tan, T. and Werlang, S. (1986), “On Aumann's notion of common knowledge—an alternative approach”, Working paper no. 85-26, University of Chicago.Google Scholar
Van Damme, E.E.C. (1983), Refinements of the Nash Equilibrium Concept. Springer-Verlag, Berlin.CrossRefGoogle Scholar