Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-tsvsl Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-28T11:14:36.273Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Color Perception and Neural Encoding: Does Metameric Matching Entail a Loss of Information?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Gary Hatfield*
Affiliation:
University of Pennsylvania

Extract

It seems intuitively obvious that metameric matching of color samples entails a loss of information. Metamers are distributions of wavelength and intensity (or “spectral energy distributions“) that perceivers cannot discriminate. Consider two color samples that are presented under ordinary white light and that appear to normal observers to be of the same color. It is well-established that such color samples can have quite different surface-reflective properties; e.g., two samples that appear to be the same shade of green may in fact reflect strikingly different patterns of wavelengths within the visible spectrum (see Figure 1). In this case, sameness of appearance under similar conditions of illumination does not entail sameness of surface reflectance. Spectrophotometrically diverse materials appear the same. It would seem then that information has been lost, that the visual system has failed in its task of chromatic discrimination.

Type
Part XII. Issues in the Philosophy of Psychology
Copyright
Copyright © 1992 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Cornell Cognitive Science Symposium and to the Departments of Psychology and Philosophy of Dalhousie University, both in June, 1991.I thank each audience for their stimulating discussion. Larry Shapiro has given me helpful comments and criticisms on a more recent draft.

References

, Aristotle (1984), “Sense and Sensibilia”, in his Complete Works, 2 volumes, Barnes, J. (ed.). Princeton:Princeton University Press, 1:693-720.Google Scholar
Barlow, H.B. (1953), “Summation and Inhibition in the Frog’s Retina”, Journal of Physiology, 119: 69-88.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Barlow, H.B. (1961a), “The Coding of Sensory Messages”, in Current Problems in Animal Behavior, Thorpe, W.H. and Zangwill, O.L. (eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 331-360.Google Scholar
Barlow, H.B. (1961b), “Possible Principles Underlying the Transformations of Sensory Messages”, Sensory Communication, in Rosenblith, W.A. (ed.). New York: Wiley, pp. 217-234.Google Scholar
Barlow, H.B. (1982a), “General Principles: The Senses Considered as Physical Instruments”, The Senses, in Barlow, H.B. and Mollon, J.D. (eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1-33.Google Scholar
Barlow, H.B. (1982b), “Physiology of the Retina”, The Senses, H.B. Barlow and Mollon, J.D. (eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 102-113.Google Scholar
Barlow, H.B. (1982c), “What Causes Trichromacy? A Theoretical Analysis Using Comb-Filtered Spectra”, Vision Research 22: 635-644.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beck, J. (1972), Surface Color Perception. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Boynton, R.M. (1990), “Human Color Perception”, in Science of Vision, Leibovic, K.N. (ed.). Berlin: Springer-Verlag, pp. 211-253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchsbaum, G. and Gottschalk, A. (1983), “Trichromacy, Opponent Colours Coding and Optimum Colour Information Transmission in the Retina”, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 220: 89-113.Google ScholarPubMed
Eckert, M.P., Derrico, J.B., and Buchsbaum, G. (unpublished), “The Laplacian of Images Is a Special Case of Predictive Coding in the Retina”, paper presented at the 1989 ARVO meeting.Google Scholar
Gibson, J.J. (1950), Perception of the Visual World. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Gibson, J.J. (1966), The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Goldsmith, T.H. (1991), “Optimization, Constraint, and History in the Evolution of Eyes”, Quarterly Review of Biology 65:281-322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, S.J., and Lewontin, R.C. (1979), “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme”, Proceedings of the Royal Society B 205:581-598.Google Scholar
Hardin, C.L. (1988), Color for Philosophers: Unweaving the Rainbow. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Hatfield, G. (1988), “Representation and Content in Some (Actual) Theories of Perception”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 19:175-214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hatfield, g. (1991), “Representation in Perception and Cognition: Connectionist Affordances”, in Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, Ramsey, W., Rumelhart, D., and Stich, S. (eds.). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, pp. 163-195.Google Scholar
Hilbert, D.R. (1987), Color and Color Perception. Stanford, CA: Center for the Study of Language and Information.Google Scholar
Hurvich, L.M. (1981), Color Vision. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Jacobs, G.H. (1981), Comparative Color Vision. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Lythgoe, J.N. (1979), The Ecology of Vision. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Marr, D. (1982), Vision. San Francisco: Freeman.Google Scholar
Matthen, M. (1988), “Biological Functions and Perceptual Content”, Journal of Philosophy 85: 5-27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, J. (1978), “Optimization Theory in Evolution”, Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 9: 31-56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Millikan, R.G. (1984), Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
McFarland, W.N., and Munz, F.W. (1975), “The Evolution of Photopic Visual Pigments in Fishes”, Vision Research, 15:1071-1080.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Polyak, S. (1957), The Vertebrate Visual System. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ptolemy, C. (1989), L’optique. Edited and translated by Lejeune, A.. New York: Brill.Google Scholar
Snodderly, D.M. (1979), “Visual Discriminations Encountered in Food Foraging by a Neotropical Primate: Implications for the Evolution of Color Vision”, in Behavioral Significance of Color, Burtt, E.H. (ed.). New York: Garland Press, pp. 237-279.Google Scholar
Sterling, P. (1990), “Retina”, in The Synoptic Organization of the Brain, 3d ed, Shepherd, G.M. (ed.). New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 170-213.Google Scholar
Travis, J. (1991), “The Role of Optimizing Selection in Natural Populations”, Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 20: 279-296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodhouse, J.M., and Barlow, H.B. (1982), “Spatial and Temporal Resolution and Analysis”, in The Senses, Barlow, H.B. and Mollon, J.D. (eds.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 133-164.Google Scholar
Wright, L. (1973), “Functions”, Philosophical Review, 82,139-168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar