Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-qs9v7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-13T21:33:09.189Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Decisions, Games and Equilibrium Solutions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

William Harper*
Affiliation:
University of Western Ontario

Extract

Von Neumann and Morgenstern based their theory of games on the representation of individual preferences for outcomes by utilities generated by preferences for gambles over these outcomes. A utility function (an assignment of numbers to outcomes) represents an agent's preferences just in case the agent's preference relation between any two gambles agrees with the numerical relation between their expected utilities (where these expectations are calculated using the objective probabilities specified in the gambles). This representation constrains the utility assignments up to scale transformations (multiplying each value by the same positive number) and adjustments of the zero point (adding the same positive or negative number to each value). This fixes the ratios of differences between utilities of outcomes.

Von Neumann and Morgenstem proposed qualitative constraints on the agent's preferences among these gambles which are equivalent to the assertion that such a utility representation exists. Here is an equivalent formulation of such rationality postulates.

Type
Part XI. Decision and Game Theory
Copyright
Copyright © 1989 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allais, M. (1953), “Le comportment de l'homme rationnel devant le risque: Critique des postulates et axiomes de l'ecole americaineEconometrica 21: 503-46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allais, M. (1979), “The so-called Allais paradox and rational decisions under uncertainty” in Allais and Hagen, eds (1979), 437-681.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allais, M. and Hagen, (eds) (1979), Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox, Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aumann, R.J. (1976), “Agreeing to disagree”, Annals of Statistics 4: 12361239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barwise, J. (1988), “Three views of common knowledge” in Vardi, M. Y. (ed.), 365-374.Google Scholar
Bernheim, D. (1984), “Rationalizable strategic behaviorEconometrica 52: 10071028.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bicchieri, C. (1988), “Common knowledge and backward induction: a solution to the paradox” in Vardi, M. Y. (ed.), 381-393.Google Scholar
Bicchieri, C. (1989) this volume.Google Scholar
Binmore, K. (1986) “Modeling rational players II”, manuscript.Google Scholar
Brandonberger, A. and Dekel, E. (1985.) “Common knowledge with probability 1”, research paper 796R, Graduate School of Business, Stanford University.Google Scholar
Gârdenfors, P. and Sahlins, E. (eds) (1988), Decision, Probability and Utility: Selected Readings, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giles, R. (1979), “Non Archimedian belief”, manuscript.Google Scholar
Harsanyi, J. C. (1967-68), “Games with incomplete information played by ‘Bayesian’ players” Parts I-III, Management Science 14: 159182, 320-334, and 486-502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, J. C. (1973) “Games with randomly-disturbed payoffs: a new rationale for mixed strategy equilibrium points”, International Journal of Game Theory 2: 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, J. C. (1977), Rational Behavior and Bargaining Equilibrium in Games and Social Situations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harsanyi, J. C. and Selten, R. (1988), A General Theory of Equilibrium Selection in Games, Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kohlberg, E. and Mertens, J. F. (1986), “On the strategic stability of equilibriaEconometrica 54: 10031037.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kreps, D. and Wilson, R. (1982), “Sequential equilibria”, Econometrica 50, 863894.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kreps, D., Milgrom, P. and Wilson, R. (1982) “Rational cooperation in the finitely repeated Prisoner's Dilemma”, Journal of Economic Theory 27: 245252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D.K. (1969), Convention, A Philosophical Study, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Luce, R.D. and Raiffa, H. (1957), Games and Decisions, New York: John Wiley and Sons, Inc.Google Scholar
McClennen, E.F. (1978), “The Minimax theory and expected utility reasoning”, in Hooker et al. (eds) (1978) Vol. Ii: 337359.Google Scholar
McClennen, E.F. (1983), “Sure-thing doubts”, in Stigum, B. and Wenstop, F. (eds), 117136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McClennen, E.F. (1986), “Prisoners dilemma and resolute choice”, in Campbell, R. and Sowden, L. (eds), 94104.Google Scholar
McClennen, E.F. (1988), “Ordering and independence”, Economics and Philosophy 4, 298308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pearce, D. (1984), “Rationalizable strategic behaviour and the problem of perfection”, Econometrica 52: 10281050.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K.R. (1959), The Logic of Scientific Discovery New York: Harper Torchbook edition.Google Scholar
Reny, P. (1988), “Backward induction and common knowledge in games with perfect information”, manuscript.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Renyi, A. (1955), “On a new axiomatic theory of probability”, Acta Mathematica 6: 285335.Google Scholar
Renyi, A. (1970), Foundations of Probability, San Francisco: Holden-Day Inc.Google Scholar
Savage, L.J. (1954), The Foundations of Statistics, New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.Google Scholar
Selten, R. (1965), “Spieltheoretische Behandlungeines Otigopolmodells mit Nachfragetragheit”, Zeitschrift fur die Gesamte Straatiswissenschaft 121: 301324.Google Scholar
Selten, R. (1975), “Re-examination of the perfectness concept for equilibrium points in extensive games”, International Journal of Game Theory 4: 2555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, B. (1982), “Causal decision theory”, The Journal of Philosophy 79: 695711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, B. (1984), Pragmatics and Empiricism, New Haven: Yale Press.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. (1989), The Dynamics of Rational Deliberation, forthcoming, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Tan, T. and Werlang, S. (1988), “On Aumann's notion of common knowledge — an alternative approach”, CARESS working paper #88-09, University of Pennsylvania.Google Scholar
Tan, T. and Werlang, S. R. D. C. (1988), “A guide to knowledge and games”, in Vardi, M.Y. (ed.), 163-177.Google Scholar
Vardi, M. Y. (ed.) (1988), Proceedings of the Second Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning about Knowledge, Los Altos, California: Morgan Kaufmann Publishers.Google Scholar
van Damme, E. (1983), Refinements of the Nash Equilibrium Concept, lecture notes in Mathematical Economics and Social Systems, No. 219, Berlin: Springer-Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Neumann, J. and Morgenstern, O. (1944), Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar