Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-7drxs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-18T16:15:29.074Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Microeconomic Interpretation of Games

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Chantale LaCasse
Affiliation:
University of Ottawa
Don Ross
Affiliation:
University of Ottawa

Extract

It is clear that many philosophers of science are inclined to be sceptical about the scientific ambitions of economics. Sometimes this scepticism amounts to a forthright denial of economists’ entitlement to be granted the epistemic authority normally claimed by scientists (for example, Dupré 1993). A more modest ambivalence may be signalled by a philosopher's refusal to treat the intuitions of economists as data for the philosophy of science, in the way that (e.g.) physicists’ ontological and epistemological judgements are now routinely treated. The following paper is part of a much larger project that criticizes the basis for this scepticism, at least where microeconomics is concerned. This general project is partly motivated by our belief that philosophers have often viewed microeconomics from a highly distorting set of perspectives. One source of these distortions is a sociological accident: the philosophy of economics, as a part of the philosophy of science, has been largely owned since its outset by Popperians and their intellectual descendants.

Type
Part X. Games, Explanations, Authority, and Justification
Copyright
Copyright © 1994 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

Thanks to Paul Dumouchel, Maurice Lagueux, Paisley Livingstone, Robert Nadeau, and the other members of the Groupe de Recherche en Epistémologie Comparée at l'Université du Québec à Montréal, for their helpful criticism.

References

Binmore, K. (1992), Fun and Games. Lexington: D.C. Heath.Google Scholar
Blaug, M. (1980), The Methodology of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Caldwell, B. (1982), Beyond Positivism: Economic Methodology in the Twentieth Century. London: Unwin.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1983), How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, D. (1991), “Real Patterns”, The Journal of Philosophy 88:2751.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dupré, J. (1993), The Disorder of Things. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Hausman, D. (1992), The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hollis, M. and Sugden, R. (1993), “Rationality in Action”, Mind 102:135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Luce, R., and Raiffa, H. (1957), Games and Decisions. New York: Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
Neumann, J. von, and Morgenstern, O. (1947), Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Redman, D. (1991), Economics and the Philosophy of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1992), Economics: Mathematical Politics or Science of Diminishing Returns? Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ross, D. (forthcoming), “Dennett's Conceptual Reform”, Behavior and Philosophy 21.Google Scholar
Ross, D., and LaCasse, C. (1993), Toward a New Philosophy of Positive Economics: Working Paper #9324, Groupe de Recherche en Épistémologie Comparée, Université du Québec à Montréal.Google Scholar
Savage, L. (1954), The Foundations of Statistics. New York: Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar