Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-gq7q9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-21T12:15:02.223Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Neo-Skinnerian Psychology: A Non-Radical Behaviorism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Terry L. Smith*
Affiliation:
University of the District of Columbia

Extract

Radical Behaviorism makes the implausible claim that “the appeal to mind explains nothing at all” (Skinner 1971, p. 186). Clearly, such a claim (if accepted) would lend strong support to the Skinnerian research program, if only because it would eliminate the major competition. But what support remains when such a claim is not accepted? This paper shall argue that the Skinnerian research program need not depend upon the supposition that there is something scientifically illicit or vacuous about the explanations offered by mentalistic psychology. Distinguishing Radical Behaviorism from a position that grows out of Skinner’s writings from 1938 through 1950, it asserts that the latter position provides a conception of the behavior analytic program that is compatible with the basic claims of cognitive and folk psychology.

We may give a rough definition of this position by following Cummins (1983) in distinguishing between two types of scientific theory.

Type
Part V. Perception and Psychology
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, R. (1983). The Nature of Psychological Explanation. Cambridge: M.I.T Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. (1979). Brainstorms. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
Ferster, C.B. and Skinner, B.F. (1957). Schedules of Reinforcement. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lea, S.E.G. (1981). “Correlation and Contiguity in Foraging Theory.” In Advances in Analysis of Behavior (Volume 2: Predictability, Correlation, and Contiguity). Edited by Harzem, P. & Zeiler, M.D. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Mackintosh, N.J. (1974). The Psychology of Animal Learning. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Rachlin, H. (1976). Introduction to Modern Behaviorism. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman.Google Scholar
Schwartz, B. and Lacey, H. (1982). Behaviorism, Science, and Human Nature. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
Skinner, B.F. (1938). The Behavior of Organisms. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.Google Scholar
Skinner, B.F. (1950). “Are Theories of Learning Necessary?Psychological Review 57: 193216.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Skinner, B.F. (1953). Science and Human Behavior. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Skinner, B.F. (1971). Beyond Freedom and Dignity. New York: Bantam Books.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1984). The Nature of Selection. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
Staddon, J.E.R. (1983). Adaptive Behavior and Learning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Staddon, J.E.R. and Simmelhag, V.L. (1971). “The ‘Superstition’ Experiment: A Reexamination of Its Implications for the Principles of Adaptive Behavior.Psychological Review 78: 343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar