Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-n9wrp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-20T06:24:29.142Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Truth, Epistemio Ideals and the Psychology of Categorization

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Robert N. McCauley*
Affiliation:
Emory University

Extract

Many philosophers, and particularly those of a Kantian stripe, have suspected that claims about the ways the world and its Joints are (in contrast to claims about the joints in our models of the world and the way they are) make little sense. Recently, similar views have gained prominence in the philosophy of science and in cognitive psychology. The demise of the strong distinction between theoretical and observational terms over the past two decades is just one, among many, developments in the philosophy of science which is of a piece with such suspicions. Meanwhile, a great deal of recent theoretical work on the psychology of categorization also affirms the fundamentality of our cognitive constructs in structuring human experience.

Type
Part III. Psychology
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I wish to express my gratitude to Larry Barsalou, William Bechtel, John Heil, George Lakoff, Douglas Medin, Olric Neisser, and Robert Richardson for their helpful comments. Positions advanced in this paper are closely related to those in the last section of McCauley (1985).

References

Barsalou, L. (1982). “Context-Independent and Context-dependent Information in Concepts.” Memory and Cognition 10: 8293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. (1984). Matter and Consciousness. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. (1974). “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual- Scheme.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association XLVII: 5-20. (As reprinted in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984. Pages 183198.)Google Scholar
Dougherty, J. (1978). “Salience and Relativity in Classification.” American Ethnologist 5: 6680.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, S. (1983). “What, If Anything, Is a Zebra?” In Hens’ Teeth and Horses’ Toes. New York: Norton. Pages 355-365.Google Scholar
Heil, J. (1983). Cognition and Perception. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lakoff, G. (forthcoming). Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Tell Us About the Nature of Thought. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCauley, R. (1985). Concepts. Theoriesr and Truth. Emory Cognition Project Report #8.Google Scholar
McCauley, R. (in press). “The Role of Theories in a Theory of Concepts.” In Neisser (in press).Google Scholar
Mervis, C. and Rosch, E. (1981). “Categorization of Natural Objects.” Annual Review of Psychology 32: 89115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, G. and Medin, D. (1985). “The Role of Theories in Conceptual Coherence.” Psychological Review 92: 289316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neisser, U. (1985). From direct perception to conceptual structure. Emory Cognition Project Report #7.Google Scholar
Neisser, U. (ed.). (in press). Concepts Reconsidered: The Ecological and Intellectual Bases of Categorization. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1972). Objective Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, Truth and History. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1983). Realism and Reason. (Philosophical Papers. Volume 3.) New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Z. (1980). “Computation and Cognition: Issues in the Foundations of Cognitive Science.” The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3; 111-132.Google Scholar
Quine, W.V.O (1951). “Two Dogmas of Empiricism.” The Philosophical Review 60: 2043. (As reprinted in From a Logical Point of Vie w. New York: Harper 4 Row, 1963. Pages 20-46.)Google Scholar
Rosch, E.; Mervis, C.; Gray, W.; Johnson, D. and Boyes-Braem, P. (1976). “Basic Objects in Natural Categories.” Cognitive Psychology 8: 382439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar