Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-k7p5g Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-09T15:41:37.766Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Causal Modeling and the Statistical Analysis of Causation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Gurol Irzik*
Affiliation:
University of Southern Indiana

Extract

Recent studies on probabilistic causation and statistical explanation (Cartwright 1979; Salmon 1984), I believe, have opened up the possibility of a genuine unification between philosophical approaches and causal modeling (CM) in the social, behavioral and biological sciences (Wright 1934; Blalock 1964; Asher 1976). This unification rests on the statistical tools employed, the principle of common cause, the irreducibility of causation to probability or statistics, and the idea of causal process as a suitable framework for understanding causal relationships. The aim of this paper is to draw attention to these four areas of contact by focusing on the relevant aspects of CM.

Causal analysis in the social sciences is based on two fundamental notions: model and method. A causal model is an idealized picture of the causal relationships in the world. Method, on the other hand, refers to certain statistical techniques that are used to evaluate and test a causal model using data which consist of joint observations on the model variables.

Type
Part I. Physics
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1986

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Asher, H. (1976). Causal Modeling. Beverly Hills: Sage Publications.Google Scholar
Blalock, H.M. (1964). Causal Inferences in Nonexperimental Research. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Blalock, H.M. (1969). Theory Construction. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Blau, P.M. and Duncan, O.D (1967). The American Occupational Structure. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1979). “Causal Laws and Effective Strategies.Nous 13: 419437. (As reprinted in Cartwright, N. How The Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983. Pages 21-43.)Google Scholar
Duncan, O.D. (1975). Introduction to Structural Equation Models. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Ellett, F. and Ericson, D. (1983). “The Logic of Causal Methods in Social Science.” Synthese 57: 6782.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hanushek, E. and Jackson, J. (1977). Statistical Methods for Social Scientists. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Irzik, G. and Meyer, E (forthcoming). “Causal Modeling: New Directions for Statistical Explanation.” Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. (1956). The Direction of Time. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. (1971). Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Simon, H. (1979). “The Meaning of Causal Ordering.” In Qualitative and Quantitative Social Research. Edited by Merton, R.K. Coleman, J.J. and Rossi, P. . New York:Free Press. Pages 6581.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B.C. (1982). “The Charybdis of Realism: The Epistemological Implications of Bell’s Inequality.” Synthese 52: 2538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, S. (1934). “The Method of Path Coefficients.” Annals of Mathematical Statistics 5: 161215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar