Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-5lx2p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-26T16:27:11.144Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Law and moral agency in De libero arbitrio I

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 February 2017

IVAN WELTY*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Willamette University, Salem, Oregon, 97301, USA

Abstract

Augustine's account of postlapsarian human moral agency in Book I of De libero arbitrio is analysed more fully than heretofore. Consideration is given to Augustine's Stoic antecedents and, following a suggestion by R. J. O'Connell, a comparison with Kant's moral philosophy is developed. The result is a more nuanced understanding of Augustine's account of moral agency in the early period. Whether that account persists into Augustine's later work is left an open question.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Augustine, Saint (1991a) Confessions, Chadwick, H. (tr.) (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Augustine, Saint (1991b) The Trinity (De Trinitate), Rotelle, J. E. (ed.) & Hill, E. (tr.) (Hyde Park NY: New City Press).Google Scholar
Augustine, Saint (1992) Sermons III/5 (148–183) on the New Testament, Rotelle, J. E. (ed.) & Hill, E. (tr.) (New Rochelle NY: New City Press).Google Scholar
Augustine, Saint (1999) Unfinished Work in Answer to Julian, Rotelle, J. E. (ed.) & Teske, R. J. (tr.) (Hyde Park NY: New City Press).Google Scholar
Augustine, Saint (2010) On the Free Choice of the Will, On Grace and Free Choice, and Other Writings, King, P. (tr.) (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Byers, S. C. (2012) Perception, Sensibility, and Moral Motivation in Augustine: A Stoic-Platonic Synthesis (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Byrd, B. S. (2015) ‘The elusive story of Kant's permissive laws’, in Denis, L. (ed.) Kant's Lectures on Ethics: A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 156169.Google Scholar
Chroust, A.-H. (1944) ‘The philosophy of law of St. Augustine’, The Philosophical Review, 53, 195202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cicero, (1928) On the Republic. On the Laws, Keyes, C. (tr.) (Cambridge MA: The Loeb Classical Library of Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Cicero, (1991) Cicero on Stoic Good and Evil, Wright, M. R. (tr.) (Warminster: Aris & Phillips Ltd.).Google Scholar
Colish, M. (1985) The Stoic Tradition, 2 vols (Leiden: E. J. Brill).Google Scholar
Davenport, J. (2002) ‘Liberty of the higher-order will: Frankfurt and Augustine’, Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers, 19, 437461.Google Scholar
Dihle, A. (1982) The Theory of Will in Classical Antiquity (Berkeley CA: University of California Press).Google Scholar
Dillon, J. & Gerson, L. P. (trs) (2004) Neoplatonic Philosophy: Introductory Readings (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company).Google Scholar
Epictetus, (1979) The Discourses as Reported by Arrian, The Manual, and Fragments, I, Oldfather, W. A. (tr.) (Cambridge MA: The Loeb Classical Library of Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
Epictetus, (1985) The Discourses as Reported by Arrian, The Manual, and Fragments, II (Cambridge MA: The Loeb Classical Library of Harvard University Press, 1985).Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. (1971) ‘Free will and the concept of a person’, The Journal of Philosophy, 68, 520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, M. (2002) ‘John of Damascus on human action, the will, and human freedom’, in Lerodiankonou, K. (ed.) Byzantine Philosophy and its Ancient Sources (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), 6395.Google Scholar
Frede, M. (2011) A Free Will: Origins of the Notion in Ancient Thought (Berkeley: University of California Press).Google Scholar
Gilbert, N. W. (1963) ‘The concept of the will in early Latin philosophy’, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 1, 1735.Google Scholar
Green, W. M. & Daur, K.-D. (eds) (1970) Sancti Aurelii Augustini: Contra academicos. De beata vita. De ordine. De magistro. De libero arbitrio (Corpus Christianorum Series Latina, Volume XXIX) (Turnhout: Typographi Brepols).Google Scholar
Hogan, D. (2009) ‘Noumenal affection’, The Philosophical Review, 118, 501532.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (2002a) Critique of Practical Reason, Pluhar, W. (tr.) (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing).Google Scholar
Kant, I. (2002b) Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, Wood, A. (tr.) (New Haven: Yale University Press).Google Scholar
Kirwan, C. (1989) Augustine (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
Mann, W. E. (1999) ‘Inner-life ethics’, in Matthews, G. B. (ed.) The Augustinian Tradition (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999), 140165.Google Scholar
O'Connell, R. J. (1970) ‘ De libero arbitrio I: Stoicism Revisited’, Augustinian Studies, 1, 4968.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Daly, G. (1987) Augustine's Philosophy of Mind (Berkeley: University of California Press).Google Scholar
Stang, N. (2013) ‘Freedom, knowledge and affection: reply to Hogan’, Kantian Review, 18, 99106.Google Scholar
Thompson, S. E. (2012) ‘What goodness is: order as imitation of unity in Augustine’, Review of Metaphysics, 65, 525553.Google Scholar
Wetzel, J. (1992) Augustine and the Limits of Virtue (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar