Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-cx56b Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-26T21:54:36.736Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Commentary - Timothy W. Burns: Leo Strauss on Democracy, Technology, and Liberal Education. (New York: State University of New York Press, 2021. Pp. 201.)

Review products

Timothy W. Burns: Leo Strauss on Democracy, Technology, and Liberal Education. (New York: State University of New York Press, 2021. Pp. 201.)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 January 2023

Rodrigo Chacón*
Affiliation:
Instituto Tecnológico Autónomo de México Tizapán, Mexico
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
A Symposium on Timothy W. Burns's Leo Strauss on Democracy, Technology, and Liberal Education
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of University of Notre Dame

Burns has written an excellent book on the contemporary importance of Strauss. Speaking as someone who has read Strauss through different lenses, I found it both provocative and deeply instructive. To begin with the latter aspects, Burns writes both as an expert in full command of his sources and as a concerned citizen. He seeks to show (as far as I understand him) that liberal democracy and modernity are more dangerous than is commonly acknowledged. American democracy, in particular, is not immune to the kind of moral critique that contributed to the demise of the Weimar Republic and the rise of fascism (84). Nor can one simply ignore those who despised modern civilization in the 1930s as blind fanatics. For at the root of the nihilistic hatred of all things “bourgeois” lies a love of morality that seems to be essential to the preservation of humanity (8). That is, the longing for a total revolution that characterized politics in the 1930s continues to resonate. And we cannot simply respond by invoking “the modern doctrine of inalienable rights” or a rationalism that claims to perceive “what is just by nature” (87–88). Neither Locke nor Aristotle is of much help in addressing the challenges posed by democracy, technology, and liberal education today. A broader vision is needed—one that draws on the most radical critics of modern civilization, especially on Heidegger, and on the wisdom and example of statesmen such as Winston Churchill. Above all, perhaps, the possibility of civilization and human nobility today seems to depend on a disposition that embodies the “fruitful tension between religious and liberal education” (66).

Drawing on most available sources, including seminars and unpublished lectures, this book probes the depths of Strauss's engagement with Heidegger in an admirably concise and comprehensive manner. Heidegger's “existentialism” grasps “the fact that reason has become radically problematic,” in sharp contrast to positivism—“the last” and most dogmatic expression of “modern rationalism.” Existentialism transcends modern rationalism by stressing the “fundamental dependence of reason on language,” and reason's dependence, more generally, on “powers which [we] cannot comprehend.”Footnote 2 By alluding to such powers, existentialism represents an “elevation of the religious disposition” (118), which Strauss regarded as a pillar of civilization. Heidegger's thought also coincided with Strauss's in its diagnosis of modern rationalism as essentially technological—bent on conquering nature and on a blind augmentation of human power. Indeed, Strauss takes this diagnosis much further by suggesting that moral modernity's defense of individual dignity is itself part of “the technological project of enlightenment” (cf. 66, 10). Finally, our unplanned encounter with mortality, which Heidegger saw as the key to a morally serious life, was also fundamental for Strauss, even though, of course, his conception of moral seriousness was radically different from Heidegger's. Whereas Heidegger elevated Dasein to the status of “the mysterious ground of ‘History,’”Footnote 3 which is capable of revolutionizing moral-political life (as Heidegger attempted with disastrous results), Strauss found in our awareness of mortality a source of liberation from the delusion that we can change the world (96). Our awareness of mortality may further inspire in us “a yearning for the noble, for a dignified life” (100).

Burns's approach provides important clues as to why Strauss could think along with Heidegger for such long stretches, while arriving at largely opposite conclusions. Heideggerian existentialism grew out of the religious impulses evident in thinkers from Pascal to Feuerbach to Kierkegaard. Their awareness of incomprehensible powers, such as the “intelligence of the heart” and the “call of conscience,” which addresses us in our mysterious singularity, brought them close to the “classical” rationalism that recognized the central role of elusive chance in shaping our destinies. In that respect, Heidegger's path leads back to Strauss's “classics.” Yet, rather than retrieving “classical” rationalism, Heidegger ultimately opted for its modern, “idealistic” counterpart, thus partaking in the “anti-theological ire” that has narrowed our horizons since the time of Machiavelli (7). The reason behind this (perhaps unconscious?) choice leads to the core divergence between Heidegger and Strauss, namely, Heidegger's neglect—and indeed ignorance—of political philosophy as well as his renunciation of theology. Thus, Strauss's call for a “fruitful tension between religious and liberal education” (66) can be read as precisely an antidote to Heideggerian thought.

So far, so insightful. Yet I wonder whether the high-altitude genealogies of “modern rationalism” Burns relies on can truly shed light on the problems of democracy and liberal education today. In his account, modern science—political and physical—is “constructivist” and “technological” at core (66–67, 97). This includes foundational tenets of our moral and legal self-understanding, such as human rights and dignity: they, too, seem to be part of “the technological project of enlightenment” (66).

Now, one may well be convinced that Strauss's history of (scientific, political, moral) modernity gets to the core of what “actually happened.” Still, it is obviously not the whole story. The rise of “dignity” and the concomitant abolition of institutions such as torture was perhaps, first and foremost, the result of social practices of recognition, notably within republics where citizens were considered inviolable since the late Middle Ages.Footnote 4 “Dignity” also draws its force from secularized Protestant doctrines. Strauss was certainly aware of this, but chose to follow a single path in the complex genealogy that leads to moral modernity.

Let us concede that that path leads to “the fundamental problems,” such as what counts as a right and whether social rights presuppose modern technology with all its dehumanizing potential (64). Still, it is not clear what a “civilized” response to this situation would be. One may try to deactivate such rights as the “equal . . . protection against the risk of dying prematurely” (64) for all kinds of good and bad reasons, but whether those rights exist or not, I would argue, is ultimately up to us as citizens. More precisely, natural right doctrines—and their critique—have certainly been fundamental as pillars of our collective moral lives, but their concrete meaning and institutional form depend on social and political struggles, not on great thinkers debating across the ages. Crudely put, if it were up to Locke, (poor) children would still be forced to work beginning at age three. And if Americans had simply followed the Founding Fathers they would not live in a society that guarantees equal protection by the law irrespective of race or gender. These institutions and protections were invented by ordinary men and women (abolitionists, suffragists, etc.), rather than by political philosophers.

Political philosophy, as Burns seems to understand it, is radically insufficient if what we want—as educators and citizens—is to understand “things as they are” (23). The modern “constructivist” alternative, from Kant through Hegel to Marx, cannot simply be brushed aside. In Burns's account this alternative appears to be morally irrelevant and/or “ideology” (175, 182). Thus, if I understand him correctly, there is virtually nothing to be learned morally and politically from engaging with the “moderns,” say from Baruch Spinoza to Hannah Arendt to Simone de Beauvoir. We should focus instead on the exemplary lives of (for instance) Cyrus the Great and Churchill, much as earlier generations were educated reading Plutarch and Cicero. Thus conceived, a liberal education would instill an appreciation of honorable ambition as well as a sense of duty and sacrifice for the public good.Footnote 5 Further, we should shelter the heart (notably of the young) with religious traditions and a “classical” attunement to the ultimate futility of attempts to change the world.

Based on my (limited) exposure to such an education, I share some of its aspirations. Yet I fear that living only in that world must ultimately lead to a sectarian alienation from our lifeworld. Then again, I may be misreading Burns's intentions in a book that must count among the finest attempts to respond to our contemporary crises through a close reading of Strauss's work.

References

2 Strauss, Leo, Liberalism Ancient and Modern (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995), 26, 27Google Scholar.

3 Strauss, Leo, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 176Google Scholar.

4 Bernstein, Jay M., Torture and Dignity: An Essay on Moral Injury (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2015), 259CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

5 Whether the “glory” of (Churchillian) empire is compatible with the ideals of humanity, the public good, and civilization, which Strauss defended, remains of course a question that would have to be addressed.