Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-68ccn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-13T15:09:00.090Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Community and Morality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2009

Extract

Communitarian thinkers have counterposed their views to those of liberalism as providing a more adequate basis for a political morality—a morality that deals with issues relevant to a political unit, such as liberty, equality, and fairness. Communitarians face the difficulty that the common understandings they rely on to back up a political morality are not easy to find in the form they need. This is because social units fracture along various lines, giving rise to diverse and often conflicting discourses. Where, despite such fractures, common understandings emerge as a result of either desperation or the manufacture of consent, they do not seem appropriate as a basis for a valid political morality. To avoid the weaknesses of communitarianism, it is not necessary to abandon the importance of social context for political morality. Instead, one can make use of a social theory that stresses social divisions in order to lay the base for political morality. A political morality appropriate to a group can be developed on the basis of the interests associated with such divisions.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. For a summary of a wide variety of communitarian writing in the 1980s, see Fowler, Robert Booth, The Dance with Community: The Contemporary Debate in American Thought (Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas, 1991), Part II.Google Scholar

2. Alasdair Maclntyre sees there is no homogeneity in modem states, putting his hope instead in “the construction of local forms of community” (After Virtue (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), p. 263).Google Scholar

3. See e.g., Jameson, Fredric, “Marxism and Postmodernism,” New Left Review 176 (1989): 3145.Google Scholar

4. Fisk, Milton, “Rights in Social Context,” Journal of Social Philosophy 23 (1992): 6574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5. Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 15.Google Scholar

6. Sandel, Michael J., Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1982), pp. 96103.Google Scholar

7. Maclntyre, Alasdair, Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990)Google Scholar, chap. 3.

8. Walzer, Michael, Spheres of Justice (New York: Basic Books, 1983), pp. 2829.Google Scholar

9. Foucault, Michel, The Archaeology of Knowledge (New York: Pantheon Books, 1972), pp. 3638, 6668.Google Scholar

10. Kimball, Roger, Tenured Radicals: How Politics Has Corrupted Our Higher Education (New York: Harper & Row, 1990), p. 206.Google Scholar

11. Kramnick, Isaac, Republicanism and Bourgeois Radicalism: Political Ideology in Late Eighteenth-Century England and America (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990).Google Scholar

12. Shapiro, Ian, “J. G. A. Pocock's Republicanism and Political Theory,” Critical Review 4 (1990): 431–71, esp. 449–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

13. Dworkin, Ronald, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), pp. 271–74.Google Scholar

14. Altaian, Andrew, “Legal Realism, Critical Legal Studies, and Dworkin,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 15 (1986): 205236.Google Scholar

15. Walzer, , Spheres of Justice, p. 82.Google Scholar

16. Ibid., p. 314. The inspiration for my critique here was Norman G. Finkelstein's unpublished “Tribal Rumblings: Michael Walzer's Spheres of Justice.”

17. Dewey, John, The Public and its Problems, 2nd ed. (New York: Henry Holt, 1946)Google Scholar, chap. 4. See the discussion of this issue in Westerbrook, Robert B., John Dewey and American Democracy (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991)Google Scholar, chap. 9.

18. See the discussion of the matter in Ethnic Groups and the State, ed. Brass, Paul R. (London: Croom Helm, 1985).Google Scholar

19. Althusser, Louis, “Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses,” in his Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays (London: New Left Books, 1971), pp. 162–66.Google Scholar

20. Cohen, Joshua and Rogers, Joel, On Democracy (New York: Penguin, 1983), chap. 3.Google Scholar

21. Michael J. Sandel puts the shift toward the procedural community in the context of U.S. social history (The Procedural Republic and the Unencumbered Self,” Political Theory 12 (1984): 8196).CrossRefGoogle Scholar In unpublished work read at Indiana University in March 1993, he attempts to refine communitarian theory by allowing for a plurality of possibly conflicting moral positions within an encompassing position shared within such a pluralist community.

22. Mouffe, Chantal, “Rawls: Political Philosophy Without Politics,” in Universalism vs. Communitarianism: Contemporary Debates in Ethics, ed. Rasmussen, D. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1989), pp. 217–35.Google Scholar

23. Rawls, John, “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus,” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 7 (1987): 125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

24. Gompers said in 1890 that the AFL cannot give into the hands of “men with the best intentions outside the ranks of labor” the direction of the affairs “which rightfully belong to and must be exercised by the wage workers.” Quoted from Foner, Philip S., History of the Labor Movement in the United States, vol. 2 (New York: International Publishers, 1955), p. 175.Google Scholar

25. Rawls thought he could avoid this problem by adopting the view that once people get a taste of the great advantages of the procedural community they will be willing to modify those among their purposes that would make it impossible to work in a democratic framework with others holding conflicting purposes. (John Rawls, “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus,” Sections 6–8.) My suggestion is that people will give democracy a chance only after substantive goods have been selected to make up the common purpose of the various groups. These goods will be novel goods adopted through compromise among the parties initially holding conflicting purposes. This places substantive goods alongside the procedural goods, defeating the liberal intent of the procedural community.

26. Robert N. Van Wyk, “Political Theory and the Free Exercise of Religion.” (Delivered at the 1991 Convention of the North American Society for Social Philosophy, Colorado Springs, CO.)

27. Fisk, Milton, The State and Justice (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989), chap. 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

28. Marx, Karl, “On the Jewish Question,” in The Marx-Engels Reader, 2nd ed., ed. Tucker, R. C. (New York: Norton, 1978), p. 34.Google Scholar I have been aided in my interpretation of Marx's view of political community by Isaac's, Jeffrey C.The Lion's Skin of Politics: Marx on Republicanism,” Polity 22 (1990): 460–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29. Simon, Thomas W., “The Theoretical Marginalization of the Disadvantaged: A Liberal / Communitarian Failing,” in The Liberalism-Communitarianism Debate, ed. Delaney, C. F. (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, forthcoming).Google Scholar

30. These are not then the “real interests” formed in conditions of “perfect knowledge and freedom” about which we should surely be skeptical; see Geuss, Raymond, The Idea of a Critical Theory (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981), pp. 25, 54.Google Scholar

31. Laclau, Ernesto and Mouffe, Chantal, Hegemony and Socialist Strategy (London: Verso, 1985), p. 169.Google Scholar

32. Much has been made, for example, of the differences between workers in the “monopoly” sector as opposed to those in the “competitive” sector; see e.g. Habermas, Jürgen, Legitimation Crisis, trans. Mccarthy, T. (Boston: Beacon, 1975), p. 38.Google Scholar

33. Such views are represented by, respectively, Friedman, Milton, Capitalism and Freedom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981), pp. 1415Google Scholar; and Macpherson, C. B., Democratic Theory (New York: Oxford University Press, 1973), pp. 143–56.Google Scholar

34. Wolgast, Elizabeth, Equality and the Rights of Women (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1980), pp. 1834.Google Scholar A counterpoint is provided by Jaggar, Alison, Feminist Politics and Human Nature (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld, 1983)Google Scholar, chap. 6.

35. This method has analogies with that of critical theory, but it differs from critical theory in that by seeking an ideal freedom for individuals critical theory is not content with a political morality based on groups. See e.g., Geuss, Raymond, The Idea of a Critical Theory, p p. 5859.Google Scholar

36. An attempt is made to work out the problem of a morality for overlapping social positions in Fisk, Milton, Ethics and Society (New York: New York University Press, 1980), pp. 4853.Google Scholar

37. Selections from the Prison Notebooks of Antonio Gramsci, ed. and trans. Hoare, Q. and Smith, G. Nowell (New York: International Publishers, 1971), pp. 181–82.Google Scholar

38. Lovibond, Sabina, “Feminism and Postmodernism,” New Left Review 178 (1989): 528.Google Scholar