Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-8zxtt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-12T19:32:15.477Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Modernization of Contemporary Chinese Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 August 2009

Extract

With the collapse of the Soviet Union, the People's Republic of China remains the world's only major communist society. Will China's regime go the way of its Soviet counterpart, or might it survive well into the next century and beyond? I do not undertake to answer this question directly. But my analysis of one sector of contemporary Chinese society—the legal system—suggests that the Communist party is losing its tight control over several major areas of Chinese society. In the long-run the party will be progressively weakened by current trends toward legal modernization. These trends encourage more liberal (because noninstrumentalized) forms of political, and not only legal, organization.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © University of Notre Dame 1993

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Weber, Max, The City (New York: Free Press, 1958)Google Scholar; and General Economic History (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books, 1981).Google Scholar

2. Weber, Max, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1976 [1920]), p. 26.Google Scholar On the other hand I completely reject Weber's contention that traditional Chinese society was just as highly developed in terms of differentiation as modern societies (Weber, , The Religion of China, Confucianism and Taoism [New York: Free Press, 1964 (1920)], pp. 142-50).Google Scholar Elsewhere I show that modern societies (in comparison to traditional China) are characterized by a much higher degree of differentiation, and by the significant degree to which the differentiated institutions and roles interpenetrate each other (Benjamin Gregg, “Legal Neo-Traditionalism in Communist China,” [unpublished manuscript]).

3. Gregg, “Legal Neo-Traditionalism in Communist China.” One source for imperial Chinese law is the Da Qing Lu Li (published under the alternate translation: Ta Tsing Leu Lee, trans. Staunton, George [London: Strahan and Preston 1810])Google Scholar, a body of edicts, ordinances and rules governing the activities of officials and indirectly regulating relations between citizens. It was first promulgated in 1728, amended every ten years, and finally nullified by the fall of the Qing Dynasty in 1911. Many of the amendments were in the form of sub-statutes, legislated in response to actual cases, representing further refinements and finer distinctions to statutes. Such refinements made possible an initial evaluation of a case (according to preestablished criteria), as well as an evaluation of consequences that could be expected. Hence the disposition of earlier cases provided “precedents” which could be used to guide disposition of later, related cases. Further, the code contains rules of interpretation (e.g., sec. 21, on the procedure to be followed when a person under sentence commits a second offense, or sec. 25, on remission of penalty for voluntary surrender), including a clause providing for the use of analogy to determine appropriate punishment for crimes not mentioned in the code. Hence Jones's assertion is overstated that no contemporaneous tradition existed of analyzing the Qing code or legal relations in general (Jones, William C., “Studying the Ch'ing Code—The Ta Ch'ing Lü Li,” American Journal of Comparative Law 22 [1974]).CrossRefGoogle Scholar Staunton's translation of the Da Qing Lu Li (which I cite) does not include any of the sub-statutes, which may be found in Chinese in Tu-Li Tsun-I [“Reservations on Reading the Li”], ed. Huang, Tsing-chia (Taipei: Hsueh, 1970)Google Scholar, and in French translation in Manuel du Code Chinois, trans. Boulais, Guy (Paris, 1924).Google Scholar

4. Münch, Richard, “Differentiation, Rationalization, Interpenetration: The Emergence of Modem Society,” in Differentiation Theory and Social Change, Comparative and Historical Perspectives, ed. Alexander, Jeffrey C. and Colomy, Paul (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990), p. 226.Google Scholar

5. Clarke, Donald, “What's Law Got to Do with It? Legal Institutions and Economic Reform in China,” UCLA Pacific Basin Law Journal 10 (1991): 16.Google Scholar

7. Turner, Jonathan, “A Cybernetic Model of Legal Development,” Western Sociological Review 5 (1974): 13.Google Scholar

8. Ibid., p. 12.

9. Turner, Jonathan, “Emile Durkheim's Theory of Integration in Differentiated Social Systems,” Pacific Socwlogical Review 24 (1981).Google Scholar

10. Marshall, T. H., Class, Citizenship, and Social Development (Garden City, NY: Doubleday, 1964).Google Scholar

11. Weber, Max, Economy and Society, 3 vols. (New York: Bedminster Press, 1968), 1: 311–38.Google Scholar

12. Parsons, Talcott and Smelser, Neil, Economy and Society (New York: Free Press, 1956).Google Scholar

13. Turner, , “Cybernetic Model of Legal Development,” p. 12.Google Scholar

14. Spencer, Herbert, Principles of Sociology, vol. 1 (New York: Appleton, 1876)Google Scholar; Pareto, Vilfredo, The Rise and Fall of the Elites (Towota, NJ: Bedminster, 1968) [1901]Google Scholar; Treatise on General Sociology (New York: Harcourt and Brace, 1935 [1916])Google Scholar; The Transformation of Democracy (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction, 1984 [1921])Google Scholar.

15. Spencer, Principles of Sociology; Pareto, General Sociology; Pareto, Vifredo, Manual of Political Economy (New York: Kelley, 1971 [1909]).Google Scholar

16. Durkheim, Emile, The Division of Labor in Society (New York: Free Press, 1964 [1893])Google Scholar; Pareto, General Sociology.

17. Durkheim, Division of Labor.

18. Cantor, Paul and Kraus, James, “Changing Patterns of Ownership Rights in the People's Republic of China: A Legal and Economic Analysis in the Context of Economic Reforms and Social Conditions,” Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law 23 (1990): 536.Google Scholar

19. China Daily, 9 07 1986, p. 4.Google Scholar

20. Herman, Richard, “The Education of China's Lawyers,” Albany Law Review 46 (1982): 793–94.Google Scholar

21. After the Qing Dynasty's fall in 1911, modern legal expertise was developed in the later years of Guomindang (or Nationalist) rule, especially during the nine years from 1928 to 1937, before the outbreak of the Sino-Japanese war. But these gains were lost again with the Communist victory over the Guomindang in 1949, when all private practice of law was banned and the application of legal expertise was limited to those in certain government ministries and within the state-controlled judiciary. Due to the insufficient number of trained Communist judicial personnel immediately after 1949, many judges, procurators, court clerks, and prison administrators who had served under the Nationalists were allowed to continue in their offices. But a Legal Reform Campaign launched in 1952 removed many from office or condemned many as counterrevolutionaries (Cohen, Jerome, “Chinese Mediation on the Eve of Modernization,” California Law Review 59 [1966]: 10Google Scholar). At the time of the Hundred Flowers movement in 1957, some 800 “legal adviser's offices” were served by 2500 full-time and 300 part-time lawyers (Spence, Jonathan, The Search for Modern China [New York: Norton, 1990], p. 704Google Scholar). Most of these skilled practitioners were dismissed during the anti-rightist campaign of 1957, and most civil disputes were handled by the informal, nonjudicial organs, namely mediation committees. In 1959 the government abolished the Ministry of Justice altogether, along with all fora for organizing lawyers as a group. The few remaining law schools had few students, and political theory courses supplanted professional legal training (Chen, Shouyi, “Thirty Years of Chinese Legal Science,” in Zhongguo Faxue Wenji [“Collected essays on Chinese legal science”] [Beijing, 1984]Google Scholar). In serious criminal cases the “law,” such as it was, was administered by a system of state courts and state prosecutors. Party members who transgressed were subject to a separate system of review and punishment meted out by the provincial party committee structure. Most of what might be called civil cases were handled at the local city-ward or rural-brigade level by mediators. Early in the Cultural Revolution (1966–1976) the few remaining law schools were closed, their libraries dispersed or destroyed and their faculty sent to the countryside. During the next ten years virtually no laws were enacted, and almost no law books or journals were published.

22. Spence, , Modern China, p. 708.Google Scholar

23. Renmin Ribao (overseas edition), 13 July 1986, p. 4.

24. China Daily, 22 February 1989; Japan Times, 27 October 1992, p. 8. To appreciate the truly daunting task in China today of quickly educating large numbers of students in a specialized field like law, one must bear in mind that 230 million people in China (95% of them rural and 70% of them female) were defined as “illiterate” by the State Statistical Bureau, (China Quarterly 117 (03 1989):180–95 and 118 (04 1989):391–407).Google Scholar According to a 1980 estimate (Spence, , Modern China, p. 690)Google Scholar, less than 6 percent of the Chinese judiciary had any formal legal education. Short-term special training courses have been used to educate newly appointed officials with no previous exposure to legal study. But in the allocation of assignments to the bench, political dependability remains far more important than professional competence.

25. Spence, , Modern China, p. 730.Google Scholar

26. Ibid.

27. Hsia, Tao-tai and Zeldin, Wendy, “Recent Legal Developments in the People's Republic of China,” Harvard International Law Journal 28 (1987): 267–70.Google Scholar Substantial problems remain, however. For example many parts of the Foreign Economic Contract Law are ambiguous, and foreign corporations need detailed, carefully worded contracts if they are to avoid later complications.

28. For example a definitive textbook of international law, with contributions from twenty senior Chinese jurists, was published in 1981. Beijing officials invited numerous foreign legal experts to visit China and help analyze international procedures, such as the Law of the PRC on Enterprise Bankruptcy of 1986 (Spence, , Modern China, p. 709Google Scholar).

29. Quarterly Documentation,” in China Quarterly 77 (03 1979): 172.Google Scholar

30. Powers, Charles, “On Regulatory Authority: Insights from Emile Durkheim,” Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 21 (1985).3.0.CO;2-L>CrossRefGoogle Scholar

31. Zhengfa Luntan (“Law and politics tribune”) 5 (1989): 3745.Google Scholar

32. Summary of World Broadcasts (BBC), Part 3, Far East, 1038 (5 April 1991): C1 / 5–6.

33. Zhengfa Luntan 5 (1989): 3745.Google Scholar

34. Summary of World Broadcasts, 0841 (13 08 1990): B2/ 6.Google Scholar

35. Spence, , Modern China, p. 736.Google Scholar For even more crime statistics, see Rocca, Jean-louis, “Corruption and Its Shadow: An Anthropological View of Corruption in China,” China Quarterly 130 (1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

36. Durkheim, , Division of Labor, p. 113.Google Scholar

37. Cotterrel, Roger, “Durkheim on Legal Development and Social Solidarity,” British Journal of Law and Society 4 (1977): 247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

38. Ibid., p. 250.

39. China Quarterly 102 (June 1985): 374.

40. Clarke, , “What's Law Got to Do with It?” pp. 5657.Google Scholar

41. Pye, Lucien, “The State and the Individual: An Overview Interpretation,” China Quarterly 127 (1991):462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

42. Pye, Lucien, “Liberalization in China: Can Economics Be the Engine of Political Change?The Fletcher Forum 12 (1988): 228.Google Scholar

43. Zheng, Tianxian, “Zuigao renmin fayuan gongzuo baogao” (“Work report of the supreme people's court”), translated in Foreign Broadcast Information Service, Daily Report, China, 25 04 1985, p.7.Google Scholar

44. Ibid.

45. Buxbaum, David, “Some Aspects of Civil Procedure and Practice at the Trial Level in Tan shui and Hsin chu from 1789 to 1895,” Journal of Asian Studies 30 (1971): 266–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar The very form and organization of the Da Qing Lu Li suggest that Qing law was undifferentiated from administration in many ways. In form, the code is a directive from the emperor to magistrates on correct procedures in trying or deciding cases; it is not addressed to the population to whom it applied. The code organizes offenses according to which of the six state bureaucracies a particular delict would fall under—and not according to the nature of the crime (e.g., crimes against person or crimes against property), its seriousness (e.g., crimespunishable with beating or crimes punishable with death) or the status of the victims (e.g., family members or government officials) (Jones, , “Studying the Ch'ing Code,” pp. 338-39Google Scholar).

46. In Qing China law was not formally studied, as were for example philosophy and literature, both of which were subjects on the civil service examination (Watt, John, The District Magistrate in Late Imperial China [New York: Columbia University Press, 1972], pp. 2425Google Scholar). No provision was made for on-the-job training or practica. The district magistrates who enforced the Da Qing Lu Li were not trained in the law, although they had secretaries who were experts of a sort and who, at least in some cases, may have functioned as the actual decisionmakers (Der Sprenkel, Sybille Van, Legal Institutions in Manchu China [London: Athlone Press, 1962], pp. 144–46Google Scholar). The county magistrates acted as detectives, judges, and jury; they accumulated the evidence, evaluated it, and passed sentence. Punishments for particular crimes were prescribed in the legal code, which magistrates had to follow. Although these officials often relied on a member of their clerical staff allegedly “expert” in the law, no independent profession of law and no lawyers existed. Those who, from the outside, tried to intervene in criminal cases were usually castigated for their efforts.

47. Jones, , “Studying the Ch'ing Code,” p. 356.Google Scholar

48. Hence the criminal-civil distinction was not so relevant as whether an offense or dispute should be settled by the formal or informal judicial machinery, which, according to Ansley (Ansley, Clive, “Chinese Criminal Law under Manchus and Marxists,” University of British Columbia Law Review 20 [1986]: 169–71)Google Scholar, depended on three related factors. (1) Were the interests of the government (or society at large) seriously affected? A theft, an assault, or in certain specific family situations, a killing, might not involve the formal legal machinery at all. Conversely, stirring up litigation or even reneging on a stated intention to commit suicide might well result in heavy penalties being inflicted by the formal judicial process. (2) What was the magnitude of the act? As a general rule, an act would not encounter the formal machinery of the law if it had a relatively minor impact on society. But if it created a noticeable disturbance, whether by “criminal” activity or simply by fomenting discontent, formal legal implications were inevitable. Thus inciting a commercial strike was punished by decapitation in the Qing code (Bodde, Derk and Morris, Clarence, Law in Imperial China, Exemplified by 190 Ch'ing Dynasty Cases [translation of Hsing-an hui-lan] [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1967], p. 279).Google Scholar Correspondingly, art. 10 of the PRC's current Code of Criminal Procedure renders criminal and punishable by law “any action which… disrupts public order… or any other action which endangers society.” (3) Did the more informal judicial organs fail? If clan, guild, or village organizations or mediators failed to resolve a dispute or reform a chronic troublemaker, the matter would end up at court.

49. Gray, Whitmore and Zheng, Henry, trans., “General Principles of Civil Law of the People's Republic of China,” American Journal of Comparative Law 34 (1986).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

50. Luhmann, Niklas, Differentiation of Society (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982), p. 126.Google Scholar

51. Ibid., p. 129.

52. Habermas, Jürgen, Faktizität und Geltung. Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie de Rechts und des detnokratischen Rechtsstaats (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1992), p. 484.Google Scholar

53. Alexy, Robert, Theorie der Grundrechte (Baden-Baden: Nomos, 1985), p. 458.Google Scholar

54. Habermas, , Faktizitat und Geltung, p. 500.Google Scholar

55. Nor is modernization necessarily and in all respects emancipatory, in a political and social sense. In some cases modernization may simply provide resources for new forms of domination. In other cases it may increase anxiety over social status. For example the distribution of rewards in modern societies depends, increasingly, on individual achievement, not group membership or ascribed status.

56. If for example a legal rule (plausible in terms of both civil and economic law) asserts that, in a given context, the equal should be treated equally and the unequal unequally, how should it be applied in concrete cases? In fact, no legal rule, no matter how context-sensitive, can actually bring about the asserted equal right to private autonomy unless it simultaneously provides the individual an effective equal right to political autonomy (the right to participate in, or otherwise influence, the political fora in which equality and inequality are defined in practical terms and measures decided upon to create, eliminate, or modify them). In many concrete instances probably only the affected parties themselves can determine what equality and inequality actually mean.

57. The liberal and the welfare-state models both regard the individual solely in his or her role as addressee of the legal order. But individuals can only be autonomous when they are equally “authors” of the law to which, as addressees, they are also subject (Habermas, , Faktizität und Geltung, p. 492Google Scholar). In this spirit (though in a very different context) I develop a general model which I call “enlightened localism” (Benjamin Gregg, “Possibility of Social Critique in an Indeterminate World,” Theory and Society [forthcoming]). “Enlightened localism” does not attempt to resolve the tension between the liberal and the welfare-state models, but rather to go beyond both paradigms. Both constructs freedom as the equal distribution of earned or entitled goods. My alternative constructs freedom not as possession, but as action: equal participation in the collective self-determination of interested citizens or otherwise relevant members of a community, however defined. Such a model could be relevant to a future China freed of its enduring traditionalism.