Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T17:40:20.111Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Genomic data and the dividual self

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 December 2019

Ian McGonigle*
Affiliation:
Nanyang Assistant Professor, School of Social Sciences, School of Biological Sciences (courtesy appointment), Nanyang Technological University, Singapore
*
Author for correspondence: Dr Ian McGonigle, E-mail: ianmcgonigle@ntu.edu.sg
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In response to a recent commentary (Tigard, in press) on my previous article, ‘The Collective Nature of Personalized Medicine’ (McGonigle, 2016), herein I discuss collective responsibilities and rights in relation to the ethics of genomic data and personalized medicine. I respond to and elaborate on some of the issues Tigard raises and I draw on the anthropological concept of ‘dividuality’ to emphasize the precisely shared nature of genomic data in order to illuminate the ethical complexity surrounding their protection. Overall, I argue that genomic data, by virtue of their distributed and shared nature, necessitate novel approaches for bioethical assessment.

Type
Commentary
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2019

1. Introduction

It is a pleasure to respond to the thoughtful commentary of Tigard (Reference Tigardin press) regarding my previous article (McGonigle, Reference McGonigle2016) in this journal on the collective nature of personalized medicine. I am grateful for the consideration my article has garnered and for the engaged reading it has received. Tigard, the author of the article ‘Changing the Mindset for Precision Medicine: From Incentivized Biobanking Models to Genomic Data’, is principally concerned with the ethical problems of enrolling participants in databases and precision medicine initiatives. The core issues he raises are that precision medicine is distinct from previous organ/blood donation systems and that prior incentive programmes that worked in the past may not be appropriate for genomic data. The rationale underlying his thesis is that genomic data are qualitatively different from organs, blood or other partible bodily elements. Genomic data may be reused infinitely without being consumed and their immaterial nature makes data a more complex form of property to legally protect and ethically safeguard. Moreover, Tigard correctly suggests that future models for incentivizing participation in databases and biobanks must move ‘toward brand new ways of collectively improving individual treatment and overall health’. Here we certainly agree.

In my previous article (McGonigle, Reference McGonigle2016), I made the argument that personalized medicine, despite ostensibly targeting the unique individual, actually depends upon collective participation of large groups in biobanks and genome projects. In that regard alone, personalized medicine is precisely a collective project. That was the major point I wanted to emphasize in my earlier article. In this short rebuttal, I would like to clarify my position on the matter of collective responsibilities and rights, identify the points of agreement with Tigard and elaborate on some of the ethical issues at hand. Principally, I want to draw on the anthropological concept of ‘dividuality’ to further emphasize the precisely shared nature of genomic data. The purpose of this characterization of dividual genomes is to illuminate the ethical complexity surrounding the protection of genomic data.

2. The nature of genomic data

We know that genomic data are different in nature from organs. Firstly, as Tigard aptly observes, data are partible and alienable. Secondly, for now at least, ‘vital organs are properly considered scarce and non-renewable resources’ (Tigard, Reference Tigardin press). Data and patients’ medical records, however, are abundant even if they are not yet fully available for use in precision medicine databases. Data, in distinction to organs, are highly available and obtainable. Thirdly, in contrast to blood and organs, ‘personal data are very easily duplicated, transmitted and shared with anyone, anywhere.’ Furthermore, when data are consumed, they do not diminish in value. This is an important point. It may even be the case that the more genomic data are used for precision medicine projects, the more valuable the data become for further studies and clinical applications. There is indeed a growing market valuation of data.

There is a further characteristic of genomic data, however, that Tigard did not address: the shared nature that genomic data have with the wider genetic cohort, be they biological kin, tribe, ethnic group or nation. This characteristic makes it difficult and even dangerous to treat individual genomic data as solely and simply individual property and to proceed to protect genomic data under established mechanisms of private property or through systems applied to individual organs. Rather, genomic data need sui generis systems of protection and regulation.

3. Dividual genomes

Dividuality is an anthropological concept from the study of kinship that describes the intersubjective nature of personhood in contextualized social relations. As opposed to a circumscribed individual self, the dividual self is a distributed entity, relationally constructed, partible, composite and essentially divisible (Strathern, Reference Strathern1988; Wagner, Reference Wagner, Godelier and Strathern1991; Gell, Reference Gell1998; Mosko, Reference Mosko2015). These insights come from the ethnographic study of native communities where the self is understood to exist only within the social networks and situated contexts that lend meaning and identity to the person. The dividual self is also a surprisingly good metaphor for describing the shared nature of genomic data. Like the dividual self in an anthropological sense, genomic data gain their meaning and utility in reference to the wider genomic cohort. Or, more precisely, genetic variants attain their significance in relation to the reference genome.

In thinking of the limits of personal privacy in relation to genomic data, the concept of dividuality is particularly illuminating. Noam Shomron and I first introduced this notion in an earlier article in this journal (McGonigle & Shomron, Reference McGonigle and Shomron2016). There we argued that human genetic personhood (i.e., who you are genetically) and social identity might be better considered as being ‘dividual’ rather than individual, in the sense that genetic data are partially shared with close kin who may also share relevant health and life experiences. Indeed, it is precisely the ‘dividual’ character of genomic data that fosters the establishment of national biobanks and national or ethnic genome projects. A presumed shared set of genetic variants underpins the value in studying a specific ethnic cohort.

The fact that genomic data and the associated personal medical data are precisely ‘dividual’ in nature must perforce impact ethical standards, legislation and governance structures. Legal citizens will have to recognize that when they disclose their perceived personal genomic data publicly, they also share data about their biological kin.

This phenomenon becomes more readily apparent with the growing use and power of genomics in forensics. In 2018, for example, the so-called ‘Golden State Killer’ was arrested in the USA after detectives tracked the suspect down through genetic analysis. The police had previously linked the Golden State Killer to more than 50 rapes and 12 murders from 1976 to 1986, but the investigation had gone cold decades ago. By uploading a DNA sample collected at one of the crime scenes to a recreational genetic ancestry website (Kolata & Murphy, Reference Kolata and Murphy2018), the suspect was tracked down based on genetic relatedness to participants who had shared their DNA with the genealogy service. In this instance, genetic databases were used for the public good of bringing a notorious murderer to justice. This is just one example of how disclosing personal genomic data may have unintended consequences (positive or negative) for other related persons. But in the fields of healthcare and personalized medicine, there are other bioethical issues to consider when sharing personal genetic data.

Exposing genomic data may impact employment or marriage opportunities. The disclosure of your individual genomic data may entail damages to related individuals who could suffer discrimination as a consequence, particularly if the persons share a high risk of developing an inheritable disease. This potential raises more questions about collective consent, the responsibility or danger in disclosing or restricting data and the limits of personal and family privacy. There arises the issue of balancing individual rights with a collective responsibility to ensure no harm comes to related others. There is thus a potential conflict of interest between protecting individual privacy and the growing importance of genomic databases with the economic valuation of data in the context of personalized medicine projects. Data on specific groups are becoming more sought and valued as we enter the era of ethnic genome projects. Consequently, there are tensions between individual privacy, genomic sovereignty and the need for collective databases for personalized medicine to move forward.

4. The genomic group

In the 1990s, there was a call for a worldwide survey of human genetic diversity (Gurwitz et al., Reference Gurwitz, Kimchi, Bonne-Tamir and Knoopers2003, p. 4), initially by the Human Genome Diversity Project. The main assumptions were that the Human Genome Project would not sufficiently capture the human diversity of the world and that there was also a need to better understand the varying degrees of human susceptibility to disease and historical migrations. Since then, national genome projects and national biobanks have proliferated around the world.

After the advent of second-generation genome sequencing, biobanks have also yielded the possibility of cataloguing genomic data on large numbers of people. Fast and high-throughput genomic sequencing platforms raise hopes of revealing the associations of many diseases with single-nucleotide polymorphisms. It is assumed that by identifying the molecular basis for disease a new age of personalized treatment will arrive. One of the principles of personalized medicine is that performing genome-wide association studies with the masses of data generated from thousands of individuals would reveal meaningful disease biomarkers.

These developments have captured the attention of scholars in bioethics and the social study of science and there is a significant literature focusing on biobanks and genomic databases. Much of this scholarship has focused on the ethics of the sampling and storage of human biological material and medical information (Cambon-Thomsen, Reference Cambon-Thomsen2004; Cambon-Thomsen et al., Reference Cambon-Thomsen, Rial-Sebbag and Knoppers2007; Haga & Beskow, Reference Haga and Beskow2008; Hansson, Reference Hansson2009; McGonigle & Shomron, Reference McGonigle and Shomron2016), the problems and limitations of collective and individual consent (Hansson et al., Reference Hansson, Dillner, Bartram, Carlson and Helgesson2006; Caulfield & Kaye, Reference Caulfield and Kaye2009) and the entailed protection of personal data and the legal definition of the nature of the individual participant (Kaye, Reference Kaye, Tutton and Corrigan2004; Gurwitz, Reference Gurwitz2015; McGonigle, Reference McGonigle2016). Other work on biobanks has described how transnational collaborations entail challenges for governance where different regulatory and ethical regimes face the challenges of cross-border harmonization (Gottweis & Peterson, Reference Gottweis and Petersen2008; Kaye, Reference Kaye2011; Gottweis & Lauss, Reference Gottweis and Lauss2012; Chen, Reference Chen2013).

Beyond these pragmatic and normative ethical questions of governance and procedure, biobanks and identity-based genetic research also raise significant and broad-ranging societal concerns that impinge on social identities. Today, social identities (including national, racial or ethnic identities) are progressively attended to in the molecular realm, a phenomenon I have discussed in this journal under the idiom ‘molecularization of identity’ (McGonigle & Benjamin, Reference McGonigle and Benjamin2016).

More and more, genetics has entered the lexicon of identity politics. Recently, for example, Lebanese foreign minister Gebran Bassil tweeted about the genetic character of the Lebanese: ‘We have devoted a concept to our Lebanese identity, above any other affiliation, and we have said that it was genetic, since it was the only explanation for our similarity and distinction…’ (Nassar, Reference Nassar2019). Genomics has become a way of imagining collective identity. Indeed, white nationalists in the USA have been wielding genomic evidence to support their racial identity (Panofsky & Donovan, Reference Panofsky and Donovan2019). All of this is to say that genomics has a profound impact on how the ethnic or national group self-identifies, understands itself and defends its boundaries. The significance of this phenomenon in relation to personalized medicine is that genomic data affect not only the individual donor. Genomic data speak for the collective, and accordingly must be ethically recognized as a partially shared resource.

5. New ethical directions

Tigard (Reference Tigardin press) notes ‘the challenge of amassing the large-scale databases necessary for the success of precision medicine cannot be met by looking to existing models of blood and organ donation wherein contributors are incentivized with distinct personal benefits.’ He is correct. We need to develop novel ways of thinking about the ethics of genomic data that are tailored to their precise nature.

This is all the more important as we enter an era when genomic databasing is intersecting with identity politics. The USA recently launched ‘All of Us’, a research programme that aims to further personalized medicine by generating medical and genomic databases across all US ethnic groups. One of the principles underlying the effort is that genetic variants vary across ethnic groups so that each ethnic group shares certain medical and genetic inheritances. Simply put, you cannot achieve personalized medicine for all ethnic groups without data on all ethnic groups. This is the logic behind the proliferation of ‘ethnic reference genomes’. Such ethnic-based genomic research is flourishing worldwide. GenomeAsia100K, for example, is a Singapore-based human genome project that aims to generate ethnic reference genomes for the major Asian ethnicities. GenomeAsia100K aims to sequence 100,000 Asian genomes in an effort that addresses an ethnic bias towards Western populations in previous genomic research (see McGonigle & Schuster, Reference McGonigle and Schuster2019). It is thus crucial to recognize that genomic data are precisely a shared resource and indeed a shared risk.

6. The future of ethnic medicine

As Tigard (Reference Tigardin press) observes, personalized medicine may, in fact, become routinized in a way that resembles traditional clinical approaches and older therapeutic models. It is not simply that establishing genomic databases will radically improve patient outcomes. Environmental factors may become more salient in some cases than genetic variants. Nonetheless, personalized medicine will have unique characteristics and will raise novel ethical concerns in each cultural context. In certain cases, we may need to recognize that identifying a genetic variant associated with a disease in a person may impact the patient's biological kin, tribe or ethnic group through stigmatization.

For example, being associated with a lineage that has a particular haplotype with a high disease risk could be detrimental to marriage prospects. This issue is particularly salient in highly endogamous societies where an elevated rate of inheritable Mendelian disorders is present. This is the case in the Arab Gulf countries. The Qatari population, for example, has many inheritable diseases, which have been attributed to a history of tribal endogamy with an estimated consanguinity rate of approximately 54% (Sidra, 2015, p. 47). Consequently, a large-scale genome project, Qatar Genome, has been established to generate genomic data from Qatari citizens.

The goal of Qatar Genome is to reduce the burden of childhood disease associated with such autosomal recessive single-gene disorders. One of the most ambitious aims of the plan is to ‘do whole genome sequencing (WGS) of 10,000 Qataris (3% of the Qatar Genome project)’ (Sidra, 2015, p. 52). This target was the largest international genome project of its time when it launched, comparable to the ongoing sequencing project of the Genomics England projectFootnote 1 or Singapore-based GenomeAsia100K in terms of the amount of data generated.

The large-scale genomic sequencing of Qatar Genome has already yielded a high-resolution characterization of the Qatari genome structure (Fakhro et al., Reference Fakhro, Staudt and Ramstetter2016). This is the first Qatar ethnic reference genome, which is being used to develop neonatal screening and assessment of genetic disorders prevalent in Qatar. The Qatar reference genome is a map of the rare and common genetic variants in the Qatari population. One of the other achievements of Qatar Genome with Weill Cornell Medicine – Qatar is the development of the first population-specific screening array – the Q-Chip – that can be used to determine risk for recessive disorders known to segregate in the population. The Q-Chip contains the gene variants specific to the Qatari population so that clinical diagnosis of genetic diseases using the Q-Chip will be based on the unique genetic information derived from the Qatari population (Qatar Genome, 2018).

Such ethnic personalized medicine developments as Qatar Genome take us closer to eliminating inheritable genetic diseases, but they also pose ethical dilemmas: who wants to have custodianship of such highly sensitive data? Who is liable if there is a data leak? Is it a crime to expose another person's genomic profile? Or, can you demand that a relative keep secret an inheritable disease for fear of family stigma?

These questions may only be tackled properly if we first recognize the collective – indeed dividual – nature of genomic data. The path forward must entail a reconfiguration of the notion of genomic data as being individual (like organs or blood) to being precisely dividual, as complex and fraught as that may initially seem.

7. Conclusion

In conclusion, I concur with Tigard (Reference Tigardin press) that genomic data are qualitatively different from other forms of biological substances like blood or internal organs. However, I would add that genomic data may be further distinguished by their ‘dividual’ character, demanding recognition of their shared identity with related others. This phenomenon poses methodological challenges for overcoming the fear of exposure on the side of individuals with certain inheritable disease in their family or wider kin group. It also poses an ethical dilemma as to how to regulate the protection of genomic data. In conceiving of a way forward from these complex ethical dilemmas, I agree with Tigard that new and creative avenues need to be pursued. Crucially, however, I add that we must start thinking of genomic data as a common pool of information and value. Unlike bodily organs, which are clearly defined objects of individual origin, genomic data are far blurrier.

Footnotes

1 Genomics England was set up in 2015 to deliver the 100,000 Genomes Project, its flagship project to sequence 100,000 whole genomes from NHS patients with rare diseases and their families, as well as patients with common cancers. In late 2018, Secretary of State for Health and Social Care, the Rt Hon. Matt Hancock MP, announced plans to sequence five million genomes over the following five years (see Genomics England, 2018).

References

Cambon-Thomsen, A. (2004). The social and ethical issues of post-genomic human biobanks. Nature Reviews Genetics 5, 866873.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cambon-Thomsen, A., Rial-Sebbag, E. and Knoppers, B. M. (2007). Trends in ethical and legal frameworks for the use of human biobanks. European Respiratory Journal 30(2), 373382.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Caulfield, T. and Kaye, J. (2009). Broad consent in biobanking: reflections on seemingly insurmountable dilemmas. Medical Law International 10(2), 85100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chen, H. (2013). Governing international biobank collaboration: a case study of China Kadoorie Biobank. Science, Technology & Society 18(3), 321338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fakhro, K. A., Staudt, M. R., Ramstetter, M. D., et al. (2016). The Qatar Genome: a population-specific tool for precision medicine in the Middle East. Human Genome Variation 3, 16016.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gell, A. (1998). Art and Agency: An Anthropological Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Genomics England (2018). Genomics England. https://www.genomicsengland.co.uk (accessed 29 September 2019).Google Scholar
Gottweis, H. and Lauss, G. (2012). Biobank governance: heterogeneous modes of ordering and democratization. Journal of Community Genetics 3(2), 6172.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gottweis, H. and Petersen, A. (eds.) (2008). Biobanks: Governance in Comparative Perspective. London and New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gurwitz, D. (2015). Genetic privacy: trust is not enough. Science 347(6225), 957958.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gurwitz, D., Kimchi, O. and Bonne-Tamir, B. (2003). The Israeli DNA and cell line collection: a human diversity repository. In Knoopers, B. M. (ed). Populations and Genetics: Legal and Socio-Ethical Perspectives. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, pp. 95113.Google Scholar
Haga, S. B. and Beskow, L. M. (2008). Ethical, legal, and social implications of biobanks for genetics research. Advances in Genetics 60, 505544.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hansson, M. G. (2009). Ethics and biobanks. British Journal of Cancer 100, 812.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hansson, M. G., Dillner, J., Bartram, C. R., Carlson, J. A. and Helgesson, G. (2006). Should donors be allowed to give broad consent to future biobank research? Lancet Oncology 7(3), 266269.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kaye, J. (2004). Abandoning informed consent: the case of genetic research in population collections. In Genetic Databases: Socio-Ethical Issues in the Collection and Use of DNA (eds. Tutton, R. and Corrigan, O.), pp. 117138. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kaye, J. (2011). From single biobanks to international networks: developing e-governance. Human Genetics 130(3), 377382.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kolata, G. and Murphy, H. (2018). The Golden State Killer is tracked through a thicket of DNA, and experts shudder. New York Times, 27 April.Google Scholar
McGonigle, I. V. (2016). The collective nature of personalized medicine. Genetics Research 98, e3.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McGonigle, I. V. and Benjamin, R. (2016). The molecularization of identity: science and subjectivity in the 21st century. Genetics Research 98, e12.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McGonigle, I. V. and Schuster, S. C. (2019). Global science meets ethnic diversity: Ian McGonigle interviews GenomeAsia100k Scientific Chairman Stephan Schuster. Genetics Research 101, e5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McGonigle, I. V. and Shomron, N. (2016). Privacy, anonymity, and subjectivity, in genomic research. Genetics Research 98, e2.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mosko, M. S. (2015). Unbecoming individuals: the partible character of the Christian person. HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 5(1), 361393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nassar, A. (2019). In his Machiavellian designs, Bassil is using racist discourse. Arab Weekly, 16 June.Google Scholar
Panofsky, A. and Donovan, J. (2019). Genetic ancestry testing among white nationalists: from identity repair to citizen science. Social Studies of Science 49(5), 653681.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Qatar Genome (2018). Qatar Genome and Qatar Biobank lead efforts to produce the first Qatari gene chip. https://qatargenome.org.qa/node/138 (accessed 29 September 2019).Google Scholar
Sidra (2015). Sidra 5-Year Strategic Plan. http://www.sidra.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/12/sidras-five-year-strategic.pdf (accessed 28 November 2015).Google Scholar
Strathern, M. (1988). The Gender of the Gift: Problems with Women and Problems with Society in Melanesia. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tigard, D. (in press). Changing the mindset for precision medicine: from incentivized biobanking models to genomic data. Genetics Research.Google Scholar
Wagner, R. (1991). The fractal person. In Big Men and Great Men: Personifications of Power in Melanesia (eds. Godelier, M. and Strathern, M.), pp. 159173. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar