Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-qxsvm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-27T10:06:33.744Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Conduct of Hostilities, Attack Effects, and Criminal Accountability

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 June 2024

Geoffrey Corn*
Affiliation:
George R. Killam Jr. Chair of Criminal Law and Director of the Center for Military Law and Policy, Texas Tech University School of Law; Lieutenant Colonel, US Army (Retired), and formerly Special Assistant for Law of War Matters and Chief of the Law of War Branch, Office of the Judge Advocate General, United States Army; Chief of International Law for US Army Europe; Professor of International and National Security Law at the US Army Judge Advocate General's School (United States)

Abstract

War crimes related to the decision to carry out attacks during the conduct of hostilities are almost always defined in terms of conduct and not result (Article 8(2)(b) of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court). Yet it is common for critiques of such decisions to focus on attack results as proof of their alleged illegality. While such results are probative of compliance or non-compliance with international humanitarian law rules regulating the conduct of hostilities, they should rarely be indisputable. This article addresses the challenge of attaching probative value to attack results when assessing responsibility for alleged war crimes based on allegedly illicit attack decisions.

Type
Articles
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press in association with the Faculty of Law, the Hebrew University of Jerusalem

1. Introduction

For more than a century, the international community has aspired to ensure individual accountability for serious violations of the laws and customs of war, today known as international humanitarian law, or IHL. Several considerations have motivated this aspiration, including the retributive and general deterrence interests normally associated with criminal sanction. While there have been periods of rapid evolution in the processes associated with such accountability, preventing impunity for what appear to be relatively obvious war crimes continues to be a significant international legal and diplomatic challenge.Footnote 1

Tolerance for such impunity, however, has become increasingly perceived as unacceptable. This itself is a consequence of numerous factors, not the least of which is the speed with which global audiences are exposed to the consequences of such apparent violations, and the density and clarity of that exposure. Images and on-scene reports of the death and destruction inflicted during armed conflicts – especially when civilians are the victims – are transmitted so rapidly that the forces engaged in such hostilities struggle to influence the perceptions and narratives created by such instant access to battlefield information.

Intolerance of perceived impunity for those suspected of committing war crimes has been elevated to a new level in relation to the ongoing conflict between Russia and Ukraine. Calls for criminal accountability have been robust and consistent since Russia launched its most recent campaign of aggression.Footnote 2 These calls are undoubtedly influenced substantially by the visceral reaction to visual evidence of the widespread infliction of suffering on the Ukrainian civilian population, especially as this suffering appears to result from indiscriminate and illegal attacks by Russian armed forces.Footnote 3

It is difficult to deny the validity of the perception that Russian forces have committed, and continue to commit, serious war crimes in the conduct of these hostilities. However, the near total reliance on attack effects to conclude that war crimes have been committed raises an important question in the mosaic of the criminal accountability process: what is – or perhaps what should be – the probative value of attack effects in the criminal accountability process for allegations of conduct of hostilities crimes? Arguably, while attack effects are relevant to raising suspicion and the assessment of guilt of those subsequently accused of conduct of hostilities crimes, they rarely (if ever) provide conclusive evidence of such guilt. This is because the focus of both the IHL regulation of the conduct of hostilities and the international criminal law proscription of this conduct is on the decision to attack, rather than the result of the attack. Accordingly, it is the judgement of the individual in deciding to launch the attack, within the context of the totality of the circumstances that existed at the time of the attack decision, that defines compliance or non-compliance with both bodies of law.

This article will consider this question of how attack effects should play into the accountability process for war crimes prosecutions. It will begin by outlining why accountability must ultimately turn on the legality of attack decisions and not on their effects. It will then consider what is often the evidentiary dilemma created by a lack of access to direct evidence of the pre-attack state of mind of a criminal defendant when that state of mind is an essential element of criminality. This will lead to consideration of the importance of circumstantial evidence as proof of a subjective criminal mental state. The article will then consider whether attack effects alone can ever legitimately provide sufficient proof of illegal attack decisions. It will then briefly suggest other types of circumstantial evidence that should play an important role in the totality of the evidence mustered in a case where attack effects are the primary evidence of culpability. Finally, the article will raise the question of whether resistance to prosecutorial efforts to gain access to evidence associated with attack decision making should ever justify an adverse inference against a defendant to war crimes.

2. Conduct of hostilities and attack decisions

The effects of an attack are emotive.Footnote 4 They are also nearly always the primary publicly available information related to the process of employing force during the conduct of hostilities.Footnote 5 Furthermore, because hostilities seem increasingly to gravitate towards areas of substantial civilian populations, these effects routinely include widespread destruction of civilian property, death and injury to civilians, and the infliction of substantial second- and third-order negative impacts on the civilian population.Footnote 6 These brutal realities of war are also increasingly broadcast to international audiences in near real time, generating widespread perceptions that the conduct of hostilities is both unlawful and immoral.Footnote 7

Yet such imagery rarely tells the complete story of such military actions.Footnote 8 Why was the attack launched? Why was a particular weapon system used? What was the commander's understanding of the enemy's situation at the time of the attack? What alternate feasible options did the commander have at his or her disposal? These are just a few considerations related to the legality of an attack that are almost never revealed by the imagery of attack effects. Nonetheless, because of the emotive nature of such imagery and the lack of access to all these other considerations, it is logical that so many observers and critics of military operations tend to gravitate towards what I have previously labelled ‘effects-based condemnations’ – the process of drawing ipso facto conclusions that war crimes were committed based exclusively on such effects.Footnote 9 However, assessing compliance or non-compliance with the attack legality framework of IHL based solely on such effects is inconsistent with the focus of legal regulation of hostilities that lies at the core of such compliance.Footnote 10

IHL provides a comprehensive legal framework applicable to the conduct of hostilities.Footnote 11 This framework is best reflected in what is routinely characterised as the ‘targeting’ rules codified in the 1977 Additional Protocol I to the Four Geneva Conventions of 1949 (AP I).Footnote 12 These treaty rules reflect near universally recognised principles of customary international law: distinction, proportionality, and, to a somewhat lesser extent, attack precautions.Footnote 13

The principle of distinction, rightly designated as the ‘basic’ rule in AP I, mandates that the only subjects that may be made the deliberate targets of attack are lawful military objectives, members of enemy armed forces and other organised armed groups, and civilians directly participating in hostilities.Footnote 14 In so doing, the rule requires participants in hostilities to constantly ‘distinguish’ between these lawful subjects of attack and all other persons.Footnote 15 This obligation applies equally to a private deciding whether to shoot someone in battle as it does to the highest-level commander deciding whether to launch a massive missile attack.Footnote 16

The principle of distinction also prohibits launching an attack on any object or place that is not a military objective. This limitation is functionally implemented through compliance with the rule of military objective – a customary international law rule codified in AP I.Footnote 17 In its most basic conception, this rule establishes the criteria to decide the places and things that qualify prima facie as lawful objects of a deliberate attack.Footnote 18 While the military objective test does not textually apply to which people may be attacked, it is generally recognised that the same concept applies to justify attacking combatants and civilians directly participating in hostilities.Footnote 19 For combatants, the authority to attack is based on a determination of that ‘status’ and justifies deliberate targeting unless the individual is rendered hors de combat; for civilians directly participating in hostilities, attack authority continues ‘for such time’ as the participation continues.Footnote 20 There is a divergence of views on how individuals who do not qualify as combatants but are members of organised armed groups are properly categorised, with an ‘increasing tendency to treat all non-state actors as merely a conglomeration of civilians who take a direct part in hostilities’.Footnote 21 Some states, like the United States, utilise a membership approach, characterising civilians who are part of an organised armed group as unprivileged belligerents subject to deliberate attack no differently from combatants;Footnote 22 other states follow the approach advanced by the International Committee of the Red Cross and consider these individuals as civilians who lose protection from attack only if their role in the organised armed group amounts to a ‘continuous combatant function’Footnote 23 (CCF).Footnote 24 However, under either approach, the civilian becomes subject to deliberate attack once the relevant assessment is made.Footnote 25

Determining whether a person, place or thing was prima facie subject to deliberate attack is ultimately, however, a matter of judgement.Footnote 26 Indeed, it is self-evident why the rules establishing who or what is a lawful object of deliberate attack are prospective in nature: they require a reasonable assessment of all available information before the trigger is pulled.Footnote 27 No commander or soldier can be expected to have perfect situational awareness, and the variables of combat operations will inevitably influence this important decision.Footnote 28 Accordingly, when making attack decisions, participants in hostilities are obligated to assess all ‘reasonably available’ information to inform the judgement of whether a person, place or thing qualifies as a lawful object of attack.Footnote 29 If the decision turns out to have been wrong, that alone is not an indication of a legal violation.Footnote 30 Only if the error was the result of unreasonable decision making will it indicate such a violation.Footnote 31

If a person, place or thing is assessed as not qualifying as a lawful object of attack, or target, an attack is unquestionably prohibited,Footnote 32 but even when the person or object does so qualify, the legality assessment will normally continue to consider other obligations. These additional steps in the legality assessment are required whenever the attack is reasonably assessed as creating risk to civilians or civilian property.Footnote 33 Only when the attack is assessed as creating no such risk may these additional steps of the process be bypassed. In other words, if the target is assessed as a lawful military objective (or individual subject to deliberate attack) and there is no reasonably assessed risk that launching the attack will create such civilian risk, the attack is legally permitted.Footnote 34 However, because this is rarely the case in contemporary armed conflicts, additional rules intended to protect civilians from the incidental or collateral risk of attack must be implemented, notably precautions and proportionality.Footnote 35

The principle of proportionality is part of a broader prohibition against launching any attack that qualifies as indiscriminate.Footnote 36 Again, however, the prohibition is not defined by the result, but by the decision to launch the attack.Footnote 37 For example, if a commander treats distinct military objectives located in a civilian population centre as one general target – what is often called ‘area targeting’ – launching the attack would be considered indiscriminate.Footnote 38 The same rule prohibits employing weapons that cannot be effectively directed at a specific military objective (like a missile or rocket that cannot be designated to strike a specific target) or that produce effects that cannot be controlled after release (such as an incendiary weapon).Footnote 39 However, the proportionality component of this prohibition against launching an indiscriminate attack is most commonly associated with the law's objective of mitigating risk to civilians and civilian property.Footnote 40

Where an attack directed against a military objective is anticipated to result in civilian casualties and/or destruction of civilian property that is assessed as excessive in comparison with the anticipated concrete and direct military advantage, the attack falls within the definition of indiscriminate and is prohibited.Footnote 41 Importantly, this means that such casualties and/or destruction are not categorically prohibited, even when they are an anticipated consequence of conducting an attack on a military objective.Footnote 42 So long as these effects are not the intended objects of attack and are not assessed as excessive, the law tolerates them.Footnote 43

While a cursory review of these principles and accordant implementing treaty rules, one consistent thread runs through all of them: they are focused on the judgement to launch the attack, not the outcome of the attack.Footnote 44 This focal point of legality obligations related to the conduct of hostilities provides the very foundation for a legal regime that seeks to accommodate both the necessity of employing decisive combat power against an enemy and the humanitarian interest of mitigating the suffering resulting from such combat action.Footnote 45 By focusing on the legality of decisions versus the legality of effects, the law accounts for the realities of war by rejecting an impossible standard of complete accuracy in the exercise of attack decision making (not to mention incentivising the exploitation of the presence of civilians in an effort to shield targets from attack).Footnote 46 Instead, what is demanded is not that decisions to attack are always right but that they are always reasonable under the circumstances.Footnote 47

This focus on regulating attack decisions is also integrated into the international criminal law accountability equation.Footnote 48 These provisions generally align with IHL targeting rules and reflect the effort to define offences that subject attack decision makers to liability for illegal attack decisions.Footnote 49 Because of the importance of defining the constituent elements of such offences, the focus on decision making, and not result, is even more explicit.Footnote 50

Like almost all crimes, war crimes fall into two general categories: conduct crimes, and result crimes.Footnote 51 Conduct crimes are defined by the concurrence between a defined criminal state of mind and prohibited conduct, with no requirement to prove a criminal result.Footnote 52 In contrast, result crimes are defined by the concurrence between a defined criminal state of mind and an act or omission that produces a criminal result.Footnote 53 This is reflected in offences falling within the jurisdiction of the International Criminal Court (ICC), which include both conduct and result crimes.Footnote 54 Consider the war crime of wilful killing, as defined in Article 8(2)(a)(i):Footnote 55

  1. (1) The perpetrator killed one or more persons.

  2. (2) Such person or persons were protected under one or more of the Geneva Conventions of 1949.

  3. (3) The perpetrator was aware of the factual circumstances that established that protected status.

  4. (4) The conduct took place in the context of and was associated with an international armed conflict.

  5. (5) The perpetrator was aware of factual circumstances that established the existence of an armed conflict.

Note the evidentiary requirement to prove that the alleged criminal act or omission caused the alleged result: the actual death of a protected person.Footnote 56 Numerous other crimes within the Court's jurisdiction are equally result-focused.Footnote 57

In contrast, almost all war crimes related to the conduct of hostilities are conduct-focused.Footnote 58 These crimes generally align with the IHL principles outlined above.Footnote 59 The ‘basic rule,’ or principle of distinction, is reflected in several war crimes, including the war crimes of attacking civilians, attacking civilian objects, and attacking personnel or objects involved in humanitarian assistance or peacekeeping missions.Footnote 60 Each of these war crimes defines the criminal act as directing an attack on the defined individual or object, with no requirement to prove an actual result of achieving the illegitimate objective.Footnote 61 For example, Article 8(2)(b)(i) defines the war crime of attacking civilians and lists the material elements of this offence as:Footnote 62

  1. (1) The perpetrator directed an attack.

  2. (2) The object of the attack was a civilian population as such or individual civilians not taking direct part in hostilities.

  3. (3) The perpetrator intended the civilian population as such or individual civilians not taking direct part in hostilities to be the object of the attack.

  4. (4) The conduct took place in the context of and was associated with an international armed conflict.

  5. (5) The perpetrator was aware of factual circumstances that established the existence of an armed conflict.

Article 8(2)(e) defines an analogous war crime among the offences applicable to conflicts not of an international character.Footnote 63 Like Article 8(2)(b)(i), the prohibited act is defined as directing an attack against ‘a civilian population as such or individual civilians not taking direct part in hostilities’, with no requirement to prove a criminal result.Footnote 64

Criminal sanction for launching an indiscriminate attack in violation of the proportionality rule is also codified as a conduct crime, which is belied by the title of the offence.Footnote 65 Specifically, Article 8(2)(b)(iv) is titled the ‘[w]ar crime of excessive incidental death, injury, or damage’.Footnote 66 This suggests that the crime is focused on the result of inflicting this excessive harm.Footnote 67 However, the elements of the offence contradict this suggestion, as they require proof of the following:Footnote 68

  1. (1) The perpetrator launched an attack.

  2. (2) The attack was such that it would cause incidental death or injury to civilians or damage to civilian objects or widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural environment, and that such death, injury or damage would be of such an extent as to be clearly excessive in relation to the concrete and direct overall military advantage anticipated.

  3. (3) The perpetrator knew that the attack would cause incidental death or injury to civilians or damage to civilian objects or widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural environment and that such death, injury or damage would be of such an extent as to be clearly excessive in relation to the concrete and direct overall military advantage anticipated.

  4. (4) The conduct took place in the context of and was associated with an international armed conflict.

  5. (5) The perpetrator was aware of factual circumstances that established the existence of an armed conflict.

Note that the prohibited criminal act is the launching of the attack, again with no requirement to prove a criminal result, only the anticipation that the attack will result in the prohibited result.Footnote 69 Thus, a commander who launches an attack with the requisite knowledge that it is anticipated to inflict clearly excessive civilian death, injury or destruction of civilian property, has violated this provision, even if that outcome does not come to fruition.Footnote 70 In contrast, the commander who launches an attack based on a reasonable assessment that it will not result in clearly excessive civilian death, injury or destruction of civilian property has not violated this proscription, even if it turns out that the actual result does give rise to that level of harm.Footnote 71

It is unfortunate that the Rome Statute does not enumerate a war crime based on a violation of the obligation to implement feasible civilian risk mitigation precautions. Such an offence, however, would need to focus on an alleged criminal omission rather than on an alleged criminal result.Footnote 72 Depending on the requisite criminal mental state, such an offence would require proof either that the defendant knew that implementing such precautions was feasible and omitted to do so, or omitted to do so as the result of a reckless or grossly negligent omission.Footnote 73

Nonetheless, while not a stand-alone crime, evidence of such an omission would almost certainly be relevant in proving the crime of launching an indiscriminate attack. Specifically, where an attack decision maker omitted to implement feasible precautions, it contributes to the finding that the decision maker knew that launching an attack would result in clearly excessive civilian harm.Footnote 74 Importantly, however, even if the IHL precautions obligation is considered functionally embedded within Article 8(2)(b)(iv),Footnote 75 the focal point of accountability remains on conduct, and not result. The relevance of this consideration is not whether precautionary measures were in fact feasible to implement, but whether the decision maker perceived they were and then omitted to do so. Thus, whether considering the basis for a stand-alone IHL violation or an aspect of proving the war crime of launching an indiscriminate attack, the focal point of criminal responsibility remains conduct, and not result.

Accordingly, while both IHL and the ICC make attack conduct the focal point of legal compliance and not attack results, the mental state related to compliance or violation is not identical. When assessing the legality of attack decisions within the IHL framework, it is generally understood that attack decision makers are held to a standard of reasonableness.Footnote 76 Pursuant to this standard, the ultimate focus of the inquiry is whether their decisions fell within a margin of objective reasonableness based on the circumstances ruling at the time of the decisions.Footnote 77 Accordingly, it is logical that war crimes based on violation of these fundamental targeting rules focus on attack decisions and not attack outcomes.Footnote 78 In war, outcomes are often beyond the control of commanders and others who decide to launch attacks.Footnote 79 In contrast, the judgement of the decision to do so is obviously within their control, and therefore it is the state of mind related to that judgement that is the logical focal point of criminal liability.Footnote 80

An unreasonable attack decision, however, is a necessary but insufficient basis for proving guilt for an attack-related war crime. This is because the ICC imposes a culpability standard that is more demanding than that of the reasonable commander standard.Footnote 81 This heightened standard is reflected in the mental elements required for proving violation of targeting-based war crimes.Footnote 82 The requirement to prove that an attack decision violated distinction or proportionality requires, as noted above, that the defendant launched the attack with intent to target civilians or civilian property, or knowledge that the attack on a military objective would result in clearly excessive incidental injury or collateral damage.Footnote 83 These subjective criminal mental states exceed the reasonable commander standard because both require proof of more than simply an unreasonable decision:Footnote 84 proof that the decision to attack was reckless or even grossly negligent would indicate that it was unreasonable, but neither of these findings prove the intent or knowledge required for the ICC offences.Footnote 85

Of course, investigating and punishing individuals who make unreasonable attack decisions is not the exclusive or even the primary responsibility of the ICC. States bear an independent responsibility to hold attack decision makers accountable for unlawful conduct.Footnote 86 In that context, proof of a different criminal state of mind, such as recklessness or gross negligence – imposing a less demanding burden on the prosecution for alleged violations of targeting rules – may satisfy the requirements for domestic criminal accountability.Footnote 87 This may also, however, necessitate proof of a prohibited result depending on how the domestic crime is defined.Footnote 88 Thus, for example, a grossly negligent attack decision would satisfy the requisite mental element for the crime of manslaughter in violation of the Uniform Code of Military Justice applicable to US armed forces, but because manslaughter requires proof of the unlawful killing of a human being, the decision alone would be insufficient to prove this offenceFootnote 89 (or perhaps reckless or grossly negligent attack decisions could provide the basis for other conduct crimes, such as reckless endangerment or dereliction of duty).Footnote 90

Comparing the crime of reckless manslaughter with the crime of launching an attack with the intent to target civilians or individual civilians reinforces the dichotomy between conduct and result targeting violations.Footnote 91 As noted, the former offence is defined in terms of result: the unlawful killing of a human being.Footnote 92 In contrast, the latter offence is defined by conduct: the directing of an attack intending to target civilians.Footnote 93 Accordingly, proving a harmful result is not essential for proving the conduct crime.Footnote 94 However, this does not mean such a result is irrelevant in seeking to prove a conduct violation, but just how should attack results be factored into the culpability equation?

3. Attack effects as circumstantial evidence of criminal intent

3.1. Proof beyond reasonable doubt and the criminal state of mind

Proof beyond reasonable doubt requires evidence to satisfy both a burden of production and a burden of persuasion.Footnote 95 The burden of production is satisfied when the evidence, viewed in the light most favourable to the prosecution, supports a rational finding that all elements of the alleged crime have been established.Footnote 96 Attack effects resulting in the death of civilians, injury to civilians, and/or destruction of civilian property logically serve as important circumstantial evidence to satisfy this prima facie burden.Footnote 97 Of course, the more widespread the injury and/or damage, the more rational is the inference that intent to inflict such results or knowledge that the attack would produce indiscriminate results.Footnote 98

Yet while attack effects may often justify criminal investigation and charge, and satisfy the prima facie burden of production, can they, standing alone, also satisfy the burden of persuasion?Footnote 99 In theory, as long as the inference of criminal intent is the only rational inference derived from such effects, such a finding would be justified.Footnote 100 However, when the circumstantial evidence associated with the attack effects points to the alternate reasonable inference, it would be far less likely that those effects alone would satisfy this burden because those effects must be considered in the context of the attack situation.Footnote 101

This necessitates two qualifications to reliance on attack effects as the principal or exclusive circumstantial evidence of guilt. First, the risk of potential over-reliance on such effects should constantly be emphasised to the jury or judges in deciding guilt. Second, the effects must be assessed in the context of the situation as perceived by the defendant at the time of the attack decision, meaning consideration of available information related to the nature of the target and the circumstances related to the attack. This is because the complexity of combat operations and the myriad of influences on attack decisions will often indicate that effects alone are insufficient to rule out the alternative reasonable conclusion: that the attack – and the resulting effects – were not the result of the requisite criminal intent or knowledge.Footnote 102

3.2. Translating the legal standard to trial process

Effective war crimes prosecutions involve more than just an understanding of the requisite elements of a charged offence; they require proving these elements to a degree sufficient to overcome the legal presumption of innocence.Footnote 103 This is the point at which the evidentiary value of attack results intersects with the challenge of proving conduct crimes.Footnote 104 Proof that satisfies this burden of persuasion will normally fall into two broad categories: direct evidence and circumstantial (to include opinion) evidence.Footnote 105 Contrary to lay misconceptions, these categories of evidence are not, as a matter of law, valued differently.Footnote 106 Instead, it is the plenary prerogative of the fact finder to allocate probative value to all evidence.Footnote 107 The following pattern instruction used in US military trials is an example of this evidentiary principle:Footnote 108

Evidence may be direct or circumstantial. ‘Direct evidence’ is evidence that tends directly to prove or disprove a fact in issue. If a fact in issue was whether it rained during the evening, testimony by a witness that he/she saw it rain would be direct evidence that it rained.

On the other hand, ‘circumstantial evidence’ is evidence that tends to prove some other fact from which, either alone or together with some other facts or circumstances, you may reasonably infer the existence or nonexistence of a fact in issue. If there was evidence the street was wet in the morning, that would be circumstantial evidence from which you might reasonably infer it rained during the night.

There is no general rule for determining or comparing the weight to be given to direct or circumstantial evidence. You should give all the evidence the weight and value you believe it deserves.

Because the war crimes related to illegally launching attacks require proof of a defendant's subjective criminal mental state, direct evidence of that element will often be elusive.Footnote 109 This is simply a truism of any criminal accountability process: proving a defendant's subjective criminal mental state is never easy short of an admission or confession.Footnote 110 When such direct evidence of the defendant's intent or knowledge is admissible and reliable, the likelihood of conviction is at its strongest.Footnote 111 However, when such evidence is available to a prosecutor, the reality is that it creates a powerful incentive for a defendant to offer to plead guilty to secure either a favourable negotiated plea bargain or the mitigating value of contrition.Footnote 112

In practice, this means that in most cases that involve an allegation of a crime requiring proof of intent or knowledge, a plea of not guilty and contested trial will often mean that direct evidence of the criminal mental state is either not available to the prosecution or, if available, is of dubious credibility,Footnote 113 but, when available, direct evidence of criminal intent when launching an attack makes prosecution most compelling. A commander or other attack decision maker whose illicit use of force is so conclusively established by admission – either contemporaneous with the decision or in the form of a post-attack statement – is certainly deserving of punishment. The reality, though, is that this will rarely be the case,Footnote 114 as it is not common for prosecutors to gain access to admissions of the intent to attack civilians or actual knowledge that launching an attack will result in an indiscriminate result.Footnote 115

Furthermore, even when available, such direct evidence may be insufficient to satisfy the burden of persuasion when considered within the broader context of the ‘totality of the circumstances’.Footnote 116 This is because the complexities of combat operations may dilute the probative value of such a statement.Footnote 117 A good example of this was the attack order issued by General Ante Gotovina and introduced against him in his trial before the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY).Footnote 118 That order directed his artillery commander to attack the city of Knin.Footnote 119 For the prosecution, this order seemed to provide near conclusive proof of an intent to attack civilians and civilian objects, as the entire city of Knin was obviously not itself a lawful military objective;Footnote 120 but other evidence placed that order into a broader and less incriminating context.Footnote 121 The artillery commander recounted that, prior to the attack, military objectives in the city had been identified and designated for artillery attack.Footnote 122 Accordingly, when he received the order, he understood it to direct that he place those designated targets under attack as previously planned.Footnote 123

Ultimately this indicates the evidentiary challenge of proving an intent to attack civilians or civilian objects and/or knowledge that an attack will result in an indiscriminate effect – the requisite subjective state of mind required to prove war crimes based on attack decisions. Absent direct evidence of those criminal mental states, prosecutors must rely almost exclusively on circumstantial evidence and the persuasiveness of the state of mind inferences supported by that evidence.Footnote 124 While there may be nothing remarkable about this in the broad context of criminal law, this does frame the critical question related to attack-based war crimes: where do the effects of such an attack fit into this equation?

When considering the totality of available evidence to establish the state of mind of someone accused of an unlawful attack decision, it would be illogical to exclude attack effects. Indeed, both the effects of the alleged illegal attack and the effects of other attacks ordered by the defendant are relevant in drawing inferences about the defendant's state of mind. However, while often highly persuasive, over-reliance on such effects creates the risk of shifting the culpability focus from the attack decision to the attack result.Footnote 125 This also fails to account for the fact that attack decisions involve a wide range of other relevant factors in assessing the defendant's state of mind at the time the attack was launched.Footnote 126 The Gotovina example above illustrates this point.Footnote 127 In isolation, the terms of the attack order, coupled with the fact that there was significant damage to civilian property, suggested an illegal attack decision.Footnote 128 When considered in the broader context, however, a reasonable alternative explanation emerged: that the attack had been intentionally directed against buildings and areas assessed as military objectives.Footnote 129

Accordingly, deliberation guidance that emphasises the importance of considering other aspects of circumstantial evidence in relation to attack effects would be useful in guiding the accountability judgement. Specifically, because the circumstantial evidence would have to prove either an intent to attack civilians or civilian property, or knowledge that the attack would result in clearly excessive indiscriminate effects, any such guidance must caution against treating attack effects as conclusive or near-conclusive evidence of guilt.Footnote 130 Instead, the inquiry should focus on how other circumstantial evidence related to the attack decision aligns with or contradicts the inference of criminal intent or knowledge; for example, evidence indicating that nothing in the nature of the target subjected to attack could plausibly have been assessed as a lawful military objective.Footnote 131

Such deliberative guidance should direct the inference inquiry towards common situational aspects that frame attack decisions. There may be cases where an attack inflicts civilian casualties and/or destruction of civilian property in an area with absolutely no objective indicia of military value. Those effects in that context, absent any other evidence to suggest a genuine mistake on the part of the defendant, could justify a singular reasonable inference: the attack was intended to inflict that harm.Footnote 132 Thus, while there are situations where circumstantial evidence derived from attack effects may provide near conclusive proof of an intent to launch an unlawful attack, this will be the case only where nothing supports an alternate rational inference that the attack may have been the result of an erroneous or mistaken judgement of legality, one resulting from the complexity of the combat situation.Footnote 133

Proving that an attack was launched with knowledge that it would result in a clearly excessive incidental effect on civilians and/or civilian property, based on an inference derived from the effects themselves, is even more complex.Footnote 134 This is because, unlike intentionally attacking civilians and/or civilian property, such an allegation presupposes the attack was launched at an actual military objective.Footnote 135 Accordingly, circumstantial evidence in the form of civilian casualties and/or destruction of civilian property should rarely, standing alone, be sufficient to satisfy the burden of persuasion.Footnote 136 This is because this offence requires proof beyond a reasonable doubt of a knowingly invalid judgement as to the permissible balance between anticipated military advantage and anticipated civilian risk.Footnote 137

More importantly, any finding that the attack decision maker launched the attack with such criminal knowledge demands some consideration of the military advantage component of the legality equation.Footnote 138 Accordingly, attack effects may certainly justify suspicion of such requisite criminal knowledge, but it is difficult to imagine they can be conclusive absent consideration of the totality of the value/risk equation.Footnote 139 Guilt would necessitate evidence that supports only one rational inference: the commander knew the military advantage derived from launching the attack would in no possible scenario ‘pay its way’ and justify the anticipated excessive incidental civilian harm.Footnote 140

Circumstantial evidence would play a critical role in any such assessment.Footnote 141 The objective disparity between the nature of the intended target and the manner of the attack compared with the expected harmful effects on civilians and civilian property should be the primary source of such evidence.Footnote 142 For example, a field kitchen serving an enemy unit would certainly qualify as a military objective.Footnote 143 If, however, the commander knew the field kitchen was located in an elementary school full of children and knew that the means and method of his planned attack would be likely to result in killing or wounding dozens of children, the imbalance between the concrete and direct anticipated military advantage and the anticipated civilian harm would justify a finding of knowledge of excessive effect.Footnote 144

In most cases, however, evidence of such obvious disparity is likely to be elusive.Footnote 145 This points to one ultimate conclusion: the burden of persuasion will require the prosecution to muster all available evidence related to the attack decision to meet the demanding burden of proof related to the attack decision.Footnote 146

4. A totality approach to assessing attack decisions

It seems relatively clear that proving that a defendant launched an attack intending to target civilians and/or civilian property, or an attack she knew would produce civilian harm that was clearly excessive in relation to the anticipated military advantage, is a daunting challenge. It seems equally clear that absent the unusual situation of a prosecutor being able to offer an admission from the defendant, circumstantial evidence and the inferences drawn therefrom will, by necessity, be the primary, if not exclusive, evidence of guilt.Footnote 147 Like all questions of evidentiary value, it is impossible to assign arbitrary weight to any single category of circumstantial evidence; that judgement is entrusted to the court (in the common law tradition, this is the function of the fact-finder responsible for determining the true facts, whether that fact-finder is a trial jury or a judge or panel of judges responsible for weighing evidence and determining guilt).Footnote 148 It is therefore useful to consider broad categories of circumstantial evidence that should be considered in assessing the requisite criminal state of mind related to an alleged unlawful attack decision. While, as noted above, attack effects are clearly included within this category, what follows is a proposed template for the presentation of other potentially probative categories related to this key issue.Footnote 149

4.1. The enemy situation

One of the most important sources of evidence related to assessing the legality of an attack decision is what the decision maker knew of the enemy situation, as it is the state of mind at the time the attack is conducted that is the focal point of the legality assessment.Footnote 150 It may be difficult to completely replicate that picture, but objective evidence of that situation must play a significant role in the fact-finding process.Footnote 151 Still, the highly contextual nature of any such information makes it essential that the fact finder exercises caution to avoid considering the actual instead of the reasonably perceived situation at the time of the attack.Footnote 152

Assessing such evidence is essential for a credible determination of guilt.Footnote 153 This is because there is really no object that is immune from being transformed into a military objective, and because whether a decision maker knew an attack would result in excessive civilian harm depends on the anticipated military advantage.Footnote 154

4.2. Precautionary measures

As noted above, there is no existing crime within the ICC's jurisdiction for failing to implement feasible precautions. Nonetheless, the implementation of such measures – or the omission to do so – provides significant insight into a commander's overall approach to civilian risk mitigation.Footnote 155 Implementation of such civilian risk mitigation measures is evidence of good faith commitment to IHL obligations.Footnote 156 While certainly not indisputable as to the assessment of guilt for launching an unlawful attack, the more extensively a commander implemented precautionary measures in relation to the alleged unlawful attack and in relation to overall operations, the less plausible it is to conclude that the commander acted with intent or knowledge to attack civilians or inflict clearly excessive civilian harm.Footnote 157

This evidence extends beyond the measures taken in relation to the alleged criminal attack. Instead, it includes all civilian risk mitigation measures implemented in relation to the preparation for and conduct of operations.Footnote 158 This would include evidence of training, command policies and procedures related to civilian risk mitigation, investigations into possible failures of mitigation efforts and incorporation of lessons learned into future operations, and the leveraging of available technologies to maximise the risk mitigation objective.Footnote 159

4.3. Evidence of patterns of conduct

Illegal attacks are rarely a ‘one-off’ in combat; a commander acting with the intent to kill or injure civilians, destroy civilian property, or the knowledge of inflicting a clearly excessive harmful effect on civilians is one who can be assumed to have virtually no regard for humanitarian obligations. It is therefore logical to expect that the conduct of operations under his or her command will include other incidents of suspected illegality or indifference to violations committed by subordinates.Footnote 160 Such evidence, even if insufficient to justify stand-alone charges, is probative in assessing whether an alleged illegal attack was the result of criminal intent or knowledge.Footnote 161

The circumstantial value of a pattern of prior criminal or wrongful acts, or modus operandi evidence, aids in the determination of whether the alleged criminal conduct was or was not set in motion by the requisite criminal intent or knowledge.Footnote 162 Where the defendant has engaged in such prior bad acts – especially when those bad acts share similar characteristics with the alleged crime – they suggest that the harmful effects were not the result of a mistake or accident but were indeed calculated to inflict the civilian harm.Footnote 163

4.4. Record of command interest in investigating alleged violations

How a commander responds to indications that subordinates violated IHL obligations and/or related command policies and directives is a reflection of the commander's overall commitment to compliance.Footnote 164 The very notion of ‘responsible command’ includes the obligation to set and enforce command standards through the integration of internal disciplinary processes.Footnote 165 Indeed, the very qualification as a ‘privileged’ belligerent – an individual entitled by international law to engage in hostilities – is contingent in part on being part of a unit subject to responsible command which respects the laws and customs of war.Footnote 166

When commanders ignore this duty to respond to indications of subordinate misconduct or, even worse, encourage or condone such misconduct, they violate their command obligation and set the conditions for future violations.Footnote 167 The doctrine of command responsibility subjects the commander to criminal responsibility for the foreseeable war crimes that result from such a dereliction of duty.Footnote 168 In the context of prosecuting a commander for an unlawful attack decision, such indifference or condoning of subordinate misconduct provides relevant insight into the commander's attitude and approach to the law.Footnote 169 When coupled with other evidence, this can bolster the inference of the requisite subjective criminal mental state related to an attack.Footnote 170

4.5. Motive

Motive is among the most common types of circumstantial evidence used to prove subjective intent or knowledge. Motive is not intent, but is rather the reason why a defendant engaged in certain actions.Footnote 171 In the context of war crimes, the relevance of an illicit motive – for example, to ‘cleanse’ an area of civilians or to terrorise the civilian population – may provide especially persuasive circumstantial evidence of criminal intent or knowledge.Footnote 172 Indeed, when such motive proves intent to target civilians or civilian property, or knowledge that an attack would produce clearly excessive civilian harm, guilt is established by proof of the decision to launch the attack regardless of the effects.Footnote 173 That a commander fails in such a situation to produce the intended result is no shield to criminal responsibility.Footnote 174 Thus, such an illicit motive would justify a charge and conviction even absent any death or injury to civilians or destruction of civilian property.Footnote 175

Such evidence of motive can come in a number of forms, to include evidence related to the overall strategic objectives of the operation.Footnote 176 Again, while not conclusive, motive should be emphasised as an important basis for inferring a defendant's state of mind related to attacks.

5. Conclusion

There is a substantial difference between information that warrants suspicion of war crimes based on violation of ‘targeting’ principles and proving such violations beyond a reasonable doubt. This is especially true for the war crimes within the jurisdiction of the ICC, proscribing unlawfully directing attacks against civilians and/or civilian property and launching indiscriminate attacks. This is because, unlike the standard of objective reasonableness at the foundation of the IHL targeting legality framework, these offences require proof of a subjective criminal mental state that actuates the proscribed conduct: intent to attack civilians and/or civilian property or knowledge that the attack will result in clearly excessive incidental injury to civilians and/or collateral damage to civilian property.

When attacks produce such results, it is tempting to assume that the attack must have been unlawful, but these offences are not defined in terms of result. Instead, it is the conduct of directing or launching the attack that is the proscribed criminal act. As a result, satisfying the burden of proof to convict a commander or other attack decision maker for such a crime requires proof that the decision to direct or launch the attack was actuated by the requisite subjective criminal mental state.

Proving each of these criminal mental states will almost inevitably necessitate reliance on circumstantial evidence and the inferences it supports. While attack effects certainly fall within this category of evidence, because these crimes are defined in terms of conduct and not result, it is dangerous to assume that effects alone establish guilt. Instead, attack effects are better understood as one category of circumstantial evidence within a totality equation that contributes to drawing inferences about the decision maker's state of mind at the time the attack was launched. Recognising the qualified probative value of such effects is important for two reasons. First, it guards against conclusions of illegal attack decisions based on an ‘after the fact’ assessment of results when the proper focus of inquiry is the assessment of the attack decision based on the situation that existed at the time the attack was launched. Second, it serves as a reminder that culpability for directing or launching an illegal attack is not contingent on the result of the harmful attack but on the criminal mental state of the decision maker at the time of the attack.

Ultimately, when assessing the legality of an attack, it is both logical and justified to rely on attack effects as the basis for reasonably suspecting attack-related war crimes. It will also, in some cases, be valid to rely on such effects to satisfy the prima facie burden of production in a criminal prosecution, as the infliction of civilian casualties and destruction of civilian property may justify at least a rational conclusion that the decision to attack was unlawful. However, it should rarely be the case that such effects, standing alone, satisfy the requirement to prove guilt beyond reasonable doubt, a burden that requires the proof to exclude all reasonable conclusions other than guilt. Relying exclusively on attack effects to satisfy this aspect of the burden of persuasion is dubious whenever there is any plausible basis to conclude that the decision was intended to attack a military objective, or that the decision was based on a good faith mistake as to the true nature of the target, the military advantage derived from the attack, or the risk of incidental injury and/or collateral damage.

Accordingly, whether assessing the reasonableness of an attack decision pursuant to the IHL objective standard or whether the attack was set in motion as the result of the criminal intent or knowledge standard of the ICC, its attack effects should be considered as only one factor in a broader category of relevant circumstantial evidence. This evidence includes all the information reasonably available to the commander at the time of the decision to attack, to include the enemy situation, civilian situation, implementation of feasible precautions, patterns of compliance or non-compliance, motive, and command commitment to imposing accountability for subordinate violations. All of these factors contribute to recreating the context of the attack decision, and yet it should be rare that any single category – to include attack effects – will justifiably be accorded indisputable value in determining the decision maker's state of mind at the time of the attack. Focusing the culpability assessment on this totality equation will enhance fundamental fairness in the criminal accountability process and encourage prosecutors to avoid the temptation of endorsing the invalid process of effects-based condemnations.Footnote 177

Acknowledgements

A special note of thanks to my research assistant, Nicholas LeFevre, Texas Tech University School of Law Class of 2023.

Funding statement

Not applicable.

Competing interests

The author declares none.

References

1 Barnes, Gwen P, ‘The International Criminal Court's Ineffective Enforcement Mechanisms: The Indictment of President Omar Al Bashir’ (2011) 34 Fordham International Law Journal 1584, 1619Google Scholar (highlighting the legitimacy concerns of the International Criminal Court (ICC) and the need to strengthen the Rome Statute in order to improve the ICC's perceived effectiveness in international forums. Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (entered into force 1 July 2002) 2187 UNTS 90.

2 ‘Statement of ICC Prosecutor, Karim AA Khan QC, on the Situation in Ukraine: Receipt of Referrals from 39 States Parties and the Opening of an Investigation’, 2 March 2022, https://www.icc-cpi.int/news/statement-icc-prosecutor-karim-aa-khan-qc-situation-ukraine-receipt-referrals-39-states.

3 ibid.

4 Freeman, Lindsay, ‘Law in Conflict: The Technological Transformation of War and Its Consequences for the International Criminal Court’ (2019) 51 New York University Journal of International Law and Politics 807, 840Google Scholar (explaining how the increase of user-created combat footage following the founding of YouTube has created ample opportunities for manipulation into propaganda).

5 ibid.

6 ibid 841 (‘Social media platforms are the perfect propaganda tools for war’); United Nations Meetings Coverage and Press Releases, ‘Ninety Per Cent of War-Time Casualties Are Civilians, Speakers Stress, Pressing Security Council to Fulfil Responsibility, Protect Innocent People in Conflicts’, 25 May 2022, https://press.un.org/en/2022/sc14904.doc.htm#:~:text=With%20civilians%20accounting%20for%20nearly,the%20field%20told%20the%2015%2D; Max Roser and others, ‘War and Peace’, Our World in Data, 2023, https://ourworldindata.org/war-and-peace.

7 Freeman (n 4) 840 (‘Today the current generation of [Information Communication Technologies] is quickly turning the conflicts in Syria and Iraq into the first social media wars, in which users generate photographs and videos of the war and post firsthand commentaries online, circumventing traditional media outlets and competing with state-sponsored narratives’).

8 ibid 840–41.

9 Corn, Geoffrey S, ‘Ensuring Experience Remains the Life of the Law: Incorporating Military Realities into the Process of War Crimes Accountability’ in Capaldo, Giuliana Ziccardi (ed), The Global Community: Yearbook of International Law and Jurisprudence (Oxford University Press 2014) vol I 189, 190Google Scholar (‘This “effects-based” focus, however, is inconsistent with fundamental tenets of the law, which demand reasonable combat judgments, which must be assessed contextually, not based on retrospective analysis’). See generally Corn, Geoffrey S, ‘Attack Decision-Making: Context, Reasonableness, and the Duty to Obey’ in Alcala, Ronald TP and Jensen, Eric Talbot (eds), The Impact of Emerging Technologies on the Law of Armed Conflict (Oxford University Press 2019) 325Google Scholar.

10 ibid; Chang, Karl S, ‘Enemy Status and Military Detention in the War Against Al-Qaeda’ (2011) 47 Texas International Law Journal 1, 78Google Scholar.

11 eg, Chang, ibid 7 (the law of war is ‘the body of international law that governs how warring parties fight’).

12 See generally Protocol Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and relating to the Protection of Victims of International Armed Conflicts (entered into force 7 December 1978) 1125 UNTS 3 (AP I).

13 ibid; Jean-Marie Henckaerts and Louise Doswald-Beck, Customary International Humanitarian Law, Vol I: Rules (International Committee of the Red Cross and Cambridge University Press 2005, revised 2009) rules 25, 46, 51.

14 AP I (n 12) art 48.

15 ibid.

16 ibid art 49.

17 ibid.

18 ibid.

19 ibid art 51.

20 ibid art 41; see also art 51(3).

21 Geoffrey Corn and Chris Jenks, ‘Two Sides of the Combatant Coin: Untangling Direct Participation in Hostilities from Belligerent Status in Non-International Armed Conflicts’ (2011) 33 University of Pennsylvania Journal of International Law 313, 316.

22 US Department of Defense, Law of War Manual’, June 2015, updated December 2016, para 4.3 (US DoD Law of War Manual).

23 Nils Melzer, Interpretive Guidance on the Notion of Direct Participation in Hostilities under International Humanitarian Law (2009) 71.

24 Corn and Jenks (n 21) 315–17.

25 ibid 316; Melzer (n 23) 27–36, (discussing the distinction of civilians, armed forces, and organised armed groups under the laws of armed conflict (LOAC), and the application of the CCF concept).

26 AP 1 (n 12) art 51; see also art 52.

27 ibid.

28 Geoffrey S Corn and James A Schoettler, Jr, ‘Targeting and Civilian Risk Mitigation: The Essential Role of Precautionary Measures’ (2015) 223 Military Law Review 785, 802.

29 Melzer (n 23) 35.

30 US Department of the Army, ‘FMI 3-07.22, Counterinsurgency Operations’, October 2004, para 2-50 (calling for the coordination of Army Special Operations Forces (ARSOF) operations in order to avoid potential unwanted casualties).

31 Bundesgerichtshof (BGH), Fuel Tankers Case, Decision, 16 Apr. 2010, III ZR 140/15 (Germany), http://juris.bundesgerichtshof.de/cgi-bin/rechtsprechung/document.py?Gericht=bgh&Art=en&sid=071de1999c01f5114ea9e467f0e843dd&nr=76401&pos=1&anz=2 (testing whether the commander refrained from acting ‘honestly’, ‘reasonably’, and ‘competently’).

32 Melzer (n 23) 74 (‘In case of doubt, the person in question must be presumed to be protected against direct attack’).

33 See generally Protocol Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and relating to the Protection of Victims of Non-International Armed Conflicts (Protocol II) (entered into force 7 December 1978) 1125 UNTS 609 (AP II).

34 ibid.

35 AP I (n 12) art 57.

36 ibid.

37 ibid.

38 ibid art 51.

39 ibid art 51(4).

40 ibid art 51.

41 ibid.

42 ibid.

43 ibid art 57.

44 ibid arts 50–57.

45 ibid art 57.

46 ibid art 51.

47 ibid art 57.

48 eg, Rome Statute (n 1) art 28 (‘A military commander … shall be criminally responsible for crimes within the jurisdiction of the Court committed by forces under his or her effective command or control’); Elements of Crimes, ICC Assembly of States Parties, 1st session, 3–10 September 2002, ICC-ASP/1/3 (Rome Statute Elements) 112, 146.

49 AP I (n 12) arts 48–49 (outlining the distinction between combatants and the civilian population as the basic requirement for parties in an armed conflict).

50 Rome Statute (n 1) art 28(a)(ii) (stating a military commander is criminally responsible when they ‘failed to take all necessary and reasonable measures within his or her power to prevent [crimes within the jurisdiction of the international criminal court]’).

51 eg, ibid arts 8(2)(a)(i) (demonstrating the result crime of wilful killing), (2)(b)(i) (demonstrating a conduct crime of intentionally directing attacks against the civilian population).

52 ibid art 8(2)(b)(i) (criminalising the intentional direction of attacks against civilians, but not requiring those acts be successful).

53 ibid art 8(2)(a)(i) (criminalising the killing of another with wilful intent).

54 ibid.

55 Rome Statute Elements (n 48) art 8(2)(a)(i).

56 ibid (‘The perpetrator killed one or more persons’).

57 eg, ibid art 8(2)(a)(ii)-1 (requiring proof of ‘severe physical or mental pain or suffering’ to prove the crime of torture), art 8(2)(a)(ii)-3 (requiring proof of a person being subjected to a particular biological experiment to prove the crime of illegal biological experiments).

58 ibid arts 8(2)(b)(i)–(xxvi).

59 Compare ibid with AP I (n 12) arts 48–49 (outlining the distinction between combatants and the civilian population as the basic requirement for parties in an armed conflict).

60 Rome Statute Elements (n 48) arts 8(2)(b)(i)–(iii).

61 ibid.

62 ibid art 8(2)(b)(i).

63 ibid art 8(2)(e).

64 ibid.

65 ibid art 8(2)(b)(iv).

66 ibid.

67 ibid.

68 ibid.

69 ibid.

70 Rome Statute (n 1) art 28 (placing criminal liability on military commanders whose forces commit crimes within the jurisdiction of the ICC); ibid (defining attacks that inflict clearly excessive civilian death, injury, or destruction of civilian property as a crime within the jurisdiction of the ICC).

71 Rome Statute Elements (n 48) art 8(2)(b)(iv).

72 ibid.

73 ibid.

74 ibid.

75 ibid art 8(2)(b)(iv).

76 Rome Statute (n 1) art 28(a) (holding that military commanders must ‘take all necessary and reasonable measures within his or her power to prevent or repress’); art 28(b) (requiring superiors to also take necessary and reasonable measures).

77 ibid.

78 Corn and Schoettler (n 28) 818.

79 ibid 802, 842.

80 Compare ibid with Rome Statute (n 1) art 28(a), (b).

81 Rome Statute (n 1) art 28(a) (on the criminal responsibility faced by commanders if they fail to maintain effective authority and control over their subordinates).

82 Rome Statute Elements (n 48) arts 8(2)(b)(i)–(iii).

83 ibid.

84 ibid; Rome Statute (n 1) art 28; AP I (n 12) art 57 (‘In the conduct of military operations, constant care shall be taken to spare the civilian population, civilians[,] and civilian objects’).

85 Rome Statute (n 1) art 28.

86 AP I (n 12) art 80 (‘The … Parties to the conflict shall without delay take all necessary measures for the execution of their obligations under the Conventions and this Protocol’).

87 eg, Uniform Code of Military Justice (2019) (US), art 119 (placing criminal accountability for reckless manslaughter).

88 ibid (stating reckless manslaughter requires an unintentional killing of a human being).

89 ibid.

90 ibid art 114 (on reckless endangerment); art 92 (on dereliction of duty).

91 Compare ibid (demonstrating a result-based violation premised on the killing of another) with Rome Statute Elements (n 48) art 8(2)(b)(i) (demonstrating a result-based violation premised on directing an attack).

92 Uniform Code of Military Justice (n 87) art 119.

93 Rome Statute Elements (n 48) art 8(2)(b)(i).

94 ibid.

95 John Calvin Jeffries Jr and Paul B Stephan III, ‘Defenses, Presumptions, and Burden of Proof in the Criminal Law’ (1979) 88 Yale Law Journal 1325, 1327–9.

96 John T McNaughton, ‘Burden of Production of Evidence: A Function of a Burden of Persuasion’ (1955) 68 Harvard Law Review 1382, 1383.

97 Deborah W Denno, ‘Criminal Law in a Post-Freudian World’ (2005) University of Illinois Law Review 601, 691–92.

98 AP 1 (n 12) art 51.

99 McNaughton (n 96) 1382–83 (for a general overview of how to satisfy the burdens of production and persuasion).

100 ibid 1383.

101 ibid.

102 The US military goes through a ‘collateral damage methodology’ before conducting a targeted attack: Gregory S McNeal, ‘Targeted Killing and Accountability’ (2014) 102 Georgetown Law Journal 681, 740. Encompassing military intelligence, weapons-effect data, and on-the-ground analysis, collateral damage methodology ensures that decision makers address proportionality issues before launching an attack: ibid 744. However, even this process does not wholly eliminate collateral damage: ibid 754. Of the operations that followed a collateral damage methodology, 1% resulted in collateral damage as a result of issues of misidentification, weapons malfunction, or human error: ibid. Thus, a decision maker could not anticipate collateral damage when launching an attack, yet still suffer collateral loss arising from the fog of war: ibid.

103 McNaughton (n 96) 1382–83.

104 ibid.

105 Luke Meier, ‘Probability, Confidence, and the “Reasonable Jury” Standard’ (2015) 84 Mississippi Law Journal 747, 753.

106 Meier, ibid 755 (‘In this sense, direct and circumstantial evidence are similar in that they both require a jury to evaluate what really happened at a particular location and at a particular time based solely on information provided in a different location (namely, a courtroom) at a later point in time (the trial)’).

107 ibid.

108 Department of the Army, ‘Military Judges’ Benchbook’, Dept of the Army Pamphlet 27-9, 29 February 2020, 7–3, https://armypubs.army.mil/epubs/DR_pubs/DR_a/pdf/web/ARN21189_P27_9_FINAL.pdf#page=1778.

109 Rome Statute (n 1) art 28; Rome Statute Elements (n 48) art 8(2)(b)(iv) (‘The perpetrator knew the attack would cause incidental death or injury to civilians or damage to civilian objects … of such an extent as to be clearly excessive in relation to the concrete and direct overall military advantage anticipated’).

110 Albert W Alschuler, ‘Plea Bargaining and Its History’ (1979) 79 Columbia Law Review 1, 30–31 (stating that the historical increase in plea bargaining came as a way to dispense with difficult cases to try).

111 ibid.

112 ibid.

113 McNeal (n 102) 755–58 (outlining the many difficulties in providing accountability with targeted strikes in Pakistan).

114 ibid.

115 ibid.

116 Major Gen Walter B Huffman, ‘Margin of Error: Potential Pitfalls of the Ruling in The Prosecutor v. Ante Gotovina’ (2012) 211 Military Law Review 1, 8 (where direct evidence of a removal plan regarding the Krajina Serbs was not necessarily dispositive when the court considered the totality of the circumstances).

117 ibid 46 (‘The law of war does not ask the impossible of battlefield commanders; nor does it unfairly disadvantage armies that lack the technological capabilities of the most advanced nations. It requires only that commanders act in good faith to do all within their capabilities and limitations to minimise civilian casualties while accomplishing their mission’).

118 ibid 7–11.

119 ibid 10.

120 ibid 7.

121 ibid 9.

122 ibid 9–10.

123 ibid 9.

124 Denno (n 97) 692.

125 eg Huffman (n 116) 8–9 (detailing the many factors that led to Gotovina's decision).

126 ibid.

127 ibid.

128 ibid 7–9.

129 ibid.

130 Meier (n 105) 754–56; Rome Statute Elements (n 48) arts 8(2)(b)(iv).

131 Rome Statute Elements (n 48) art 8(2)(b)(iv).

132 Meier (n 105) 753 (‘Circumstantial evidence … is evidence that, if believed by the jury, does not “directly prove” the material fact to the litigation, but rather supplies an inference that the material fact occurred’); McNeal (n 102) 740–44 (showing that evidence can be secured by looking at the state's decision-making process).

133 McNeal (n 102) 755–58 (outlining the many difficulties to provide accountability with targeted strikes in Pakistan).

134 ibid.

135 Rome Statute Elements (n 48) art 8(2)(b)(iv)(3) (‘The perpetrator knew that the [collateral effects] … would be of such an extent as to be clearly excessive in relation to the concrete and direct overall military advantage anticipated’).

136 ibid.

137 ibid.

138 ibid.

139 ibid.

140 eg, Huffman (n 116) 8–9 (detailing the many factors that often lead to a command decision).

141 ibid.

142 McNeal (n 102) 740–44 (showing the objective evidence that states use during the decision-making process).

143 ibid.

144 ibid.

145 ibid.

146 ibid.

147 Denno (n 97) 691.

148 ibid 691–92.

149 ibid 692.

150 Geoffrey S Corn and Lieutenant Colonel Gary P Corn, ‘The Law of Operational Targeting: Viewing the LOAC through an Operational Lens’ (2012) 47 Texas International Law Journal 337, 375 (‘But we are obliged to judge the situation as it appeared to the defendant at the time. If the facts were such as would justify the action by the exercise of judgment, after giving consideration to all the factors and existing possibilities, even though the conclusion reached may have been faulty, it cannot be said to be said to be criminal’).

151 ibid.

152 ibid.

153 ibid.

154 Rome Statute Elements (n 48) art 8(2)(b)(iv)(3).

155 McNeal (n 102) 740–44 (showing the objective evidence that states use during the decision-making process, including civilian risk management).

156 Corn and Corn (n 150) 375.

157 Emphasising the probative value of precautionary measures in the war crimes accountability equation might also produce a positive second order effect: incentivising consideration and implementation of such precautions: ibid.

158 eg, McNeal (n 102) 740–44.

159 ibid.

160 eg, Weiner, Justus Reid and Bell, Avi, ‘The Gaza War of 2009: Applying International Humanitarian Law to Israel and Hamas’ (2009) 11 San Diego International Law Journal 5, 10Google Scholar (explaining that each of the 10,000 rockets and mortars fired during the 2009 war was a war crime).

161 ibid.

162 George Blum and others, American Jurisprudence 2d, Evidence (2d edn, Lawyers Cooperative Publishing 2019) s 396.

163 ibid.

164 Rome Statute (n 1) art 28.

165 ibid.

166 Hague Convention (IV) respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land and its Annex: Regulations concerning the Laws and Customs of War on Land (entered into force 26 January 1910) Martens Nouveau Recueil (ser 3) 461, art 1.

167 Rome Statute (n 1) art 28.

168 ibid.

169 ibid.

170 ibid.

171 For example, this Wisconsin jury instruction notes that ‘[i]ntent should not be confused with motive. While proof of intent is necessary to a conviction, proof of motive is not. “Motive” refers to a person's reason for doing something. While motive may be shown as a circumstance to aid in establishing the guilt of a defendant, the State is not required to prove motive on the part of a defendant in order to convict. Evidence of motive does not by itself establish guilt. You should give it the weight you believe it deserves under all of the circumstances’: see WIS JI-CRIMINAL, 923A, https://wilawlibrary.gov/jury/files/criminal/0923A.pdf.

172 ‘Motive’, Black's Law Dictionary (11th edn, 2019).

173 Rome Statute Elements (n 48) art 8(2)(b)(i), (ii).

174 ibid.

175 ibid.

176 eg, McNeal (n 102) 740–44.

177 Médecins Sans Frontières, press release, ‘Initial Reaction to Public Release of U.S. Military Investigative Report on the Attack on MSF Trauma Hospital’, 29 April 2016, https://www.msf.org/kunduz-initial-reaction-public-release-us-military-investigative-report-attack-msf-trauma-hospital; US Central Command, press release, ‘CENTCOM Releases Investigation into Airstrike on Doctors Without Borders Trauma Center’, 29 April 2016, https://www.centcom.mil/MEDIA/PRESS-RELEASES/Press-Release-View/Article/904574/april-29-centcom-releases-investigation-into-airstrike-on-doctors-without-borde; Huffman (n 116) 7–9 (relying on attack effects to determine guilt); ICTY, Prosecutor v Ante Gotovina and Mladen Markač, Judgment, IT-06-90-A, Appeals Chamber, 16 November 2012 (reversing the conviction based on a failure to prove guilt based on the totality of the circumstances).