Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-l4ctd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-25T21:02:23.106Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Linear equivalence of scattered metric spaces

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 May 2023

Jan Baars*
Affiliation:
971 Bukit Timah Road, 06-22 Floridian, 589647 Singapore, Singapore
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Let $\alpha < \omega _1$ be a prime component, and let $X$ and $Y$ be metric spaces. In [8], it was shown that if $C_p(X)$ and $C_p(Y)$ are linearly homeomorphic, then the scattered heights $\kappa (X)$ and $\kappa (Y)$ of $X$ and $Y$ satisfy $\kappa (X) \leq \alpha $ if and only if $\kappa (Y) \leq \alpha $. We will prove that this also holds if $C_p^*(X)$ and $C_p^*(Y)$ are linearly homeomorphic and that these results do not hold for arbitrary Tychonov spaces. We will also prove that if $C_p^*(X)$ and $C_p^*(Y)$ are linearly homeomorphic, then $\kappa (X) < \alpha $ if and only if $\kappa (Y) < \alpha $, which was shown in [9] for $\alpha = \omega $. This last statement is not always true for linearly homeomorphic $C_p(X)$ and $C_p(Y)$. We will show that if $\alpha = \omega ^{\mu }$ where $\mu < \omega _1$ is a successor ordinal, it is true, but for all other prime components, this is not the case. Finally, we will prove that if $C_p^*(X)$ and $C_p^*(Y)$ are linearly homeomorphic, then $X$ is scattered if and only if $Y$ is scattered. This result does not directly follow from the above results. We will clarify why the results for linearly homeomorphic spaces $C_p^*(X)$ and $C_p^*(Y)$ do require a different and more complex approach than the one that was used for linearly homeomorphic spaces $C_p(X)$ and $C_p(Y)$.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Canadian Mathematical Society

1 Introduction

For a Tychonov space $X$ , we define $C(X)$ to be the set of real-valued continuous functions in $X$ and $C^*(X)$ to be the subset of bounded functions in $C(X)$ . If we endow $C(X)$ and $C^*(X)$ with the topology of pointwise convergence, we denote that by $C_p(X)$ and $C_p^*(X)$ . These function spaces are topological vector spaces that are dense subspaces of $\mathbb {R}^X$ . We define spaces $X$ and $Y$ to be $l_p$ -equivalent if $C_p(X)$ and $C_p(Y)$ are linearly homeomorphic and $l_p^*$ -equivalent if $C_p^*(X)$ and $C_p^*(Y)$ are linearly homeomorphic. Function spaces with the topology of pointwise convergence have been widely investigated. For the results achieved, we refer to [Reference Arhangel’skii2, Reference Baars and de Groot8, Reference van Mill15, Reference Tkachuk18Reference Tkachuk21].

In this paper, we will focus on linear homeomorphisms between function spaces of metric spaces and the linear equivalence of the scattered height of the underlying spaces. For a scattered metric space $X$ , $\kappa (X)$ denotes the scattered height of $X$ (see Section 2 for a formal definition). The following result for $l_p$ -equivalent metric spaces can be found in [Reference Baars and de Groot8, Theorem 4.1.15].

Theorem 1.1 Let $\alpha < \omega _1$ be a prime component, and let $X$ and $Y$ be $l_p$ -equivalent metric spaces. Then $\kappa (X) \leq \alpha $ if and only if $\kappa (Y) \leq \alpha $ .

The notion of “support,” introduced in [Reference Arhangel’skii1] by Arhangel’skii, was very important in proving results for $l_p$ -equivalent spaces. In particular, Lemmas 2.2 and 2.3 in the next section formulate properties of the support function that were key in the proof of Theorem 1.1. Although the support function is also defined for continuous linear functions $\phi : C_p^*(X) \to C_p^*(Y)$ , both Lemmas 2.2 and 2.3 are not true in this case. Therefore, a different approach is required to derive the equivalent of Theorem 1.1, for $l_p^*$ -equivalent spaces. For this, the notion of $\varepsilon $ -supported sets and Lemma 2.5, the alternative for Lemma 2.3, were introduced in [Reference Baars, de Groot and Pelant10]. In addition to that, we also need an alternative for Lemma 2.2. For the purposes of this paper, it will turn out that Lemma 2.8 suffices as that alternative (see Section 2 for more details). These are amongst the essential ingredients to prove the following 30-year-old problem (see [Reference Baars, de Groot, van Mill and Pelant9] or [Reference Baars and de Groot8], Conjecture 4.6.8).

Theorem 1.2 Let $\alpha < \omega _1$ be a prime component, and let $X$ and $Y$ be $l_p^*$ -equivalent metric spaces. Then:

  1. (a) $\kappa (X) \leq \alpha $ if and only if $\kappa (Y) \leq \alpha $ .

  2. (b) $\kappa (X) < \alpha $ if and only if $\kappa (Y) < \alpha $ .

We will also show, for metric spaces $X$ and $Y$ , that if $C_p^*(X)$ and $C_p^*(Y)$ are linearly homeomorphic, then $X$ is scattered if and only if $Y$ is scattered. Since Theorem 1.2 will only be derived in this paper for $\alpha < \omega _1$ , this result does not directly follow from it.

Theorem 1.2(a) shows that Theorem 1.1 also holds for $l_p^*$ -equivalent spaces. In [Reference Baars, de Groot, van Mill and Pelant9], Theorem 1.2(b) was proved for $\alpha = \omega $ and, therefore, Theorem 1.2(b) generalizes this result for all prime components. The proof in [Reference Baars, de Groot, van Mill and Pelant9] for $\alpha = \omega $ made use of techniques that seem to be unsuitable for the general case. The techniques in this paper also provide an alternative proof of the original result for $\alpha = \omega $ .

Theorem 1.2(b) shows that $C_p^*([1,\omega ^2))$ and $C_p^*([1, \omega ^{\omega }))$ are not linearly homeomorphic, where $[1,\alpha )$ is the ordinal space $\{\beta : 1 \leq \beta <\alpha \}$ with the order topology. However by the classification results in [Reference Baars and de Groot6], $C_p([1,\omega ^2))$ and $C_p([1, \omega ^{\omega }))$ are linearly homeomorphic which shows that Theorem 1.2(b) cannot always be true for $l_p$ -equivalent metric spaces. One might think that for $l_p$ -equivalent metric spaces, Theorem 1.2(b) is not true for all prime components $\alpha < \omega _1$ . In this paper, we will show this is not the case. For $l_p$ -equivalent metric spaces, it is true for some prime components $\alpha < \omega _1$ but not for all.

Theorem 1.3 Let $0< \alpha < \omega _1$ be a prime component, and let $X$ and $Y$ be $l_p$ -equivalent metric spaces.

  1. (a) If $\alpha = \omega ^{\mu }$ with $\mu = 0$ or $\mu $ a limit ordinal, then $\kappa (X) < \alpha $ if and only if $\kappa (Y) < \alpha $ .

  2. (b) For all other $\alpha $ , $\kappa (X) < \alpha $ if and only if $\kappa (Y) < \alpha $ is not always true.

We will conclude this paper by showing that Theorems 1.1 and 1.2(a) do not hold for arbitrary Tychonov spaces, but that it remains an open question whether this is the case for Theorems 1.2(b) and 1.3(a).

2 The support function

Let $X$ and $Y$ be Tychonov spaces, and let $\phi : C_p(X)\rightarrow C_p(Y)$ be a continuous linear function. For $y \in Y$ , the map $\psi _y: C_p(X)\rightarrow \mathbb {R}$ defined by $\psi _y (f)= \phi (f)(y)$ is continuous and linear. This means $\psi _y \in L(X)$ , the dual space of $C_p(X)$ . Since the evaluation mappings $\xi _x$ ( $x \in X$ ) defined by $\xi _x (f) = f(x)$ for $f \in C_p(X)$ form a Hamel basis for $L(X)$ , there are $x_1, \ldots , x_n \in X$ and $\lambda _{x_1}^y, \ldots , \lambda _{x_n}^y \in \mathbb {R} \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt \{0\}$ such that $\psi _y = \sum _{i=1}^{n}\lambda _{x_i}^y \xi _{x_i}$ . This means that for every $f \in C_p(X)$ , $\phi (f)(y) = \sum _{i=1}^{n}\lambda _{x_i}^y f(x_i)$ . We define the support of $y$ to be $\{x_1, \ldots , x_n \}$ and we denote that by $\textrm {supp}_{\phi }(y)$ or simply by $\textrm {supp}(y)$ if the subscript can be omitted without confusion. For $B \subseteq Y$ , we denote $\bigcup _{y \in B} \textrm {supp}(y)$ by $\textrm {supp}_{\phi }(B)$ or $\textrm {supp} (B)$ . The following lemma is well known (see [Reference van Mill15, Lemma 6.8.2]).

Lemma 2.1 Let $X$ and $Y$ be Tychonov spaces, let $\phi : C_p(X)\rightarrow C_p(Y)$ be a continuous linear function, and let $y \in Y$ .

  1. (a) If $f,g \in C_p(X)$ coincide on $\mathrm{supp}_{\phi }(y)$ , then $\phi (f)(y) = \phi (g)(y)$ .

  2. (b) If $\phi $ is a homeomorphism, then $y \in \mathrm{supp}_{\phi ^{-1}}(\mathrm{supp}_{\phi }(y))$ .

Similarly, the support function can be defined for continuous linear functions between $C_p^*(X)$ and $C_p^*(Y)$ and Lemma 2.1 holds for continuous linear functions $\phi : C_p^*(X)\rightarrow C_p^*(Y)$ . For more information on the support function, we refer to [Reference Baars and de Groot8] and [Reference van Mill15, Chapter 6].

The following two lemmas were key in the proof of Theorem 1.1.

Lemma 2.2 [Reference Arhangel’skii1]

Let $X$ and $Y$ be Tychonov spaces, and let $\phi : C_p(X)\rightarrow C_p(Y)$ be a continuous linear function. If $A \subseteq Y$ is bounded, then $\mathrm{supp}(A) \subseteq X$ is bounded.

Lemma 2.3 [Reference Baars and de Groot7]

Let $X$ and $Y$ be normal spaces, and let $\phi : C_p(X)\to C_p(Y)$ be a continuous linear function. Let $\mathcal {V}$ be a locally finite family of open sets in $X$ , and let $y_0 \in Y$ be of countable character. Then there are a neighborhood $U$ of $y_0$ and a finite subset $\mathcal {W} \subseteq \mathcal {V}$ such that $\mathrm{supp}(U) \cap \bigcup \{V \in \mathcal {V}: V \notin \mathcal {W} \}= \emptyset $ .

Examples in [Reference Baars and de Groot8, Reference Baars, van Mill and Tkachuk12] show that both Lemmas 2.2 and 2.3 do not hold for continuous linear functions $\phi : C_p^*(X)\rightarrow C_p^*(Y)$ . Therefore, a new approach is required to prove Theorem 1.2. For continuous linear functions $\phi : C_p^*(X)\rightarrow C_p^*(Y)$ , $\varepsilon $ -supported sets and an alternative for Lemma 2.3 were introduced in [Reference Baars, de Groot and Pelant10].

Let $X$ and $Y$ be Tychonov spaces, and let $\phi : C_p^*(X)\to C_p^*(Y)$ be a continuous linear function. Let $A \subseteq X$ , $B \subseteq Y$ and $\varepsilon> 0$ . We define $B$ to be $\varepsilon $ -supported on $A$ if for each $y \in B$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} \sum \{ | \lambda_x^y | : x \in \textrm{supp}(y) \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt A \} < \varepsilon. \end{align*} $$

The following lemma is straightforward.

Lemma 2.4 Let $X$ and $Y$ be Tychonov spaces, and let $\phi : C_p^*(X)\to C_p^*(Y)$ be a continuous linear function. Let $A \subseteq X$ , $B \subseteq Y$ and $\varepsilon> 0$ be such that $B$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $A$ .

  1. (a) If $D \subseteq B$ , then $D$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $A$ .

  2. (b) If $A \subseteq C$ , then $B$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $C$ .

  3. (c) If $\delta> 0$ and $C \subseteq X$ are such that $B$ is $\delta $ -supported on $C$ , then $B$ is $\varepsilon + \delta $ -supported on $A \cap C.$

  4. (d) If $D \subseteq Y$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $A$ , then $B \cup D $ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $A.$

The next lemma on $\varepsilon $ -supported sets can be found in [Reference Baars, de Groot and Pelant10]. This lemma is the alternative for Lemma 2.3 that we need in the proof of Theorem 1.2.

Lemma 2.5 Let $X$ and $Y$ be metric spaces, and let $\phi : C_p^*(X)\to C_p^*(Y)$ be a continuous linear function. Let $\mathcal {V}$ be a locally finite family of open sets in $X$ , and let $y \in Y$ . For every $\varepsilon>0$ , there are a neighborhood $U$ of $y$ and a finite subset $\mathcal {W} \subseteq \mathcal {V}$ such that $U$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $\bigcup \mathcal {W} \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt \bigcup \mathcal {V})$ .

We need the following corollary to Lemma 2.5.

Corollary 2.6 Let $X$ and $Y$ be metric spaces, and let $\phi : C_p^*(X)\to C_p^*(Y)$ be a continuous linear function. Let $\mathcal {V}$ be a locally finite family of open sets in $X$ , and let $K \subseteq Y$ be compact. For every $\varepsilon>0$ , there is a finite subset $\mathcal {W} \subseteq \mathcal {V}$ such that $K$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $\bigcup \mathcal {W} \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt \bigcup \mathcal {V})$ .

Proof For every $y \in K$ , there are, by Lemma 2.5, a neighborhood $U_y \subseteq Y$ of $y$ and a finite subset $\mathcal {W}_y \subseteq \mathcal {V}$ such that $U_y$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $\bigcup \mathcal {W}_y \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt \bigcup \mathcal {V})$ . Since $K$ is compact, there is a finite subset $F \subseteq K$ such that $K \subseteq \bigcup \{U_y: y \in F \}$ . Let $\mathcal {W} = \bigcup \{\mathcal {W}_y: y \in F \}$ . Then $\mathcal {W}$ is a finite subset of $\mathcal {V}$ . Let $y \in F$ . Since $U_y$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $\bigcup \mathcal {W}_y \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt \bigcup \mathcal {V})$ , we have by Lemma 2.4(b), $U_y$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $\bigcup \mathcal {W} \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt \bigcup \mathcal {V})$ . Then, by Lemma 2.4(d), $\bigcup \{U_y: y \in F \}$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $\bigcup \mathcal {W} \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt \bigcup \mathcal {V})$ , and hence, by Lemma 2.4(a), $K$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $\bigcup \mathcal {W} \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt \bigcup \mathcal {V})$ .

For a Tychonov space $X$ and an ordinal $\alpha $ , we define $X^{(\alpha )}$ , the $\alpha $ th derivative of $X$ by transfinite induction as follows:

  1. (a) $X^{(0)}=X$ and $X^{(1)}=\{x \in X : x \text { is an accumulation point of } X \}$ .

  2. (b) If $\alpha $ is a successor, say $\alpha = \beta +1$ , then $X^{(\alpha )}= (X^{(\beta )})^{(1)}$ .

  3. (c) If $\alpha $ is a limit ordinal, then $X^{(\alpha )}= \bigcap _{\beta < \alpha } X^{(\beta )}$ .

For each ordinal $\alpha $ , $X^{(\alpha )}$ is a closed subset of $X$ . A Tychonov space $X$ is defined to be scattered if there exists an ordinal $\alpha $ such that $X^{(\alpha )} = \emptyset $ . The scattered height $\kappa (X)$ of a scattered space $X$ is defined to be the smallest ordinal $\alpha $ such that $X^{(\alpha )} = \emptyset $ .

Theorem 2.7 [Reference Semadeni16, Theorem 8.5.2 and Proposition 8.5.5]

Let $X$ be a topological space. Then there exists an ordinal $\alpha $ such that $X^{(\alpha )} = X^{(\alpha +1)}$ . For this $\alpha $ , $X^{(\alpha )}$ is closed and dense in itself and $X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt X^{(\alpha )}$ is scattered. In particular, $X$ is scattered if and only if $X^{(\alpha )} = \emptyset $ . Moreover, if $X$ is second countable and scattered, then it is countable.

As mentioned in the introduction, Lemma 2.2 does not hold for continuous linear functions $\phi : C_p^*(X)\to C_p^*(Y)$ . Instead, we will use the following lemma in the proof of Theorem 1.2.

Lemma 2.8 Let $X$ and $Y$ be metric spaces, and let $\phi : C_p^*(X)\to C_p^*(Y)$ be a continuous linear function. Let $A \subseteq X$ be closed and scattered. Then, for every $K \subseteq Y$ compact and $\varepsilon> 0,$ there is $L \subseteq A$ compact such that $K$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt A)$ .

Proof Let $\kappa (A) = \alpha $ . We will prove the lemma by transfinite induction on $\alpha $ . For $\alpha =0,$ we have $A = \emptyset $ . Then, for $L = \emptyset $ , the lemma follows. For $\alpha> 0$ , assume the lemma is true for every $\beta < \alpha $ .

First, suppose that $\alpha $ is a limit ordinal. Since $A^{(\alpha )} = \emptyset $ , the family $\mathcal {V} = \{X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt A^{(\beta )}: \beta < \alpha \}$ is an open cover of $X$ . Let $\mathcal {U}$ be a locally finite open cover of $X$ such that $\{\overline {U}: U \in \mathcal {U}\}$ refines $\mathcal {V}$ . By Corollary 2.6, there is a finite subset $\mathcal {W} \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ such that $K$ is $\varepsilon /2$ -supported on $\bigcup \mathcal {W}$ . Let $F = \bigcup \{\overline {U}: U \in \mathcal {W}\} \cap A$ . Then $F$ is closed and since $\mathcal {W}$ is finite, there is $\beta < \alpha $ such that $F \subseteq A \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt A^{(\beta )}$ . This implies $F^{(\beta )} = \emptyset $ , hence $F$ is scattered. By the induction hypothesis, there is $L \subseteq F$ compact such that $K$ is $\varepsilon /2$ -supported on $L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F)$ . Note that $(L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F)) \cap \bigcup W \subseteq L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt A)$ . So, by Lemma 2.4(b) and (c), the set $K$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt A)$ .

Second, suppose that $\alpha = \beta +1$ is a successor ordinal. Since $A^{(\alpha )} = \emptyset $ and $A$ is closed, $A^{(\beta )}$ is a closed and discrete subset of $X$ . Then $\mathcal {V} = \{X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt G: G \subseteq A^{(\beta )} \textrm { cofinite} \}$ is an open cover of $X$ . Let $\mathcal {U}$ be a locally finite open cover of $X$ such that $\{\overline {U}: U \in \mathcal {U}\}$ refines $\mathcal {V}$ . By Corollary 2.6, there is a finite subset $\mathcal {W} \subseteq \mathcal {U}$ such that $K$ is $\varepsilon /2$ -supported on $\bigcup \mathcal {W}$ . Let $F = \bigcup \{\overline {U}: U \in \mathcal {W}\} \cap A$ . Then $F$ is closed and since $\mathcal {W}$ is finite, there is $G \subseteq A^{(\beta )}$ cofinite such that $F \subseteq A \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt G$ . This implies that $F^{(\beta )} = F \cap A^{(\beta )}$ is finite.

Let $\{U_n:n \in \mathbb {N}\}$ be an open neighborhood base of $F^{(\beta )}$ in $X$ such that for every $n \in \mathbb {N}$ , $\overline {U}_{n+1} \subseteq U_n$ . Let $(\varepsilon _n)_{n \in \mathbb {N}}$ be a sequence of positive numbers such that $\sum _{n=1}^{\infty } \varepsilon _n = \varepsilon /2$ . For every $n \in \mathbb {N}$ , let $F_n = F \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt U_n$ . Then $F_n$ is closed in $X$ , $F_{n-1} \subseteq F_n$ and $F_n^{(\beta )} = \emptyset $ . Hence, by the induction hypothesis, there is $L_n \subseteq F_n$ compact such that $K$ is $\varepsilon _n$ -supported on $L_n \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F_n)$ . For $n \in \mathbb {N}$ , we inductively define $\widehat {L}_n$ by $\widehat {L}_1 =L_1$ and for $n>1$ , $\widehat {L}_n = \widehat {L}_{n-1} \cup (L_n \cap \overline {U_{n-1}})$ . Note that $L_n \cap \overline {U_{n-1}} \subseteq L_n$ , $\widehat {L}_n \subseteq F_n$ and $\widehat {L}_n$ is compact.

Claim 1 For every $n \in \mathbb {N}$ , $K$ is $\sum _{m=1}^n \varepsilon _m$ -supported on $\widehat {L}_n \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F_n)$ .

We will prove the claim by induction on $n$ . Clearly the claim holds for $n=1$ . Let $n>1$ and assume that the claim holds for every $m < n$ . By the induction hypothesis, the set $K$ is $\sum _{m=1}^{n-1} \varepsilon _m$ -supported on $\widehat {L}_{n-1} \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F_{n-1})$ . We also have that $K$ is $\varepsilon _n$ -supported on $L_n \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F_n)$ . Since

$$ \begin{align*} (\widehat{L}_{n-1} \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F_{n-1})) \cap (L_n \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F_n)) \subseteq \widehat{L}_n \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F_n), \end{align*} $$

we have by Lemma 2.4(b) and (c) that $K$ is $\sum _{m=1}^n \varepsilon _m$ -supported on $\widehat {L}_n \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F_n)$ . This proves the claim.

Let $L = \bigcup _{n=1}^{\infty } \widehat {L}_n \cup F^{(\beta )}$ .

Claim 2

  1. (a) For every $n \in \mathbb {N}$ , $L \cap F_n = \widehat {L}_n \cup ((\widehat {L}_{n+1} \cap \overline {U_n})\kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt U_n)$ .

  2. (b) $L \subseteq F$ is compact.

  3. (c) $K$ is $\varepsilon /2$ -supported on $L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F)$ .

Clearly $\widehat {L}_n \subseteq L \cap F_n$ and $(\widehat {L}_{n+1} \cap \overline {U_n})\kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt U_n \subseteq L \cap F_n$ . Let $x \in L \cap F_n$ . Since $F_n \cap F^{(\beta )} = \emptyset $ , we have $x \in \bigcup _{n=1}^{\infty } \widehat {L}_n$ . Let $m = \min \{k \in \mathbb {N}: x \in \widehat {L}_k\}$ . Then $x \in F_m$ and hence $x \notin U_m$ . If $m \leq n$ , then $x \in \widehat {L}_m \subseteq \widehat {L}_n$ and we are done. If $m>n$ , then $x \notin \widehat {L}_{m-1}$ and hence $x \in L_m \cap \overline {U_{m-1}}$ . If $m-1>n$ , then $\overline {U_{m-1}} \subseteq U_n$ . Since $x \in F_n$ , we have $x \notin U_n$ which is a contradiction. If $m = n+1$ , then $x \notin \widehat {L}_n$ and hence $x \in L_{n+1} \cap \overline {U_n} \subseteq \overline {U_n}$ . But then $x \in (\widehat {L}_{n+1} \cap \overline {U_n})\kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt U_n$ which proves part (a) of the claim.

For (b), note that by (a), we have $L \cap F_n$ is compact. Let $\mathcal {V}$ be an open cover of $L$ . Then, for every $x \in F^{(\beta )}$ , there is $V_x \in \mathcal {V}$ such that $x \in V_x$ . Let $n \in \mathbb {N}$ be such that $U_n \subseteq \bigcup \{V_x: x \in F^{(\beta )}\}$ . Since $L \cap F_n$ is compact, there is a finite subset $\mathcal {W} \subseteq \mathcal {V}$ such that $L \cap F_n \subseteq \bigcup \mathcal {W}$ . But then $L \subseteq \bigcup \mathcal {W} \cup \bigcup \{V_x: x \in F^{(\beta )}\}$ , hence $L$ is compact.

For $y \in K$ , $\textrm {supp}(y)$ is finite, hence there is $n \in \mathbb {N}$ such that $\textrm {supp}(y) \cap (F \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F^{(\beta )}) \subseteq F_n$ . Let $H_n = \widehat {L}_n \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F_n)$ and $H = L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F)$ . By Claim 1, we have $\sum \{ | \lambda _x^y | : x \in \textrm {supp} (y) \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt H_n \} < \sum _{m=1}^n \varepsilon _m <\varepsilon /2$ . Since $ \textrm {supp} (y) \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt H \subseteq \textrm {supp} (y) \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt H_n$ , we have $\sum \{ | \lambda _x^y | : x \in \textrm {supp} (y) \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt H \} < \varepsilon /2$ . So $K$ is $\varepsilon /2$ -supported on $H$ which proves part (c) of the claim.

Now, we can conclude that $K$ is $\varepsilon /2$ -supported on $\bigcup \mathcal {W}$ and, by Claim 2, that $K$ is $\varepsilon /2$ -supported on $L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F)$ . Note that $(L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt F)) \cap \bigcup W \subseteq L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt A)$ . Then, by Lemma 2.4(b) and (c), the set $K$ is $\varepsilon $ -supported on $L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt A)$ . Since by Claim 2, $L$ is compact, this proves the lemma.

3 Linear ${\boldsymbol{k}}$ -mappings

Let $X$ and $Y$ be Tychonov spaces, let $E$ be a linear subspace of $C_p(X),$ and let $\phi : E \to C_p(Y)$ be a continuous linear function. Let $k \in \mathbb {N}$ and $F = \phi (E) \subseteq C_p(Y)$ . We define $\phi $ to be a linear $k$ -mapping if, for every $f \in E$ satisfying $f(E) \subseteq [-1,1]$ , we have $\phi (f)(Y) \subseteq [-k,k]$ . If $\phi : E \to F$ is a linear homeomorphism, we define $\phi $ to be a linear $k$ -homeomorphism if both $\phi : E \to F$ and $\phi ^{-1}: F \to E$ are linear $k$ -mappings. In that case, we define $\phi : E \to C_p(Y)$ to be a linear $k$ -embedding.

If we endow $C^*(X)$ with the topology of uniform convergence, we denote that by $C_u^*(X)$ . For $f \in C^*(X)$ , we define $\|f\| = \sup _{x \in X} |f(x)|$ . Let $\phi : C_p^*(X)\rightarrow C_p^*(Y)$ be a continuous linear function. By the Closed Graph Theorem, $\phi : C_u^*(X)\rightarrow C_u^*(Y)$ is also continuous. This means there exist $k \in \mathbb {N}$ such that for each $f \in C^*(X)$ , $\| \phi (f) \| \leq k \cdot \|f\|$ . Hence, for this $k,$ it turns out that $\phi $ is a linear $k$ -mapping. Similarly, if $\phi $ is a linear homeomorphism (embedding), there is $k \in \mathbb {N}$ such that for each $f \in C^*(X)$ , $\frac {1}{k} \|f\| \leq \| \phi (f) \| \leq k \cdot \|f\|$ . For this $k$ , we have that $\phi $ is a linear $k$ -homeomorphism (embedding).

If there exists a linear $k$ -homeomorphism between linear subspaces $E$ and $F$ of $C_p(X)$ and $C_p(Y)$ or $C_u^*(X)$ and $C_u^*(Y)$ , we denote this by $E \stackrel {k}{\sim } F$ .

For each ordinal $\alpha $ , let $[1,\alpha ]$ be the compact ordinal space $\{\beta : 1 \leq \beta \leq \alpha \}$ with the order topology. By Corollary 8.6.7 in [Reference Semadeni16], the space $[1,\alpha ]$ is scattered. We define $C_{u,0}^*([1, \alpha ])= \{f \in C_u^*([1, \alpha ]): f(\alpha ) =0\}$ . In [Reference Bessaga and Pelczyński13], Bessaga and Pelczyński found the following:

Lemma 3.1 Let $\alpha \geq \omega $ be an ordinal. Then $C_{u,0}^*([1, \alpha ]) \stackrel {2}{\sim } C_u^*([1, \alpha ])$ .

Lemma 3.2 Let $\alpha , \beta \geq \omega $ be ordinals, let $\{ U_n : n \in \mathbb {N}\}$ be a clopen decreasing base at $\alpha $ with $U_1 =[1,\alpha ]$ , and let $\{ V_n : n \in \mathbb {N}\}$ be a clopen decreasing base at $\beta $ with $V_1 =[1,\beta ]$ . If $k \in \mathbb {N}$ is such that for every $n \in \mathbb {N}$ , there is a linear $k$ -embedding from $C_u^*(U_n \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt U_{n+1})$ to $C_u^*(V_n \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt V_{n+1})$ , then there is a linear $4k$ -embedding from $C_u^*([1, \alpha ])$ to $C_u^*([1, \beta ])$ .

Proof For $n \in \mathbb {N}$ , let $\theta _n: C_u^*(U_n \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt U_{n+1}) \to C_u^*(V_n \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt V_{n+1})$ be a linear $k$ -embedding.

Define $\theta : C_{u,0}^*([1, \alpha ]) \to C_{u,0}^*([1, \beta ])$ by

$$ \begin{align*}\theta(f)|_{(V_n \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt V_{n+1})} = \theta_n(f|_{(U_n \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt U_{n+1})}) \textrm{ and } \theta(f)(\beta) =0. \end{align*} $$

Since each $\theta _n$ is a linear $k$ -mapping, $\theta $ is well defined. Since, for every $f \in C_{u,0}^*([1, \alpha ]),$ we have $\frac {1}{k} \|f\| \leq \| \theta (f)\| \leq k \|f\|$ it follows that $\theta $ is a linear $k$ -embedding. By Lemma 3.1, it then follows there is a linear $4k$ -embedding from $C_u^*([1,\alpha ])$ to $C_u^*([1,\beta ])$ .

In [Reference Dugundji14], Dugundji proved the following:

Theorem 3.3 Let $X$ be a metric space, and let $A$ be a closed subspace of $X$ . Then there exists a continuous linear function $\phi : C_p(A) \to C_p(X)$ such that, for every $f \in C_p(A),$ we have $\phi (f)|_A = f$ and $\phi (f)(X) \subseteq \mathrm{conv}(f(A))$ the convex hull of $f(A)$ .

Dugundji’s theorem is used in the proof of the following lemma. A version of this lemma was embedded in the proof of Theorem 1.1 (see [Reference Baars and de Groot8, Theorem 4.1.15 on p. 147]).

Lemma 3.4 Let $X$ and $Y$ be metric spaces, and let $\phi : C_p(X)\to C_p(Y)$ be a linear homeomorphism. Let $K \subseteq Y$ be compact, and let $L = \overline {\mathrm{supp}(K)}$ . Then there exists a linear embedding $\theta : C_p(K) \to C_p(L)$ .

Proof By Theorem 3.3, there is a continuous linear function $\psi : C_p(L) \to C_p(X)$ such that, for every $f \in C_p(L),$ we have $\psi (f)|_L = f$ and a continuous linear function $\zeta : C_p(K) \to C_p(Y)$ such that, for every $g \in C_p(K),$ we have $\zeta (g)|_K = g$ . Define $\theta : C_p(K) \to C_p(L)$ by $\theta (g) = (\phi ^{-1} (\zeta (g))|_L$ and $\vartheta : C_p(L) \to C_p(K)$ by $\vartheta (f) = (\phi (\psi (f))|_K$ . Then $\theta $ and $\vartheta $ are well-defined continuous linear mappings.

Let $g \in C_p(K),$ and let $h = \psi (\theta (g)) - \phi ^{-1}( \zeta (g))$ . Then

$$ \begin{align*}h|_L = \psi (\theta(g))|_L - \phi^{-1}( \zeta(g))|_L = \theta(g)-\theta(g) =0. \end{align*} $$

Since $\textrm {supp}(K) \subseteq L$ , we have $h|_{\textrm {supp}(K)}=0$ . Hence, by Lemma 2.1(a), $\phi (h)|_K =0$ . Therefore,

$$ \begin{align*}\phi(h)|_K = \phi (\psi (\theta(g)))|_K - \phi(\phi^{-1}( \zeta(g)))|_K = \vartheta (\theta(g)) - g =0, \end{align*} $$

and hence $\vartheta (\theta (g)) = g$ . So $\theta $ is injective and $\vartheta \circ \theta = \textrm {id}_K$ . This implies that $\theta $ is a linear embedding.

By Lemma 2.2, the subspace $L \subseteq X$ in Lemma 3.4 is compact. This fact is essential in the proof of Theorem 1.1. Although it can be shown that Lemma 3.4 also holds for linear homeomorphisms $\phi : C_p^*(X)\to C_p^*(Y)$ , we cannot guarantee in this case that $L$ is compact. Therefore, a different approach is required to prove Theorem 1.2. Instead of Lemma 3.4, we will use Lemma 3.6 applied to the compact set $L$ in Lemma 2.8. But first, we need the following corollary to Dugundji’s theorem.

Lemma 3.5 Let $X$ be a metric space, and let $A$ be a closed subspace of $X$ . Then there is a continuous linear 1-mapping $\phi : C_p^*(A) \to C_p^*(X)$ such that, for every $f \in C_p^*(A),$ we have $\phi (f)|_A = f$ .

Proof By Theorem 3.3, there is a continuous linear function $\psi : C_p(A) \to C_p(X)$ such that, for every $f \in C_p(A),$ we have $\psi (f)|_A = f$ and $\psi (f)(X) \subseteq \textrm {conv}(f(A))$ . For $f \in C_p^*(A)$ , let $k =\|f\|$ . Then $f(A) \subseteq [-k,k]$ and hence $\psi (f)(X) \subseteq \textrm {conv}(f(A)) \subseteq [-k,k]$ . This implies $\psi (f) \in C_p^*(X)$ and $\|\psi (f)\| \leq \|f\|$ . So $\phi = \psi |_{C_p^*(A)}:C_p^*(A) \to C_p^*(X)$ is a linear 1-mapping.

The next lemma is motivated by Lemma 3.4 in [Reference Baars3].

Lemma 3.6 Let $X$ and $Y$ be metric spaces, and let $\phi : C_p^*(X)\to C_p^*(Y)$ be a linear $k$ -homeomorphism. Let $K \subseteq Y$ be compact, and let $L \subseteq X$ be such that $K$ is $\frac {1}{4k}$ -supported on $L$ . Then there exists a linear $2k$ -embedding $\theta : C_u^*(K) \to C_u^*(L).$

Proof By Lemma 3.5 and the Closed Graph Theorem, there is a continuous linear 1-mapping $\psi : C_u^*(L) \to C_u^*(X)$ such that, for every $f \in C_u^*(L),$ we have $\psi (f)|_L = f$ and there is a continuous linear 1-mapping $\zeta : C_u^*(K) \to C_u^*(Y)$ such that, for every $g \in C_u^*(K),$ we have $\zeta (g)|_K = g$ . Define $\theta : C_u^*(K) \to C_u^*(L)$ by $\theta (g) = (\phi ^{-1} (\zeta (g))|_L$ and $\vartheta : C_u^*(L) \to C_u^*(K)$ by $\vartheta (f) = (\phi (\psi (f))|_K$ . Then $\theta $ and $\vartheta $ are continuous and linear. Since $\psi $ and $\zeta $ are linear 1-mappings and $\phi $ and $\phi ^{-1}$ are linear $k$ -mappings, we conclude that $\theta $ and $\vartheta $ are linear $k$ -mappings.

Claim For every $g \in C_u^*(K),$ we have $\| ( \vartheta ( \theta (g)) - g \| \leq \frac {1}{2} \|g\|$ .

Let $h = \psi (\theta (g)) - \phi ^{-1}( \zeta (g))$ . Since $\psi $ is a linear 1-mapping and $\theta $ is a linear $k$ -mapping it follows that $\psi \circ \theta $ is a linear $k$ -mapping. Hence $\|\psi (\theta (g))\| \leq k \|g\|$ . Since $\zeta $ is a linear 1-mapping and $\phi ^{-1}$ is a linear $k$ -mapping, it follows that $\phi ^{-1} \circ \zeta $ is a linear $k$ -mapping. Hence $\|\phi ^{-1}( \zeta (g))\| \leq k \|g\|$ . This implies $\|h\| \leq \|\psi (\theta (g))\| + \|\phi ^{-1}( \zeta (g))\| \leq 2k\|g\|$ .

Note that $h|_L = \psi (\theta (g))|_L - \phi ^{-1}( \zeta (g))|_L = \theta (g) - \theta (g)= 0$ . Then, for $z \in K$ ,

$$ \begin{align*} |\phi(h)(z)| & = |\sum \{ \lambda_x^z h(x) : x \in \textrm{supp} (z)\}| \leq \sum \{ |\lambda_x^z| \cdot |h(x)| : x \in \textrm{supp} (z)\} \\ & \leq \sum \{ |\lambda_x^z|\cdot |h(x)| : x \in \textrm{supp} (z) \cap L \} + \sum \{ |\lambda_x^z| \cdot |h(x)| : x \in \textrm{supp} (z) \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt L \} \\ & \leq 0 + \sum \{ |\lambda_x^z| : x \in \textrm{supp} (z) \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt L \} \cdot \|h\| < \frac{1}{4k} \cdot 2k \|g\| = \frac{1}{2} \|g\|. \end{align*} $$

This implies $\| \phi (h)|_K \| \leq \frac {1}{2} \|g\|$ . Since

$$ \begin{align*} \phi(h)|_K & = \phi(\psi (\theta(g)))|_K - \phi(\phi^{-1}( \zeta(g)))|_K \\ & = \vartheta(\theta(g)) - \zeta(g)|_K = \vartheta(\theta(g)) - g, \end{align*} $$

this proves the claim.

Let $g \in C_u^*(K)$ and suppose $\theta (g) = 0$ . Then $\vartheta ( \theta (g)) = 0$ , and hence, it follows by the claim that $\|g\| = \| ( \vartheta ( \theta (g)) - g \| \leq \frac {1}{2} \|g\|$ . So $g = 0,$ and hence, $\theta $ is one-to-one. For $g \in C_u^*(K)$ , since $\vartheta $ is a linear $k$ -mapping, we have by the claim

$$ \begin{align*}\|g\| \leq \|(\vartheta( \theta(g)) - g\| + \|(\vartheta( \theta(g))\| \leq \frac{1}{2} \|g\| + k \|\theta(g)\|. \end{align*} $$

Hence $\|g\| \leq 2k \|\theta (g)\|$ . Since $\theta $ is a linear $k$ -mapping, it follows that $\frac {1}{2k} \|g\| \leq \|\theta (g)\| \leq 2k\|g\|$ . Hence, $\theta $ is a linear $2k$ -embedding.

4 Main results

We define an ordinal $\alpha $ to be a prime component if, for every $\beta < \alpha $ , we have $\beta + \alpha = \alpha $ . If $\alpha> 0$ is a prime component, then $\alpha = \omega ^{\mu }$ for some ordinal $\mu $ (see [Reference Sierpiński17, Theorem 1, p. 320]). By Theorem 8.6.6 in [Reference Semadeni16], for the ordinal space $X = [1,\omega ^{\mu }]$ , we have the equality $X^{(\mu )} = \{\omega ^{\mu }\}$ . It is well known that, for every ordinal $\alpha ,$ there is a largest prime component $\omega ^{\mu }$ such that $\omega ^\mu \leq \alpha$ (see [Reference Sierpiński17, p. 282]). We then have $\omega ^{\mu } \leq \alpha < \omega ^{\mu +1}$ . Note that if $X$ is a first countable space and $\mu < \omega _1$ is such that $X^{(\mu )} \neq \emptyset $ , then there is $K \subseteq X$ such that $K$ is homeomorphic to $[1,\omega ^{\mu }]$ (see, for example, Lemma 4.1.8 in [Reference Baars and de Groot8]).

Bessaga and Pelczyński [Reference Bessaga and Pelczyński13] found the following:

Theorem 4.1

  1. (a) If $\omega \leq \alpha \leq \gamma < \omega _1$ , then $C_u^*([1,\alpha ]) \sim C_u^*([1,\gamma ])$ if and only if $\gamma < \alpha ^{\omega }$ .

  2. (b) If $\theta : C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\mu }])\rightarrow C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\nu }])$ is a linear embedding with $\mu ,\nu \geq 1$ and $\mu $ is a prime component, then $\mu \leq \nu $ .

In [Reference Baars and de Groot6], it was shown that the same isomorphic classification as in Theorem 4.1(a) holds for linear homeomorphisms between function spaces $C_p([1,\alpha ])$ . We are now in a position to proof Theorems 1.2 and 1.3. In both proofs, we will need the following:

Theorem 4.2 [Reference Semadeni16, Theorem 8.6.10]

Let $X$ be a countable compact Hausdorff space. Then there is an ordinal $\alpha < \omega _1$ such that $X$ is homeomorphic to $[1,\alpha ]$ .

Proof of Theorem 1.2

Let $\phi : C_p^*(X)\to C_p^*(Y)$ be a linear homeomorphism. Let $k \in \mathbb {N}$ be such that $\phi $ is linear $k$ -homeomorphism. Clearly, we have $X = \emptyset $ if and only $Y = \emptyset $ , so (a) holds for $\alpha = 0$ and (b) holds for $\alpha = 1$ . Note that for $\alpha = 0$ , there is nothing to prove for (b). For $\alpha = 1$ , (a) follows from Theorem 2.2 in [Reference Baars, de Groot, van Mill and Pelant9], so we may assume that $\alpha \geq \omega $ .

For (a), assume that $\kappa (X) \leq \alpha $ and $\kappa (Y)> \alpha $ . Since $Y^{(1)} \neq \emptyset ,$ we have by the above that $X^{(1)} \neq \emptyset $ , hence $X$ is not discrete. Since $Y^{(\alpha )} \neq \emptyset $ , there is $K \subseteq Y$ such that $K$ is homeomorphic to $[1,\omega ^{\alpha }]$ in $Y$ . Since $X$ is scattered, we can find by Lemma 2.8, a compact subset $L$ of $X$ such that $K$ is $\frac {1}{4k}$ -supported on $L$ . Since $X$ is not discrete, we may assume, by Lemma 2.4(b), that $L$ is infinite. By Lemma 3.6, there is a linear embedding $\theta : C_u^*(K) \to C_u^*(L)$ . Since $L^{(\alpha )} = \emptyset $ , we conclude that $L$ is a compact scattered metric space. Therefore, by Theorem 2.7, $L$ is countable, and hence, by Theorem 4.2, there is $\omega \leq \gamma < \omega ^{\alpha }$ such that $L$ is homeomorphic to $[1,\gamma ]$ . Let $\omega ^{\mu } < \omega _1$ be a prime component such that $\omega ^{\mu } \leq \gamma < \omega ^{\mu +1}$ . Then $L^{(\mu )} \neq \emptyset $ and since $L^{(\alpha )} = \emptyset $ it follows that $\mu < \alpha $ . Since $\gamma < (\omega ^{\mu })^{\omega }$ , we have, by Theorem 4.1(a), that $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\mu }]) \sim C_u^*([1,\gamma ]),$ and hence, there exists a linear embedding from $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\alpha }])$ to $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\mu }])$ . But then by Theorem 4.1(b), $\alpha \leq \mu $ . Contradiction. This proves (a).

For (b), assume that $\kappa (X) < \alpha $ and $\kappa (Y) \geq \alpha $ . Let $\kappa (X) =\beta < \alpha $ . Let $(\alpha _i)_{i \in \mathbb {N}}$ be an increasing sequence of ordinals such that $\alpha _i \to \alpha $ and $\alpha _i> \beta $ for every $i \in \mathbb {N}$ . Let $K_i$ be a closed copy of $[1,\omega ^{\alpha _i}]$ in $Y$ . Since $X$ is scattered, by Lemma 2.8, there is a compact subset $L_i$ of $X$ such that $K_i$ is $\frac {1}{4k}$ -supported on $L_i$ . As in the proof of (a), we may assume that $L_i$ is infinite and, since $L_i^{(\beta )} = \emptyset $ , there is $\omega \leq \gamma _i < \omega ^{\beta }$ such that $L_i$ is homeomorphic to $[1,\gamma _i]$ . But then $L_i$ can be seen as a closed subset of $[1,\omega ^{\beta }],$ and hence, by Lemma 3.5, there is a linear 1-embedding from $C_u^*(L_i)$ to $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\beta }])$ . By Lemma 3.6, there is a linear $2k$ -embedding $\theta _i: C_u^*(K_i) \to C_u^*(L_i)$ , and hence, there is a linear $2k$ -embedding $\psi _i : C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\alpha _i}]) \to C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\beta }])$ .

Let $S = \{x_i: i \in \mathbb {N}\} \cup \{x_0\}$ be a convergent sequence, where $x_i \to x_0$ . Let $A$ be the compact space defined by replacing $x_i$ in $S$ by a copy $A_i$ of $[1,\omega ^{\alpha _i}]$ , and let $B$ be the compact space defined by replacing $x_i$ in $S$ by a copy $B_i$ of $[1,\omega ^{\beta }]$ . Then $A$ is homeomorphic to $[1,\omega ^{\alpha }]$ and $B$ is homeomorphic to $[1,\omega ^{\beta +1}]$ . By Lemma 3.2, it now follows that there is a linear $8k$ -embedding from $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\alpha }])$ to $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\beta +1}])$ . But then, by Theorem 4.1(b), $\alpha \leq \beta +1$ . Since $\beta < \alpha $ , we then have $\alpha = \beta +1$ . But $\alpha $ is a prime component and hence a limit ordinal. Contradiction. This proves (b).

Proof of Theorem 1.3

For (a), let $\phi : C_p(X)\to C_p(Y)$ be a linear homeomorphism. Since $X = \emptyset $ , if and only $Y = \emptyset $ , (a) holds for $\mu =1$ . For $\alpha = \omega ^{\mu }$ with $\mu $ a limit ordinal, let $(\mu _i)_{i \in \mathbb {N}}$ be a strictly increasing sequence of ordinals such that $\mu _i \to \mu $ . Let $\beta = \kappa (X)$ and assume that $\kappa (X) < \alpha $ and $\kappa (Y) \geq \alpha $ . Let $i \in \mathbb {N}$ be such that $\beta < \omega ^{\mu _i}$ . Let $\alpha _i = \omega ^{\mu _i}$ and $\alpha _{i+1} = \omega ^{\mu _{i+1}}$ . Let $K$ be a closed copy of $[1,\omega ^{\alpha _{i+1}}]$ in $Y$ , and let $L = \overline {\textrm {supp}_{\phi }(K)}$ . By Lemma 2.1(b), we have $K \subseteq \textrm {supp}_{\phi ^{-1}}(\textrm {supp}_{\phi }(K)) \subseteq \textrm {supp}_{\phi ^{-1}} (L)$ , and hence $L$ is infinite. By Lemma 2.2, $L$ is compact. Hence, by Lemma 3.4 and the Closed Graph Theorem, there is a linear embedding $\theta : C_u^*(K) \to C_u^*(L)$ . Since $L^{(\beta )} = \emptyset $ , as in the proof of Theorem 1.2(a), there is $\omega \leq \gamma < \omega ^{\beta }$ such that $L$ is homeomorphic to $[1,\gamma ]$ . But then $L$ can be seen as a closed subset of $[1,\omega ^{\alpha _i}]$ , and hence, by Lemma 3.5, there is a linear embedding from $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\alpha _{i+1}}])$ to $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\alpha _i}])$ . Since $\alpha _{i+1}$ is a prime component, it then follows by Theorem 4.1(b) that $\alpha _{i+1} \leq \alpha _i$ . Contradiction, which proves (a).

For (b), let $\alpha = \omega ^{\mu } < \omega _1$ be a prime component with $\mu \geq 1$ a successor ordinal. Suppose $\mu = \sigma +1$ and $\beta = \omega ^{\sigma }$ . Then $\beta \geq 1$ is a prime component and $\alpha = \beta \cdot \omega $ . For every $n \in \mathbb {N}$ , let $X_n = [1, \omega ^{\beta \cdot n}]$ . Let $X = \bigoplus _{n=1}^{\infty } X_n$ be the topological sum of the spaces $X_n$ , and let $Y = X_1 \times \mathbb {N}$ . By Theorem 4.1(a), we have, for every $n \in \mathbb {N}$ , $C_p(X_n) \sim C_p(X_1)$ . Therefore, $C_p(X) \sim C_p(Y)$ . Note that for every $n \in \mathbb {N}$ , $\kappa (X_n) = \beta \cdot n +1$ . This implies $\kappa (Y) = \beta +1 < \alpha $ and $\kappa (X) = \beta \cdot \omega = \alpha $ .

Remark 4.3 Theorems 1.11.3(a) are true for prime components. The question is if these results also hold for ordinals that are not a prime component. For such ordinals $\alpha $ , let $\omega ^{\mu }$ be the largest prime component such that $\omega ^{\mu } \leq \alpha $ , and let $\beta = \omega ^{\mu }$ . Then $\beta < \alpha < \beta \cdot \omega $ , and hence $\omega ^{\beta } < \omega ^{\alpha } < \omega ^{\beta \cdot \omega }$ .

Let $X$ and $Y$ be $l_p$ -equivalent metric spaces, and suppose $\alpha = \beta +1$ . If $\kappa (X) < \alpha $ , then $\kappa (X) \leq \beta $ . Since $\beta $ is a prime component, we have by Theorem 1.1 that $\kappa (Y) \leq \beta ,$ and hence $\kappa (Y) < \alpha $ . This implies that Theorem 1.3 also holds for $\alpha = \beta +1$ with $\beta $ a prime component. By the same reasoning, Theorem 1.2(b) also holds for $\alpha = \beta +1$ with $\beta $ a prime component.

Now assume $\alpha> \beta +1$ . By Theorem 4.1(a), we have $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\beta }]) \sim C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\alpha }])$ . As mentioned above, the same isomorphic classification holds for function spaces $C_p(X)$ , where $X$ is a countable compact ordinal space (see [Reference Baars and de Groot6]). Therefore, $C_p([1,\omega ^{\beta }]) \sim C_p([1,\omega ^{\alpha }])$ . Since $\kappa ([1,\omega ^{\alpha }]) = \alpha +1> \alpha $ and $\kappa ([1,\omega ^{\beta }]) = \beta +1 < \alpha $ , it follows that Theorems 1.11.3 do not always hold.

In Theorem 4.6, we will show that if $X$ and $Y$ are $l_p^*$ -equivalent spaces, then $X$ is scattered if and only $Y$ is scattered. This result does not directly follow from Theorem 1.2 since we have only proved it for prime components $\alpha < \omega _1$ . To prove Theorem 4.6, we need the following notion and result from [Reference Baars5].

For a metric space $X$ and an ordinal $\alpha $ , we define $X^{\{\alpha \}}$ by transfinite induction as follows:

  1. (a) $X^{\{0\}}=X.$

  2. (b) If $\alpha $ is a successor, say $\alpha = \beta +1$ , then $x \in X^{\{\alpha \}}$ if and only if for every neighborhood $U$ of $x$ , $U \cap X^{\{\beta \}}$ is not compact.

  3. (c) If $\alpha $ is a limit ordinal, then $X^{\{\alpha \}}= \bigcap _{\beta < \alpha } X^{\{\beta \}}$ .

For each ordinal $\alpha $ , it turns out that $X^{\{\alpha \}}$ is a closed subset of $X$ . The following result can be found in [Reference Baars5].

Theorem 4.4 Let $X$ and $Y$ be $l_p^*$ -equivalent metric spaces, and let $\alpha $ be an ordinal. Then $X^{\{\alpha \}} = \emptyset $ if and only if $Y^{\{\alpha \}}= \emptyset $ .

In the proof of Theorem 4.6, we also need the following lemma on non-scattered spaces.

Lemma 4.5 Let $X$ be a non-scattered Tychonov space, and let $\alpha $ be an ordinal such that $X^{\{\alpha \}} = \emptyset $ . Then $X$ contains a compact non-scattered subspace.

Proof Let $C = \bigcap _{\beta } Y^{(\beta )}$ . By Theorem 2.7, we have $C \neq \emptyset $ , and hence $\alpha>0$ . Note that for every $x \in C$ and every neighborhood $U$ of $x,$ we have $\overline {U} \cap C$ is not scattered. We will proof the lemma by transfinite induction on $\alpha $ . If $\alpha =1$ , then $Y$ is locally compact. Pick $x \in C$ , and let $U$ be a neighborhood of $x$ such that $\overline {U}$ is compact. Then $\overline {U} \cap C$ is a compact non-scattered subspace of $Y$ .

Let $\alpha>1$ and assume the lemma is true for every non-scattered Tychonov space $Z$ and every $\beta < \alpha $ such that $Z^{\{\beta \}} = \emptyset $ . Pick $x \in C$ , and let $\beta = \min \{\gamma \leq \alpha : x \notin X^{\{\gamma \}}\}$ . Since $x \notin X^{\{\alpha \}}$ , $\beta $ is well defined. Clearly, $\beta>0$ and $\beta $ is a successor ordinal, say $\beta = \gamma +1$ . Since $x \notin X^{\{\beta \}}$ , there exists a neighborhood $U$ of $x$ such that $\overline {U} \cap X^{\{\delta \}}$ is compact. If $\overline {U} \cap C$ is compact we are done, so let’s assume that $\overline {U} \cap C$ is not compact. Then there is $z \in (\overline {U} \cap C) \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt X^{\{\delta \}}$ . Let $V$ be a neighborhood of $z$ such that $\overline {V} \cap X^{\{\delta \}}=\emptyset $ . Then $\overline {V} \cap C$ is not scattered and $(\overline {V} \cap C)^{\{\delta \}} = \emptyset $ . By the induction hypothesis, $\overline {V} \cap C$ contains a compact non-scattered subspace which proves the lemma.

We will now prove the following:

Theorem 4.6 Let X and Y be $l_p^*$ -equivalent metric spaces. Then X is scattered if and only if Y is scattered.

Proof Let $\phi : C_p^*(X) \to C_p^*(Y)$ be a linear homeomorphism. Then there is $k \in \mathbb {N}$ such that $\phi $ is a linear $k$ -homeomorphism. Assume that $X$ is scattered and that $Y$ is not scattered. Let $\alpha>0$ be an ordinal such that $X^{(\alpha )} = \emptyset $ . Then $X^{\{\alpha \}} = \emptyset $ , since $X^{\{\alpha \}} \subseteq X^{(\alpha )}$ . From Theorem 4.4, it then follows that $Y^{\{\alpha \}} = \emptyset $ .

Since $Y$ is not-scattered, by Lemma 4.5, $Y$ contains a compact non-scattered subspace $K$ . Since $X$ is scattered, there is, by Lemma 2.8, a compact subset $L$ of $X$ such that $K$ is $\frac {1}{4k}$ -supported on $L$ . Then, by Lemma 3.6, there is a linear embedding $\theta : C_u^*(K) \to C_u^*(L)$ . As in the proof of Theorem 1.2, we may assume that $L$ is infinite and that there is $\omega \leq \gamma < \omega _1$ such that $L$ is homeomorphic to $[1,\gamma ]$ .

Let $\omega ^{\mu } < \omega _1$ be a prime component such that $\omega ^{\mu } \leq \gamma < \omega ^{\mu +1}$ , and let $\beta> \mu +1$ be a prime component. Since $K$ is a compact non-scattered metric space, we have $K^{(\beta )} \neq \emptyset $ , and hence, it contains a copy of $[1,\omega ^{\beta }]$ and so, by Lemma 3.5, there exists a linear embedding from $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\beta }])$ to $C_u^*(K)$ . By Theorem 4.1(a), we have $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\mu }]) \sim C_u^*([1,\gamma ]),$ and hence, there exists a linear embedding from $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\beta }])$ to $C_u^*([1,\omega ^{\mu }])$ . But then by Theorem 4.1(b), $\beta \leq \mu $ . Contradiction, which shows that $Y$ is scattered.

Remark 4.7 Theorem 4.6 also holds for $l_p$ -equivalent first countable paracompact spaces (see [Reference Baars4]). The proof of Theorem 4.6 does not work for all first countable paracompact $l_p^*$ -equivalent spaces. The reason for this is the use of Lemma 3.6. This lemma makes essential use of Dugundji’s theorem 3.3 for metric spaces. The proof of Theorem 4.6 for $l_p$ -equivalent first countable paracompact spaces in [Reference Baars4] does not need Dugundji’s theorem. A careful examination of the proofs of Lemma 2.5 in [Reference Baars, de Groot and Pelant10], Corollary 2.6 and Lemma 2.8 shows that these results do hold for first countable paracompact spaces.

Question 4.8 Let X and Y be $l_p^*$ -equivalent first countable paracompact spaces. Is it true that X is scattered if and only if Y is scattered?

The results in this paper do hold for ordinals $\alpha < \omega _1$ . For ordinals $\alpha> \omega _1$ , the approach in this paper does not seem to work, but for $\alpha = \omega _1$ it does.

Theorem 4.9 Theorems 1.11.3 hold for $\alpha = \omega _1$ .

Proof Theorem 4.1.17 in [Reference Baars and de Groot8] shows that Theorem 1.1 holds for $\alpha = \omega _1$ .

Let $X$ and $Y$ be metric spaces. Suppose $\kappa (X) < \omega _1$ . Then there is a prime component $\omega ^{\mu }$ , with $\mu <\omega _1$ a limit ordinal, such that $\kappa (X) < \omega ^{\mu }$ . So if $X$ and $Y$ are $l_p$ -equivalent or $l_p^*$ -equivalent, we then have, by Theorem 1.2(b) or Theorem 1.3(a), that $\kappa (Y) < \omega ^{\mu } <\omega _1$ . Therefore, Theorems 1.2(b) and 1.3(a) hold for $\alpha = \omega _1$ .

This leaves us with Theorem 1.2(a) for $\alpha =\omega _1$ . Let $k \in \mathbb {N}$ , and let $\phi : C_p^*(X) \to C_p^*(Y)$ be a linear $k$ -homeomorphism. Suppose $\kappa (X) \leq \omega _1$ and $\kappa (Y)> \omega _1$ . Let $y \in Y^{(\omega _1)}$ , and let $\mathcal {V} = \{X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt X^{(\alpha )}: \alpha < \omega _1\}$ . Then $\mathcal {V}$ is an open cover of $X$ . Let $\mathcal {W}$ be a locally finite open cover of $X$ such that $\{\overline {W}: W \in \mathcal {W}\}$ refines $\mathcal {V}$ . By Lemma 2.5, there are a neighborhood $U$ of $y$ and a finite subset $\mathcal {F} \subseteq \mathcal {W}$ such that $U$ is $\frac {1}{8k}$ -supported on $\bigcup \mathcal {F}$ . Let $A = \bigcup \{\overline {W}: W \in \mathcal {F}\}$ . Then $A$ is closed and since $\mathcal {F}$ is finite, there is $\beta < \omega _1$ such that $A \subseteq X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt X^{(\beta )}$ . So $A^{(\beta )} = \emptyset $ . Let $\sigma $ be a prime component such that $\beta < \sigma < \omega _1$ . Then $U$ contains a closed copy $K$ of $[1, \omega ^{\sigma }]$ . By Lemma 2.8, there is $L \subseteq A$ compact such that $K$ is $\frac {1}{8k}$ -supported on $L \cup (X \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt A)$ . Then, by Lemma 2.4(a), (b), and (c), we have that $K$ is $\frac {1}{4k}$ -supported on $L$ . Then, as in the proof of Theorem 1.2(a), there is $\omega \leq \gamma < \omega ^{\alpha }$ such that $L$ is homeomorphic to $[1, \gamma ]$ and there is a linear embedding from $C_u^*(K) \to C_u^*(L)$ . As in the proof of Theorem 1.2(a), this gives a contradiction. Hence, Theorem 1.2(a) holds for $\alpha = \omega _1$ .

The following question remains open:

Question 4.10 Let X and Y be $l_p$ -equivalent or $l_p^*$ -equivalent metric spaces. For which ordinals $\alpha> \omega _1$ are Theorem 1.1, Theorem 1.2, or Theorem 1.3 true?

We conclude this paper by showing that Theorem 1.1 and Theorem 1.2(a) do not hold for arbitrary Tychonov spaces. It remains an open question if the same holds for Theorems 1.2(b) and 1.3(a).

Example 4.11 For every prime component, such that $\omega \leq \alpha < \omega _1$ , there are Tychonov spaces $X$ and $Y$ such that:

  1. (a) $X$ and $Y$ are $l_p$ -equivalent.

  2. (b) $X$ and $Y$ are $l_p^*$ -equivalent.

  3. (c) $\kappa (X) = \alpha +1$ and $\kappa (Y) = \alpha .$

Proof Let $(\alpha _i)_{i \in \mathbb {N}}$ be an increasing sequence of limit ordinals such that $\alpha _i \to \alpha $ . Let $Z = [1,\omega ^{\alpha }),$ and for every $i \in \mathbb {N}$ , let $Z_i = [1,\omega ^{\alpha _i}]$ . Then $Z$ is homeomorphic to the topological sum $\bigoplus _{i=1}^{\infty } Z_i$ . We have $\kappa (Z) = \alpha $ and for every $i \in \mathbb {N}$ , $\kappa (Z_i) = \alpha _i +1$ . Let $z_i$ be the unique point in $Z_i^{(\alpha _i)}$ , and let $D = \{z_i: i \in \mathbb {N}\}$ . Then $D$ is a countable closed and discrete subset of $Z$ .

Let $\beta Z$ be the Čech–Stone compactification of $Z$ , and let $Z^* = \beta Z \kern2pt{\backslash}\kern2pt Z$ , the Čech–Stone remainder of $X$ . Note that $D$ is $C^*$ -embedded in $Z$ and that the closure $\mathrm {cl}_{\beta Z}{D}$ of $D$ in $\beta Z$ is $\beta D$ which is canonically homeomorphic to $\beta \mathbb {N}$ . Let $u\in \mathrm {cl}_{\beta Z} D$ , and let $X$ be the subspace $Z \cup \{u\}$ of $\beta Z$ . Then $\tilde u = \{A\subseteq \mathbb {N}: u\in \mathrm {cl}_{\beta Z} \{z_i : i\in A\}\}$ is an ultrafilter on $\mathbb {N}$ , and hence a point in $\mathbb {N}^*$ . Let $S = \mathbb {N} \cup \{\tilde u\} \subseteq \beta \mathbb {N}$ , and let $Y = Z \oplus S$ .

In [Reference Baars and van Mill11], it was shown that $X$ and $Y$ are $l_p$ -equivalent. In fact, the proof shows that there is $k \in \mathbb {N}$ such that $C_p(X) \stackrel {k}{\sim } C_p(Y)$ . Hence, $X$ and $Y$ are also $l_p^*$ -equivalent. Note that $\kappa (X) = \alpha +1$ and $\kappa (Y) = \alpha $ .

Question 4.12 Let $\alpha < \omega _1$ be a prime component. Are there $l_p^*$ -equivalent Tychonov spaces $X$ and $Y$ such that $\kappa (X) < \alpha $ and $\kappa (Y) \geq \alpha $ ?

Question 4.13 Let $\alpha = \omega ^{\mu } < \omega _1$ be a prime component with $\mu $ a limit ordinal. Are there $l_p$ -equivalent Tychonov spaces $X$ and $Y$ such that $\kappa (X) < \alpha $ and $\kappa (Y) \geq \alpha $ ?

References

Arhangel’skii, A. V., On linear homeomorphisms of function spaces . Dokl. Math. 25(1982), 852855.Google Scholar
Arhangel’skii, A. V., Topological function spaces, Mathematics and its Applications, 78, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, 1992.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baars, J., On the ${l}_p^{\ast }$ -equivalence of certain locally compact spaces . Topology Appl. 52(1993), 4357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baars, J., Function spaces on first countable paracompact spaces . Bull. Pol. Acad. Sci. Math. 42(1994), no. 1, 2935.Google Scholar
Baars, J., On the ${l}_p^{\ast }$ -equivalence of metric spaces . Topology Appl. 298(2021), 107729.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baars, J. and de Groot, J., An isomorphical classification of function spaces of zero-dimensional locally compact separable metric spaces . Comment. Math. Univ. Carolin. 29(1988), 577595.Google Scholar
Baars, J. and de Groot, J., On the l-equivalence of metric spaces . Fund. Math. 137(1991), 2543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baars, J. and de Groot, J., On topological and linear equivalence of certain function spaces, CWI-tract 86, Centre for Mathematics and Computer Science, Amsterdam, 1992.Google Scholar
Baars, J., de Groot, J., van Mill, J., and Pelant, J., An example of ${l}_p$ -equivalent spaces which are not ${l}_p^{\ast }$ -equivalent . Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 119(1993), 963969.Google Scholar
Baars, J., de Groot, J., and Pelant, J., Function spaces on completely metrizable spaces . Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 340(1993), 871883.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baars, J. and van Mill, J., Function spaces and points in Čech-Stone remainders. Submitted for publication, 2023.Google Scholar
Baars, J., van Mill, J., and Tkachuk, V. V., A note on linear invariance of (pseudo)compact spaces . Quaestiones Mathematicae 46(2022), 16.Google Scholar
Bessaga, C. and Pelczyński, A., Spaces of continuous functions IV (on isomorphical classification of spaces of continuous functions) . Dokl. Math. 19(1960), 5362.Google Scholar
Dugundji, J., An extension of Tietze’s Theorem . Pacific J. Math. 1(1951), 353367.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Mill, J., The infinite-dimensional topology of function spaces, North-Holland, 64, Gulf Professional Publishing, Oxford, 2002.Google Scholar
Semadeni, Z., Banach spaces of continuous functions, PWN, Warszawa, 1971.Google Scholar
Sierpiński, W., Cardinal and ordinal numbers, PWN, Warszawa, 1958.Google Scholar
Tkachuk, V. V., $A\,{C}_p$ -theory problem book – Topological and function spaces, Problem Books in Mathematics, Springer, Berlin, 2011.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tkachuk, V. V., $A\, {C}_p$ -theory problem book – Special features of function spaces, Problem Books in Mathematics, Springer, Berlin, 2014.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tkachuk, V. V., $A\, {C}_p$ -theory problem book – Compactness in function spaces, Problem Books in Mathematics, Springer, Berlin, 2015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tkachuk, V. V., $A\, {C}_p$ -theory problem book – Functional equivalencies, Problem Books in Mathematics, Springer, Berlin, 2016.Google Scholar