Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-wpx84 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-16T19:29:33.229Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

9 - Introduction to Part II: the need for and the place of a theory of representation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 December 2009

Mark Rowlands
Affiliation:
University College Cork
Get access

Summary

Intentionality, the aboutness or directedness of certain mental states towards their objects, was identified by Brentano as one of the essential features of the mental. Indeed, Brentano thought that it was this feature of the mental, in particular, the ability of the mind to stand in relations to intentionally inexistent objects, that marked the mind off as an essentially non-physical thing. One of the principal tasks of recent philosophy of mind, pace Brentano, has been to naturalize intentionality, to find a place for it in the natural, physical, order. And to naturalize intentionality in this sense requires showing how it can arise out of non-intentional, or non-semantic, properties and relations. This is the principal task of this second part of the book. As I shall try to show, there is, in fact, an intrinsic connection between this project and the position developed in Part I. The position defended in Part I, I shall argue, both requires a theory of representation and puts in place a framework within which a theory of representation is best located.

THE NEED FOR A THEORY OF REPRESENTATION

The need for a theory of representation can best be seen in terms of Paul Grice's (1957) famous distinction between natural meaning and non-natural meaning. Smoke naturally means fire, whereas the word ‘fire’, and not the word ‘smoke’, non-naturally means fire. To say that X naturally means Y, in this sense, is to say, roughly, that X indicates Y, whereas to say that X non-naturally means Y is to say, again roughly, that X denotes, designates, or refers to Y.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Body in Mind
Understanding Cognitive Processes
, pp. 205 - 211
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×