Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-v9fdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T02:37:52.063Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Analogy

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Gideon Manning
Affiliation:
California Institute of Technology
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

In the Private Thoughts (1619–22), Descartes stipulates that “man has knowledge of natural things only through their similarity [per similitudinem] to the things which come under the senses. Indeed, our estimate of how much truth a person has achieved in his philosophizing will increase the more he has been able to propose some similarity between what he is investigating and the things known by the senses” (AT X 218–19, CSM I 5; modified). By this measure, Descartes became a very accomplished philosopher, for in his published and unpublished work he frequently uses analogies between what comes “under the senses” and “natural things.” Specifically, Descartes’ analogies identify similarities between the effects of observable phenomena and processes, whose causes we know, and natural effects, whose causes we do not know. By way of his analogies, Descartes discovers or makes plausible the existence of specific unobservable natural causes and thereby provides a causal explanation in physics.

Although analogical reasoning is just one component of Descartes’ scientific method, which may be characterized as a version of hypothetical deduction minus careful confirmation (see Clarke 1982, Sakelleriadis 1982, and McMullin 2008 and 2009), it is with his analogies that Descartes bridges the gap between the world of experience and the moving and colliding particles at the microscopic level that ultimately explain the effects we observe. Yet Descartes rarely used the Latin term from which our “analogy” derives, let alone its French cognate analogie (cf. AT XI 158; see Galison 1984). The analogies from the Dioptrics (1637) that I discuss here are “comparisons” (comparaisons), and those from the Meteors (1637) are instances of reasoning by “example and similarity” (exemplum & similitudinem) (AT VI 83 and I 422, respectively). In the Principles (1644), analogies are typically “comparisons” (comparationes) or efforts to “compare” (consero/comparo) (e.g., AT VIIIA 87 and 110, respectively). In the famous Rule 8 from the Rules for the Direction of the Mind (1620s), Descartes’ method does not involve seeking “analogies” but advises us to “enumerate all the other natural powers so that, by means of knowledge of some other one, [we] might come to understand [the action of light]…, at least by imitation [imitationem]” (AT X 395, CSM I 29).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anstey, Peter. 2005. “Experimental versus Speculative Natural Philosophy,” in The Science of Nature in the Seventeenth Century: Patterns of Change in Early Modern Natural Philosophy, ed. Anstey, P. and Shuster, J.. Dordrecht: Springer, 215–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, Desmond. 1982. Descartes’ Philosophy of Science. University Park: Penn State University Press.Google Scholar
Gabbey, Alan. 1990. “Explanatory Structures and Models in Descartes’ Physics,” in Descartes: Il Methodo E I Saggi, ed. Belgioioso, G., Cimino, G., Costabel, P., and Papuli, G.. Rome: Enciclopedia Italiana, 273–86.Google Scholar
Galison, Peter. 1984. “Descartes's Comparisons,” Isis 75: 311–26.Google Scholar
Lauden, Laurens. 1966. “The Clock Metaphor and Probabilism: The Impact of Descartes on English Methodological Thought, 1650–1665,” Annals of Science 22: 73–104.Google Scholar
Lüthy, Christoph. 2006. “Where Logical Necessity Becomes Visual Persuasion: Descartes's Clear and Distinct Illustrations,” in Transmitting Knowledge: Words, Images, and Instruments in Early Modern Europe, ed. Kusukawa, S. and Maclean, I.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 97–137.Google Scholar
Manning, Gideon. 2012. “Analogy and Falsification in Descartes’ Physics,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 43: 402–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, Ernan. 2009. “Hypothesis in Early Modern Science,” in The Significance of the Hypothetical in the Natural Sciences, ed. Heidelberger, M. and Schiemann, G.. New York: Walter de Gruyter, 7–37.Google Scholar
McMullin, Ernan. 2008. “Explanation as Confirmation in Descartes’ Natural Philosophy,” in A Companion to Descartes, ed. Broughton, J. and Carriero, J.. Oxford: Blackwell, 84–102.Google Scholar
Palmerino, Carla Rita. 2002. “Bodies in Water like Planets in the Skies: Uses and Abuses of Analogical Reasoning in the Study of Planetary Motion,” in Mechanics and Cosmology in the Medieval and Early Modern Period, ed. Camerota, M., Bucciantini, M., and Roux, S.. Florence: Olschki, 145–68.Google Scholar
Sakelleriadis, Spyros. 1982. “Descartes’ Use of Empirical Data to Test Hypotheses,” Isis 73: 68–76.Google Scholar
Statile, Glenn. 1999. “The Necessity of Analogy in Cartesian Science,” Philosophical Forum 30: 217–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Analogy
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.006
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Analogy
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.006
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Analogy
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.006
Available formats
×