Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-17T14:45:45.771Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Language

from ENTRIES

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2016

Stefano di Bella
Affiliation:
Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa
Lawrence Nolan
Affiliation:
California State University, Long Beach
Get access

Summary

Descartes’ epistemology assigns a central role to mental contents or ideas. Language [loquela, langue] plays a secondary and auxiliary role – that is, for the storage and communication of previously constituted thoughts. From this perspective, the possession of “ideas” is seen as independent of, and prior to, their linguistic expression. Moreover, the direct inspection of ideas provides the criterion of meaning for a correct usage of words.

1.Ideas and Language

As a philosophical innovator, Descartes is bound to make use of a preexisting vocabulary – either ordinary or philosophical – while providing it with new meanings. Thus, in the Second Meditation, after gradually discovering the true notion of mind, he finally applies some common and traditional terms to it, but he is eager to stress that now they are given a novel and correct meaning: “I am … in the strict sense only a thing that thinks; that is, I am a mind, or intelligence, or intellect, or reason, words whose meaning I have been ignorant of until now” (AT VII 27, CSM II 18). Conversely, a few lines below he warns us that our language often perpetuates confused ways of thinking: “Although I am thinking about these matters within myself, silently and without speaking, nonetheless the actual words bring me up short, and I am almost tricked by ordinary ways of talking [decipior ab ipso usu loquendi]” (AT VII 31–32, CSM II 21). He adds that “one who wants to achieve knowledge above the ordinary level should feel ashamed at having taken ordinary ways of talking as a basis for doubt” (AT VII 32, CSM II 21). Actually, ordinary language incorporates in its meanings the confused notions originating from infancy. Moreover, it can mask our lack of understanding. The warning against the abuses of language is systematically developed in Principles I.74:

Because of the use of the language we tie all of our concepts to the words used to express them [loquela], and when we store the concepts in our memory we always simultaneously store the corresponding words. Later on we find the words easier to recall than the things; and because of this it is very seldom that our concept of a thing is so distinct that we can separate it totally from our concept of the words involved.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aarsleff, Hans. 1982. From Locke to Saussure: Essays on the History of Linguistics and Intellectual History.Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Cantelli, Giuanfranco. 1992. La parola come similitudine dell'uomo. Una interpretazione del rapporto mente-corpo in Cartesio.Naples: Morano.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 1966. Cartesian Linguistics: A Chapter in the History of Rationalist Thought. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Cottingham, John. 1997. “Thought and Language in Descartes,” in Thought and Language, ed. Preston, J.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 29–50.Google Scholar
Cottingham, John. 1978. “A ‘Brute to the Brutes’? Descartes’ Treatment of Animals,” Philosophy 53: 551–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gunderson, Keith. 1964. “Descartes, La Mettrie, Language and Machines,” Philosophy 39: 193–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Losonsky, Michael. 2006. Linguistic Turns in Modern Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthews, Gareth. 1986. “Descartes and the Problem of Other Minds,” in Essays on Descartes’ Meditations, ed. Rorty, A. O.. Berkeley: University of California Press, 223–41.Google Scholar
Percival, W. Keith. 1972. “On the Non-existence of Cartesian Linguistics,” in Cartesian Studies, ed. Butler, R.. Oxford: Blackwell, 137–45.Google Scholar
Rodis-Lewis, Geneviève. 1966. “Langage humain et signes naturels dans le cartésianisme,” in Le langage, Actes du XIII congrés des Sociétés de philosophie de langue française. Geneva, 132–36 (reprint, L'anthropologie cartésienne. Paris: PUF, 1990).Google Scholar
Séris, Jean-Pierre. 1995. Machine et langage à l’âge classique. Paris: Hachette.Google Scholar
Séris, Jean-Pierre. 1993. “Language and Machine in the Philosophy of Descartes,” in Essays on the Philosophy and Science of René Descartes, ed. Voss, S.. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 177–92.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Language
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.154
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Language
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.154
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Language
  • Edited by Lawrence Nolan, California State University, Long Beach
  • Book: The Cambridge Descartes Lexicon
  • Online publication: 05 January 2016
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511894695.154
Available formats
×