Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-xbtfd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T10:28:10.189Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

16 - Learning

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 April 2013

Scott Aaronson
Affiliation:
Massachusetts Institute of Technology
Get access

Summary

The puzzle from last chapter is known as Hume's Problem of Induction.

Puzzle: If you observe 500 black ravens, what basis do you have for supposing that the next one you observe will also be black?

Many people’s answer would be to apply Bayes’s Theorem. For this to work, though, we need to make some assumption such as that all the ravens are drawn from the same distribution. If we don’t assume that the future resembles the past at all, then it’s very difficult to get anything done. This kind of problem has led to lots of philosophical arguments like the following.

Suppose you see a bunch of emeralds, all of which are green. This would seem to lend support to the hypothesis that all emeralds are green. But then, define the word grue to mean “green before 2050 and blue afterwards.” Then, the evidence equally well supports the hypothesis that all emeralds are grue, not green. This is known as the grue paradox.

If you want to delve even “deeper,” then consider the “gavagai” paradox. Suppose that you’re trying to learn a language, and you’re an anthropologist visiting an Amazon tribe speaking the language. (Alternatively, maybe you’re a baby in the tribe. Either way, suppose you’re trying to learn the language from the tribe.) Then, suppose that some antelope runs by and some tribesman points to it and shouts “gavagai!” It seems reasonable to conclude from this that the word “gavagai” means “antelope” in their language, but how do you know that it doesn’t refer to just the antelope’s horn? Or it could be the name of the specific antelope that ran by. Worse still, it could mean that a specific antelope ran by on some given day of the week! There’s any number of situations that the tribesman could be using the word to refer to, and so we conclude that there is no way to learn the language, even if we spend an infinite amount of time with the tribe.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2013

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

A. Blumer, A. Ehrenfeucht, D. Haussler, and M. K. Warmuth, Learnability and the Vapnik-Chernonenkis dimension, Journal of the ACM 36:4 (1989), 929–965.
Aaronson, S., The learnability of quantum states. Proceedings of the Royal Society, A463 (2088), 2007.Google Scholar
J. Håstad, R. Impagliazzo, L. A. Levin, and M. Luby, A Pseudorandom Generator from any One-way Function. SIAM Journal on Computing 28:4 (1999), 1364–1396.
Goldreich, O., Goldwasser, S. and Micali, S., How to construct random functions. Journal of the ACM, 33:4 (1986), 792–807.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Learning
  • Scott Aaronson, Massachusetts Institute of Technology
  • Book: Quantum Computing since Democritus
  • Online publication: 05 April 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511979309.017
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Learning
  • Scott Aaronson, Massachusetts Institute of Technology
  • Book: Quantum Computing since Democritus
  • Online publication: 05 April 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511979309.017
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Learning
  • Scott Aaronson, Massachusetts Institute of Technology
  • Book: Quantum Computing since Democritus
  • Online publication: 05 April 2013
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511979309.017
Available formats
×