Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-k7p5g Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-16T02:54:44.632Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

4 - Aristotle

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

Lloyd P. Gerson
Affiliation:
University of Toronto
Get access

Summary

INTRODUCTION

Discussions of Aristotle's epistemology typically begin with the explicit or implicit assumption that, owing to his rejection of Plato's theory of Forms, Aristotle's thinking about knowledge and the objects of knowledge must be fundamentally different from Plato's. Indeed, if Forms do not exist, and if the motivation for radically separating knowledge and belief is just that cognising Forms is entirely different from cognising sensibles, that motivation is evidently not going to be shared by Aristotle. And yet Aristotle does repeatedly say, for example, that there is no knowledge of the objects of belief. He even maintains that there is no knowledge ‘by means of sense-perception’. So, one may well wonder whether Plato's point about the separation of knowledge and belief is a point that depends on a theory about Forms as opposed to a theory about the difference between what is intelligible and what is sensible generally. In the latter event, it is all the more interesting if it turns out that Aristotle – despite his substantial disagreements with Plato – agrees with his master's basic epistemological doctrines.

A terminological note is in order. In Republic as we have seen, Plato initially uses the term epistēmē for the two modes of cognition – noēsis and dianoia – in the top part of the Divided Line. He corrects this later on and limits the use of epistēmē to the highest portion, reserving the term noēsis for both.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Aristotle
  • Lloyd P. Gerson, University of Toronto
  • Book: Ancient Epistemology
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511801730.005
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Aristotle
  • Lloyd P. Gerson, University of Toronto
  • Book: Ancient Epistemology
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511801730.005
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Aristotle
  • Lloyd P. Gerson, University of Toronto
  • Book: Ancient Epistemology
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511801730.005
Available formats
×