Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-8zxtt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-09T07:50:37.346Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reception

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 January 2012

Andrea Falcon
Affiliation:
Concordia University, Montréal
Get access

Summary

Xenarchus and the reception of aristotle’s physics in antiquity

Xenarchus’ criticism of the thesis that the heavens are made of a special simple body, unique to them, was preserved and passed on to late antiquity by Alexander of Aphrodisias. Alexander is ultimately responsible for its integration into the ancient commentary tradition. The role that Xenarchus plays in this tradition can be usefully contrasted with the one played by Eudemus of Rhodes. Eudemus was not only a direct pupil of Aristotle; with the exception of Theophrastus, he was also the most prominent Peripatetic philosopher of his time. What we know about his Physics suggests that Eudemus followed the sequence of topic discussed in Aristotle's Physics very closely – so closely that it is tempting to consider him an interpreter (exegetês) of Aristotle's Physics. Because of what is perceived as loyalty to Aristotle, his views are often cited by Simplicius in his commentary on Aristotle's Physics. There, Eudemus is regarded as an exegetical aid in the exposition of Aristotle's text. By contrast, Xenarchus is treated as an adversary whose objections are to be answered in order to reaffirm the transcendence of the heavens. It is telling that his affiliation to the Peripatos is not recorded by Simplicius. This silence is symptomatic of the role that Xenarchus ended up playing in the commentary tradition. Seen through the lens of a pro-Aristotelian exegesis that ultimately goes back to Alexander of Aphrodisias, Xenarchus played the outsider within the Peripatetic tradition. This role does not do full justice to Xenarchus – or so I have argued.

A study of the reasons which may have led a Peripatetic philosopher like Xenarchus to criticize Aristotle's celestial physics helps us to better appreciate how unusual Aristotle's conception of the natural world was in antiquity. Several aspects of this conception were strongly resisted. But nothing generated more controversy than Aristotle's views on the material composition of the heavens. The mixed reception of these views indicates that his conception of the celestial world was truly exceptional, if not even anomalous. When we say that for Aristotle the natural world consisted of a celestial and a sublunary part, we do not do full justice to his position. In antiquity it was common to think of the celestial world as a somehow special region of the world. Stability and incorruptibility were often given as its differentiating features. In fact, the position recommended by Aristotle was much stronger than a generic commitment to the incorruptibility and stability of the celestial world. Aristotle was committed to the existence of material discontinuity between the celestial and the sublunary regions of this world. The so-called fifth substance or fifth body is not just different from earth, water, air, or fire. At least for Aristotle, this substance cannot be reduced to any of them. The expressions “fifth body” and “fifth substance,” which Aristotle never uses in his writings on natural philosophy, are themselves an indication of how many, if not most, people felt about Aristotle's celestial simple body in antiquity. They felt that this was an additional body, or an additional substance, alongside earth, water, air, and fire whose theoretical necessity was at best very dubious.

Type
Chapter
Information
Aristotelianism in the First Century BCE
Xenarchus of Seleucia
, pp. 167 - 198
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1928

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Reception
  • Andrea Falcon, Concordia University, Montréal
  • Book: Aristotelianism in the First Century BCE
  • Online publication: 05 January 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139025454.007
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Reception
  • Andrea Falcon, Concordia University, Montréal
  • Book: Aristotelianism in the First Century BCE
  • Online publication: 05 January 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139025454.007
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Reception
  • Andrea Falcon, Concordia University, Montréal
  • Book: Aristotelianism in the First Century BCE
  • Online publication: 05 January 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139025454.007
Available formats
×