Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-wxhwt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T14:29:09.832Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

35 - Happiness: the perfection of man

from IX - Ethics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Get access

Summary

The Aristotelian concept of happiness and the Christian tradition

The medieval discussion of happiness both before and after the reception of Aristotle is governed by two basic thoughts: there is no happiness in this world because ‘all men, so long as they are mortal, are also necessarily wretched’; true happiness is to be found only in the enjoyment of the contemplation of God (frui Deo) in the world to come. Thus the concept of happiness involves an element that transcends human capacities. But the Aristotelian and Christian conceptions also understand happiness as the perfection of human nature, the actualisation of the possibilities inherent in man. This rules out all definitions of happiness in terms of something like worldly wealth, which is external to human nature, or like the satisfaction of sensual desire, which is not specific to human nature. For Aristotle as for others the essence of happiness is to be found in perfection. It is in that spirit, for instance, that Anselm regards the contemplation of God as the perfection of human rationality, because without this form of happiness man would be rational to no purpose.

The difference between the Christian and the philosophical conception is particularly clear in the Dialogus inter philosophum, Iudaeum, et Christianum of Peter Abelard. While the philosophers speak only of ethics, aiming primarily for the way to the highest good, and accordingly deal mainly with the virtues, Christians take the goal itself as their starting point.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy
From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600
, pp. 673 - 686
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Boethius, (1957). Philosophiae consolatio, ed. Bieler, L. (Corpus Christianorum, Series Latina, 94), BrepolsGoogle Scholar
Boethius, Dacia (1936). De Summo Bono sive De Vita Philosophiae in Grabmann, M., Mittelalterliches Geistesleben, 2: Hüber, M.Google Scholar
Gauthier, R.-A. (1947–8). ‘Trois commentaires “averroistes” sur 1' Éthique à Nicomaque’, Archives d'histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen âge 22/23:Google Scholar
Gauthier, R.-A. (1975)- ‘Le cours sur l'Ethica nova d'un maître ès arts de Paris (1235–1240)’, AHDLMA 42:.Google Scholar
Honnefelder, L. (1975). ‘Duns Scotus: Der Schritt der Philosophic zur scientia trans-cenden’ in Kluxen, W. (ed.) Thomas von Aquin im philosophischen Gespräch, AlberGoogle Scholar
John, Buridan (1513) Quaestiones super decem libros Ethicorum, Paris (Reprinted Minerva 1968)Google Scholar
Kluxen, W. (1978). ‘Glück und Glücksteilhabe. Zur Rezeption der aristotelischen Glückslehre bei Thomas von Aquin’ in Bien, G. (ed.), Die Frage nach dem Glück, Frommann-HolzboogGoogle Scholar
Korolec, J. B. (1974b). ‘La philosophie de la liberté de jean Buridan’, Studia Mediewistyczne 15:.Google Scholar
Nardi, B. (1945). Sigieri di Brabante nel pensiero del Rinascimento Italiano, Edizioni ItalianeGoogle Scholar
Peter, Abelard (1970b). Dialogus inter Philosophum, Iudaeum, et Christianum, ed. Thomas, Rudolph, Frommann-HolzboogGoogle Scholar
Robert, Kilwardby (1935). De natura theologiae, ed. Stegmüller, F. (Opuscula et textus, Series scholastica, 17), AschendorffGoogle Scholar
Siger, Brabant (1948). Siger de Brabant. Questions sur la métaphysique (Quaestiones in Metaphysicam), ed. Graiff, C. A., Éditions de l'lnstitut Supérieur de Philosophie de LouvainGoogle Scholar
Thomas, Aquinas (1964b). In decern libros Ethkorum Aristotelis ad Nicomachum expositio, ed. Spiazzi, R. M. (3rd edn.), MariettiGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×