Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-7tdvq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-20T11:40:19.988Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

27 - The Oxford calculators

from VII - Natural philosophy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 March 2008

Get access

Summary

The identity and the writings of the Calculators or ‘Mertonians’

In the second quarter of the fourteenth century a collection of works was produced at Oxford whose joint impact on European natural philosophy lasted well into the sixteenth century. The works at the core of this collection are Thomas Bradwardine's De proportionibus velocitatum (1328), William Heytesbury's Regulae solvendi sophismata (1335), and Richard Swineshead's Liber calculationum (usually dated ca. 1350, but probably earlier). Other treatises were linked with these three through common interests and approaches in logic, in mathematics, and in physics or natural philosophy. Among the most closely linked works were Richard Kilvington's Sophismata, Walter Burley's De primo et ultimo instanti and Tractatus primus et secundus de formis accidentalibus (the Tractatus secundus is known better as De intensione et remissione formarum), Richard Billingham's Conclusiones, Heytesbury's Sophismata and the Probationes Conclusionum of his Regulae, Roger Swineshead's De motibus naturalibus, John Bode's treatise on the sophisma ‘A est unum calidum’ and others, the anonymous Sex inconvenientia, and John Dumbleton's Summa logicae et philosophiae naturalis, not to mention many treatises on the usual subjects of fourteenth-century logic – supposition, consequences, obligationes, insolubilia, etc. – or commentaries on Aristotle's physical works and other set books of the medieval curriculum.

Since many of the most famous authors of these works, including Bradwardine, Heytesbury, Richard Swineshead, Burley, Dumbleton, and possibly also Bode, had been fellows of Merton College, Oxford, some recent historians of science call this group of authors the Merton School, although there is little contemporary evidence that they were called Mertonians.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Philosophy
From the Rediscovery of Aristotle to the Disintegration of Scholasticism, 1100–1600
, pp. 540 - 563
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alvarus, Thomas (1509). Liber de triplici motu. ParisGoogle Scholar
Bottin, Francesco (1973). ‘Analisi linguistica e fisica Aristotelica nei “Sophismata” di Pochard Kilmyngton’ in Giacon, Carlo (ed.) Filosqfia Politico e altri saggi (Universitá di Padova, Pubblicazioni dell’ Istituto di Storia della Filosofia e del Centro per Ricerche di Filosofia Medioevale, n.s. 14), AntenoreGoogle Scholar
Clagett, Marshall (1941). Giovanni Marliani and Late Medieval Physics, ColumbiaUniversity PressGoogle Scholar
Clagett, Marshall (1959). The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages, University of Wisconsin PressGoogle Scholar
Clagett, Marshall(1950). ‘Richard Swineshead and Late Medieval Physics’, Osiris 9:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coleman, Janet (1975), ‘Jean de Ripa, O. F. M. and the Oxford Calculators’, Mediaeval Studies 37:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Courtenay, William J. (1978). Adam Wodeham. An Introduction to His Life and Writings, E.J. BrillGoogle Scholar
Crosby, H. Lamar Jr (1955). Thomas of Bradwardine: His Tractatus de Proportionibus; Its Significance for the Development of Mathematical Physics, (Publications in Medieval Science, 2), University of Wisconsin PressGoogle Scholar
Duhem, Pierre (1906–13). Études sur Léonard de Vinci (3 vols.), HermannGoogle Scholar
Gaetano, Di Thiene (1491). de reactione, veniceGoogle Scholar
Garin, E. (1969a). ‘La cultura fiorentina nella secunda meta dell Trecento e i “barbari Britanni”’, in his L'età nuova. Richerche di storia della cultura dal XII al XVI secolo, MoranoGoogle Scholar
Gibson, Strickland (1930). ‘The Order of Disputations’, Bodleian Quarterly Record 6:Google Scholar
Gibson, Strickland (1931). Statuta Antiqua Universitatis Oxoniensis, Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, Neal Ward (1976). ‘Richard de Bury and the “Quires of Yesterday's Sophisms”’, in Mahoney, Edward P. (ed.) Philosophy and Humanism. Renaissance Essays in Honor of Paul Oskar Kristeller, Columbia University PressGoogle Scholar
Glorieux, P. (1925–35). La littérature quodlibétique (2 vols.) (Bibliothéque Thomiste, 5, 21), J. VrinGoogle Scholar
Grabmann, Martin (1940a). Die Sophismataliteratur des 12. und 13. Jahrhunderts mit Textausgabe eines Sophisma des Boethius von Dacien (BGPM, XXXVI, 1), AschendorffGoogle Scholar
Guerlac, Rita (1979). Juan Luis Vives Against the Pseudodialecticians: A Humanist Attack on Medieval Logic (Synthese Historical Library, 18), ReidelCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gunther, Robert (1922–3). Early Science at Oxford (2 vols.) (Publications of the Oxford Historical Society, 77, 78),Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Knuuttila, Simo and Lehtinen, Anja Inkeri (1979). ‘Plato in Infinitum Remisse Incipit Esse Albus. New Texts on the Late Medieval Discussion on the Concept of Infinity in Sophismata Literature’, in Saarinen, E., Hilpinen, R., NÜNiluoto, I. and Hintikka, M. Provence (eds.) Essays in Honour of jaakko Hintikka, ReidelGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman (1976). ‘Incipit/Desinit’ in Machamer, P. and Turnbull, R. (eds.) Motion and Time, Space and Matter, Ohio State University PressGoogle Scholar
Kretzmann, Norman (1977). ‘Socrates is Whiter than Plato Begins to be White’, Noûs II:Google Scholar
Lewis, C.J. T. (1976). ‘The Fortunes of Richard Swineshead in the Time of Galileo’, Annals of Science 33:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Little, A. G., and Pelster, F. (1934). Oxford Theology and Theologians c. A. D. 1282–1302 (publications of the Oxford Historical Society, 96), Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Maier, Anneliese (1952). An der Crenze von Scholastik und Naturwissenschaft (Studien zur Naturphilosophie der Spätscholastik, vol. 3) (2nd ed.), Edizioni di Storia e LetteraturaGoogle Scholar
Maier, Anneliese (1964). ‘Diskussionen über das aktuell Unendliche in der ersten Hälfte des 14. Jahr-hunderts’ in Maier, (1964–7), vol. 1Google Scholar
Maier, Anneliese (1968). Zwei Grundprobleme der Scholastischen Naturphilosophie (Studien zur Naturphilosophie der Spätscholastik, vol. 2) (3rd ed.), Edizioni di Storia e LetteraturaGoogle Scholar
Michalski, K. (1922). ‘Les Courants philosophiques à Oxford et à Paris pendant le XIVesiècle’, Bulletin Internationale de I'Académie polonaise des sciences et des lettres, Classe d'histoire et de philosophie, et de philologie, les années 1919, 1920Google Scholar
Michalski, K. (1926). ‘Le Criticisme et le scepticisme dans la philosophie du XIVe siecle’, Bulletin internationale de I'Academie polonaise des sciences et des lettres, Classe d'histoire et de philosophie, et de philologie, l'année 1925Google Scholar
Molland, A. G. (1968a). ‘The Geometrical Background to the “Merton School”’, British Journal for the History of Science 4:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Molland, A. G. (1978). ‘An Examination of Bradwardine's Geometry’, Archive for History of Exact Sciences 19:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murdoch, John E. (1969). ‘Mathesis in Philosophiam Scholasticam Introducta. The Rise and Development of me Application of Mathematics in Fourteenth Century Philosophy and Theology’, in Arts Libéraux et Philosophie au Moyen Age, Actes du Quatrième Congrès International de Philosophie Médiévale, Montréal, Institut d'Études MédiévalesGoogle Scholar
Murdoch, John E. (1974a). ‘Philosophy and the Enterprise of Science in the Later Middle Ages’ in Elkana, Y. (ed.) The Interaction Between Science and Philosophy, Humanities PressGoogle Scholar
Murdoch, John E. (1975a). ‘From Social into Intellectual Factors: An Aspect of the Unitary Character of Late Medieval Learning’, in Murdoch, J. E. and Sylla, E. D. (eds.) The Cultural Context of Medieval Learning, ReidelCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murdoch, John E. (1978b). ‘Subtilitates Anglicanae in Fourteenth Century Paris: John of Mirecourt and Peter Ceffons’ in Cosman, Madeleine Pelner and Chandler, Bruce (eds.) Machaut's World. Science and Art in the Fourteenth Century (Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 314)Google Scholar
Murdoch, John E. (1979). ‘Prepositional Analysis in Fourteenth-Century Natural Philosophy’, Synthese 40:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murdoch, John E. (1976). ‘Swineshead, Richard’, in Gillispie, C. C. (ed.) Dictionary of Scientific Biography, Charles Scribner's SonsGoogle Scholar
Murdoch, John E. (1978). “The Science of Motion’ in Lindberg, David C. (ed.) Science in the Middle Ages, University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Pedersen, Olaf (1953). ‘The Development of Natural Philosophy 1250–1350’, Classica et Mediavalia 14:.Google Scholar
Pinborg, Jan (1975b). ‘Radulphus Brito's Sophism on Second Intentions’, Vivarium 13:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinborg, Jan (1979). ‘The English Contribution to Logic before Ockham’, Synthese 40:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rashdall, Hastings (1936). The Universities of Europe in the Middle Ages (2nd ed.), ed. Powicke, F. M. and Emden, A. B. (3 vols.), Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Richard, Swineshead (1520). Liber calculationum, VeniceGoogle Scholar
Rijk, L. M. ed. (1975). ‘Logica Cantabrigiensis – A Fifteenth-Century Cambridge Manual of Logic’, Revue internationale de philosophie, Grabmann, 29c année 113:Google Scholar
Shapiro, Herman (1959). ‘Walter Burley and the Intension and Remission of Forms’, Speculum 34:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, Herman and Charlotte, (1965). ‘De Primo et Ultimo Instanti des Walter Burley’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 47:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spade, Paul Vincent (1979b). William Heytesbury: On ‘Insoluble’ Sentences: Chapter One of His Rules for Solving Sophisms (Mediaeval Sources in Translation, 21), Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval StudiesGoogle Scholar
Sylla, Edith (1971). ‘Medieval Quantifications of Qualities: the “Merton School”’, Archive for History of Exact Sciences 8:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sylla, Edith (1973). ‘Medieval Concepts of the Latitude of Forms: The Oxford Calculators’, Archives d'histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen âge 40:Google Scholar
Sylla, Edith (1979). ‘The A Posteriori Foundations of Natural Science. Some Medieval Commentaries on Aristotle's Physics, Book I, Chapters 1 and 2’, Synthese 40:.Google Scholar
Thorndike, Lynn (1934). ‘Calculator and the Rise of Mathematics’, in his History of Magic and Experimental Science, vol. 3, Columbia University PressGoogle Scholar
Wallace, William A. (1969). ‘The “Calculatores” in Early Sixteenth-Century Physics’, The British Journal for the History of Science 4:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wallerand, G. (1913). Les Oeuvres de Siger de Courtrai (Les Philosophes Beiges, 8), Institut Supérieur Philosophie de l'Université de LouvainGoogle Scholar
Weisheipl, James A. (1959) ‘The place of John Dumbleton in the Merton School’, Isis 50:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weisheipl, James A. (1964a). ‘Curriculum of the Faculty of Arts at Oxford in the Early Fourteenth Century’, Mediaeval Studies 26:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weisheipl, James A. (1968). ‘Ockham and Some Mertonians’, Mediaeval Studies 30:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weisheipl, James A. (1969). ‘Repertorium Mertonense’, Mediaeval Studies 31:.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
William, Heytesbury (1494a). Tractatus Gulielmi Hentisberi de sensu composite et diviso, Regulae eiusdem cum Sophismatibus … VeniceGoogle Scholar
William, Heytesbury (1494b). Regulae solvendi sophismata in Heytesbury, William 1494a.Google Scholar
William, Heytesbury (1494c). Sophismata in Heytesbury, William 1494a.Google Scholar
Wilson, Curtis(1956). William Heytesbury: Medieval Logic and the Rise of Mathematical Physics (Publications in Medieval Science, 3), University of Wisconsin PressGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×