Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-gq7q9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-17T02:12:04.309Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

90 - Hegel, G. W. F.

from H

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 February 2015

Jon Mandle
Affiliation:
State University of New York, Albany
David A. Reidy
Affiliation:
University of Tennessee, Knoxville
Get access

Summary

Many still today consider John Rawls a straightforward Kantian and thus the degree to which his theory has been influenced by the thought of G. W. F. Hegel (1770–1831) goes largely unnoticed. Numerous communitarian thinkers (e.g. Alasdair MacIntyre, Charles Taylor and Michael Sandel) have criticized Rawls for his “individualism” and lack of an “adequate conception of community”– much in the manner Hegel criticized his predecessor Kant. Not only does A Theory of Justice have strong parallels to Hegel’s Philosophy of Right (1991 [1821]), however, but Rawls fully accepts a number of Hegel’s central criticisms of Kant. The former cites Hegel (and the British Idealist F. G. H. Bradley) numerous times in A Theory of Justice, and he lectured on Hegel at Harvard in the 1960s and again in the 1990s. So what is his theory’s relation to Hegel?

Rejecting the need to ground political philosophy in a metaphysical system (such as Hegel does with his monism, talk of one world spirit or Geist, etc.), Rawls considers his theory “political notmetaphysical” – a point emphasized in his later work (CP 388ff.). He denies that political philosophy needs any grounding in a comprehensive metaphysics for such systems generally underdetermine practical positions in political philosophy (CP 404 n.22); the materialist Hobbes and the idealist Hegel, after all, both end up defending monarchy. The aim of “justice as fairness” is farmoremodest; it is to provide a conception of justice that may serve as a public basis for the justiication of modern democratic institutions under conditions of pluralism and be supported by (at least) a “reasonable overlapping consensus” (CP 421ff.).

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×