Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-s9k8s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-08T04:20:57.973Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - Beyond Thick Confucian Communitarianism I: The Confucian Social Self and Its Discontent

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

Sungmoon Kim
Affiliation:
City University of Hong Kong
Get access

Summary

The recent resurgence of Confucianism in social and political theory is largely (if not exclusively) affiliated with the communitarian discontent and critique of liberalism in the West (particularly in North America) over the past two decades. Echoing Western communitarians who find fault with rights-based individualism as psychologically hollow (because of its assumption of the self-choosing, socially unencumbered self), ethically unpalatable (because of its priority of the right over the good), and politically undesirable (because of its tendency to erode communal bonds and civic virtue), recent Confucian political theorists criticize liberalism as too self-centered in its valorization of individual autonomy, will, choice, and (negative) freedom at the expense of communal solidarity and common good. Despite the still theoretically ambiguous connection between the democratic political regime and the communitarian society, many advocates of “Confucian democracy” recognize the communitarian elements in Confucianism as essential in the making of a viable Confucian democracy that is distinct from liberal individualistic democracy.

However, “Confucian communitarianism” as a political vision and practice is not without problems, the problems communitarianism is generally exposed to. Most important, it is still unclear whether communitarianism is theoretically superior to liberalism, or at least whether communitarianism can withstand the liberal critique of it. For instance, as far as I know, communitarians (including Confucian communitarians) have not yet successfully met the challenges that Stephen Holmes raised two decades ago. Holmes claims that while critiquing the liberal valorization of the unencumbered self, communitarians go to the other extreme by valorizing the “social self.” But why is the social self a better self than the autonomous self? Is “social” not a descriptive, rather than evaluative, term? Also, can sociality and individuality not be dialectically intertwined rather than starkly opposed by mediation of liberal political institutions and social practices? Then, are communitarians not confusing a particular version of liberal theory predicated on a speculative Cartesian epistemology of atomistic individualism with liberal social and political practice, which relies on a liberal education aimed at inculcating liberal virtues and characters? Are communitarians not mistaken when they think liberalism is essentially antisocial while the gist of liberalism lies in its reformulation (not abnegation) of the relationship between the self and society? Any attempt to justify Confucian communitarianism not merely as an antiliberal ideology but, more important, as a viable political vision and practicable theory, should be able to address (and overcome) these important challenges.

Type
Chapter
Information
Confucian Democracy in East Asia
Theory and Practice
, pp. 27 - 46
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Sandel, Michael B., Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982)Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael, Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality (New York: Basic Books, 1983)Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989)Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, 1984)Google Scholar
Fox, Russell A., “Confucian and Communitarian Responses to Liberal Democracy,” Review of Politics 59 (1997): 561–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, Daniel A., East Meets West: Human Rights and Democracy in East Asia (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, , Beyond Liberal Democracy: Political Thinking for an East Asian Context (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bary, Theodore de, Asian Values and Human Rights: A Confucian Communitarian Perspective (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998)Google Scholar
Hall, David L. and Ames, Roger T., The Democracy of the Dead: Dewey, Confucius, and the Hope for Democracy in China (Chicago: Open Court, 1999)Google Scholar
Tan, Sor-hoon, Confucian Democracy: A Deweyan Reconstruction (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2003)Google Scholar
Holmes, Stephen, “The Permanent Structure of Antiliberal Thought,” in Liberalism and Moral Life, ed. Rosenblum, Nancy L. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), 227–53Google Scholar
Macedo, Stephen, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon, 1990)Google Scholar
Gutmann, Amy, Democratic Education (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988)Google Scholar
Ames, Roger T. and Rosemont, Henry Jr., The Analects of Confucius: A Philosophical Translation (New York: Ballantine Books, 1998), 152Google Scholar
Fingarette, Herbert, Confucius: The Secular as Sacred (New York: Harper, 1972)Google Scholar
Li, Chenyang, “The Confucian Ideal of Harmony,” Philosophy East and West 56 (2006), 583–603CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chen, Albert H., “Mediation, Litigation, and Justice: Confucian Reflections in a Modern Liberal Society,” in Confucianism for the Modern World, ed. Bell, Daniel A. and Hahm, Chaibong (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 257–87Google Scholar
Tan, Sor-hoon, “From Cannibalism to Empowerment: An Analects-Inspired Attempt to Balance Community and Liberty,” Philosophy East and West 54 (2004), 52–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Sungmoon, “Self-Transformation and Civil Society: Lockean vs. Confucian,” Dao 8 (2009), 383–401Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, The Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Gregor, Mary J. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fan, Ruiping, “Self-Determination vs. Family-Determination: Two Incommensurable Principle of Autonomy,” Bioethics 11 (1997), 309–22CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tao, Julia and Brennan, Andrew, “Confucian and Liberal Ethics for Public Policy: Holistic or Atomistic?,” Journal of Social Philosophy 34 (2003), 572–89CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dewey, John, “The Ethics of Democracy,” in John Dewey: The Early Works, vol. 1, ed. Axetell, George E. and Boydston, Jo Ann (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1969), 231Google Scholar
Barber, Benjamin R., Fear’s Empire: War, Terrorism, and Democracy (New York: Norton, 2003), 88–91Google Scholar
Boyd, Richard, Uncivil Society: The Perils of Pluralism and the Making of Modern Liberalism (Lanham, MD: Lexington Books, 2004)Google Scholar
Flathman, Richard E., Thomas Hobbes: Skepticism, Individuality, and Chastened Politics (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2002)Google Scholar
Dunn, John, “The Contemporary Political Significance of John Locke’s Conception of Civil Society,” in Civil Society: History and Possibilities, ed. Kaviraj, Sudipta and Khilnani, Sunil (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001)Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo, The Political Philosophy of Hobbes: Its Basis and Its Genesis (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1952)Google Scholar
Ames, Roger T., “Confucianism: Confucius (Kongzi, K’ung Tzu),” in Encyclopedia of Chinese Philosophy, ed. Cua, Antonio S. (New York: Routledge, 2003), 61Google Scholar
Ames, Roger T., Confucian Role Ethics: A Vocabulary (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 2011)Google Scholar
Held, Virginia, The Ethics of Care: Personal, Political, Global (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006)Google Scholar
Li, Chenyang, “Shifting Perspectives: Filial Morality Revisited,” Philosophy East and West 47 (1997), 211–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Sungmoon, “Trouble with Korean Confucianism: Scholar-Official between Ideal and Reality,” Dao 8 (2009), 29–48, 43–4Google Scholar
Lai, Karyn, “Li in the Analects: Training in Moral Competence and the Question of Flexibility,” Philosophy East and West 56 (2006), 69–83CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tan, Sor-hoon, “Between Family and State: Relational Tensions in Confucian Ethics,” in Mencius: Contexts and Interpretations, ed. Chan, Alan K. L. (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 2002), 169–88Google Scholar
Villa, Dana, Socratic Citizenship (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001)Google Scholar
Hourdequin, Marion, “Engagement, Withdrawal, and Social Reform: Confucian and Contemporary Perspective,” Philosophy East and West 60 (2010), 369–90CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Sungmoon, “Confucian Citizenship? Against Two Greek Models,” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 37 (2010), 438–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eisenstadt, Shmuel N., “This Worldly Transcendentalism and the Structuring of the World: Max Weber’s ‘Religion of China’ and the Format of Chinese History and Civilization,” Journal of Developing Societies 1 (1985), 168–86Google Scholar
Schwartz, Benjamin I., “The Age of Transcendence,” in China and Other Matters (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), 64–8Google Scholar
Ivanhoe, Philip J., “Heaven as a Source for Ethical Warrant in Early Confucianism,” Dao 6 (2007), 211–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Rodney L., “The Religious Character of Confucian Tradition,” Philosophy East and West 48 (1998), 80–107CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weiming, Tu, Way, Learning, and Politics: Essays on the Confucian Intellectual (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1993), 10Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×