Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-tdptf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-16T11:23:46.965Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 September 2010

Mariska Leunissen
Affiliation:
Washington University, St Louis
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ackrill, J. L. (1981), “Aristotle's Theory of Definition: Some Questions on Posterior Analytics II.8–10,” in Berti, E. (ed.), Aristotle on Science: The Posterior Analytics, Proceedings of the 8th Symposium Aristotelicum, Padua, 359–384.Google Scholar
Anagnostopoulos, G. (ed.) (2009), A Companion to Aristotle, Blackwell Guides to Philosophy, Oxford.Google Scholar
Annas, J. (1982), “Aristotle on Inefficient Causes,” Philosophical Quarterly 32, 311–322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Apostle, H. G. (1981), Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, translated with Commentaries and Glossary, Grinnell, IA.Google Scholar
Balme, D. M. (1965), “Aristotle's Use of Teleological Explanation.” Paper presented at the Inaugural Lecture, Queen Mary College, University of London, London.
Balme, D. M. (1972), Aristotle's De Partibus Animalium I and De Generatione Animalium I (with Pages from II.1–3), Oxford.Google Scholar
Balme, D. M. (1980), “Aristotle's Biology was not Essentialist,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 62, 1–12; reprinted in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.) (1987), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 291–312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balme, D. M. (1987a), “The Place of Biology in Aristotle's Philosophy,” in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 9–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balme, D. M. (1987b), “Aristotle's Use of Division and Differentiae,” in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 69–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balme, D. M. (1987c), “Teleology and Necessity,” in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 275–286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, J. (1975), “Aristotle's Theory of Demonstration,” in Barnes, J., Schofield, M., and Sorabji, R. (eds.), Articles on Aristotle I: Science, London, 65–87.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1981), “Proof and the Syllogism,” in Berti, E. (ed.), Aristotle on Science: The Posterior Analytics, Proceedings of the 8th Symposium Aristotelicum, Padua, 17–59.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1987), “An Aristotelian Way with Scepticism,” in Matthen, M. (ed.), Aristotle Today, Essays on Aristotle's Ideal of Science, Edmonton, AB, 51–76.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1993), Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, Oxford.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (ed.) (1995), The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Barnes, J. (1999), “Review of S. Everson, Aristotle on Perception,” Classical Review, NS 49, 120–122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, J., M. Schofield, and Sorabji, R. (eds.) (1975), Articles on Aristotle I: Science, London.Google Scholar
Bayer, G. (1998), “Classification and Explanation in Aristotle's Theory of Definition,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 36, 487–505.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bekker, I. (ed.) (1831), Aristotelis Opera, Berlin.Google Scholar
Berti, E. (ed.) (1981), Aristotle on Science: The Posterior Analytics, Proceedings of the 8th Symposium Aristotelicum, Padua.Google Scholar
Berti, E. (1989–90), “La Finalità in Aristotele,” Fondamenti14–16, 8–44.Google Scholar
Bobzien, S. (2002), “The Development of Modus Ponens in Antiquity: From Aristotle to the 2nd Century AD,” Phronesis 47.4, 359–394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bodnár, I. (2005), “Teleology across Natures,” Rhizai 2, 9–29.Google Scholar
Bodnár, I. (2006), “Aristotle's Philosophy of Nature,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 1–12.
Bodnár, I. and Pellegrin, P. (2006), “Aristotle's Physics and Cosmology,” in Gill, M. L. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, Blackwell Companions to Philosophy, Malden, MA, 270–291.Google Scholar
Boeri, M. D. (1995), “Change and Teleology in Aristotle Physics,” International Philosophical Quarterly 34, 87–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bogen, J. and McGuire, J. E. (1986–7), “Aristotle's Great Clock: Necessity, Possibility and the Motion of the Cosmos in De Caelo I.12,” Philosophy Research Archives 12, 387–448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolotin, D. (1998), An Approach to Aristotle's Physics: With Particular Attention to the Role of His Manner of Writing, Albany, NY.Google Scholar
Bolton, R. (1987), “Definition and Scientific Method in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics and Generation of Animals,” in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 120–166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bolton, R. (1991), “Aristotle's Method in Natural Science: Physics I,” in Judson, L. (ed.), Aristotle's Physics, A Collection of Essays, Oxford, 2–29.Google Scholar
Bolton, R. (1997), “The Material Cause: Matter and Explanation in Aristotle's Natural Science,” in Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.), Aristotelische Biologie: Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, Stuttgart, 97–124.Google Scholar
Bolton, R. (2002), “Substance and the Definition of Definition in Aristotle,” in Canto-Sperber, M. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Le style de la pensée: recueil des textes en hommage à Jacques Brunschwig, Paris, 155–181.Google Scholar
Bolton, R. (2004), “Causal Explanation and Demonstrative Knowledge in Aristotle,” unpublished paper.
Bolton, R. (2009), “Two Standards for Inquiry in Aristotle's De Caelo,” in Bowen, A. C. and Wildberg, C. (eds.), New Perspectives on Aristotle's De Caelo, Leiden, 52–87.Google Scholar
Bonitz, H. (1870), Index Aristotelicus, 2nd edn, Berlin (reprinted Graz, 1955).Google Scholar
Bos, A. P. (2001), “Aristotle's De anima II, 1: The Traditional Interpretation Rejected,” in Sfendoni-Mentzou, D., Hattiangadi, J., and Johnson, D. M. (eds.), Aristotle and Contemporary Science, vol. II, Frankfurt am Main, 187–201.Google Scholar
Bos, A. P. and Ferwerda, R. (2008), Aristotle, On the Life-Bearing Spirit (De Spiritu) – A Discussion with Plato and his Predecessors on Pneuma as the Instrumental Body of the Soul, Leiden and Boston.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bostock, D. (2006), Space, Time, Matter, and Form: Essays on Aristotle's Physics, Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowen, A. C. (ed.) (1991), Science and Philosophy in Classical Greece, New York.Google Scholar
Bowen, A. C. and Wildberg, C. (eds.) (2009), New Perspectives on Aristotle's De Caelo, Leiden.Google Scholar
Boylan, M. (1983), Method and Practice in Aristotle's Biology, Lanham, MD, and London.Google Scholar
Boylan, M. (1984), “The Place of Nature in Aristotle's Teleology,” Apeiron 18, 126–140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradie, M. and Miller, F. D.. (1999), “Teleology and Natural Necessity,” in Gerson, L. P. (ed.), Aristotle, Critical Assessments, London, 75–89; reprint from (1984) History of Philosophy Quarterly 1, 133–146.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. (1990), “Nature and Craft in Aristotelian Teleology,” in Devereux, D. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote, Paris, 389–403.Google Scholar
Broadie, S. (1996), “Nous and Nature in De Anima III,” in Cleary, J. J. and Wians, W. (eds.), Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 12, 163–176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buller, D. J. (ed.) (1999), Function, Selection, and Design, New York.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (1981), “Aristotle on Understanding Knowledge,” in Berti, E. (ed.), Aristotle on Science: The Posterior Analytics, Proceedings of the 8th Symposium Aristotelicum, Padua, 97–139.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (1992a), “Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind still Credible? (A Draft),” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 15–26.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (1992b), “How Much Happens When Aristotle Sees Red and Hears Middle C? Remarks On De Anima 2.7–8,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 421–434.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (2001), A Map of Metaphysics Zeta, Pittsburgh.Google Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (2002), “De Anima II.5,” Phronesis 47.1, 28–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnyeat, M. F. (2004), “Introduction: Aristotle on the Foundations of Sublunary Physics,” in Haas, F. A. J. and Mansfeld, J. (eds.), Aristotle's On Generation and Corruption I Book 1, Symposium Aristotelicum, Oxford, 7–24.Google Scholar
Byl, S. (1971), “Note sur la polysémie d'Organon et sur les origines du finalisme,” L'Antiquité Classique 40, 121–133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, C. (2002), “Aristotle on Physical Necessity and the Limits of Teleological Explanation,” Apeiron 35, 20–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Byrne, P. H. (1997), Analysis and Science in Aristotle, Albany, NY.Google Scholar
Cameron, R. (2002), “The Ontology of Aristotle's Final Cause,” Apeiron 35, 153–179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Canto-Sperber, M. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.) (2002), Le style de la pensée: recueil des textes en hommage à Jacques Brunschwig, Paris.Google Scholar
Caston, V. (1996), “Aristotle on the Relation of the Intellect to the Body: Commentary on Broadie,” in Cleary, J. J. and Wians, W. (eds.), Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 12, 177–191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caston, V. (2005), “The Spirit and the Letter: Aristotle on Perception,” in Salles, R. (ed.), Metaphysics, Soul, and Ethics: Festschrift for Richard Sorabji, Oxford, 245–320.Google Scholar
Caston, V. (2006), “Aristotle's Psychology,” in Gill, M. L. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, Blackwell Companions to Philosophy Series, London, 316–346.Google Scholar
Catan, J. R. (ed.) (1981), Aristotle: The Collected Papers of J. Owens, New York.Google Scholar
Charles, D. (1984), Aristotle's Philosophy of Action, Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Charles, D. (1988), “Aristotle on Hypothetical Necessity and Irreducibility,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 69, 1–53; reprinted in Irwin, T. (ed.) (1995), Classical Philosophy: Collected Papers, New York and London, 27–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Charles, D. (1991), “Teleological Causation in the Physics,” in Judson, L. (ed.), Aristotle's Physics: A Collection of Essays, Oxford, 101–128.Google Scholar
Charles, D. (1994), “Matter and Form: Unity, Persistence, and Identity,” in Scaltsas, T., Charles, D., and Gill, M. L. (eds.), Unity, Identity, and Explanation in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Oxford, 75–105.Google Scholar
Charles, D. (1997), “Aristotle and the Unity and Essence of Biological Kinds,” in Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.), Aristotelische Biologie: Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, Stuttgart, 27–42.Google Scholar
Charles, D. (1999), “Aristotle on Substance, Essence and Biological Kinds,” in Gerson, L. P. (ed.), Aristotle: Critical Assessments, London, 227–255.Google Scholar
Charles, D. (2000), Aristotle on Meaning and Essence, Oxford.Google Scholar
Charlton, W. (1970), Aristotle's Physics I and II, Oxford.Google Scholar
Cherniss, H. (1935; reprinted 1971), Aristotle's Criticism of Presocratic Philosophy, New York.Google Scholar
Code, A. (1987), “Soul as Efficient Cause in Aristotle's Embryology,” Philosophical Topics 15, 51–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Code, A. (1997), “The Priority of Final Causes over Efficient Causes in Aristotle's Parts of Animals,' in Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.), Aristotelische Biologie: Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, Stuttgart, 127–143.Google Scholar
Code, A. and Moravcsik, J. (1992), “Explaining Various Forms of Living,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 129–145.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. M. (1989), “Aristotle on Heat, Cold, and Teleological Explanation,” Ancient Philosophy 9, 255–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S. M. (1992), “Hylomorphism and Functionalism,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 57–73.Google Scholar
Cohen, S. M. (1996), Aristotle on Nature and Incomplete Substance, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coles, A. (1990), “Animal and Childhood Cognition in Aristotle's Biology and the Scala Naturae,” in Devereux, D. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote, Paris, 287–323.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. (1975), Reason and Human Good in Aristotle, Cambridge and London.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. (1982), “Aristotle on Natural Teleology,” in Schofield, M. and Nussbaum, M. (eds.), Language and Logos, Cambridge, 197–222; reprinted in J. M. Cooper (2004), Knowledge, Nature and the Good: Essays on Ancient Philosophy, Princeton, NJ, 107–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, J. M. (1985), “Hypothetical Necessity,” in Gotthelf, A. (ed.), Aristotle on Nature and Living Things, Bristol, 150–167; reprinted in J. M. Cooper (2004), Knowledge, Nature and the Good: Essays on Ancient Philosophy, Princeton, NJ, 130–147.Google Scholar
Cooper, J. M. (1987), “Hypothetical Necessity and Natural Teleology,” in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 243–274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, J. M. (1990), “Metaphysics in Aristotle's Embryology,” in Devereux, D. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote, Paris, 55–84.Google Scholar
Corcilius, K. (2008a), “Praktische Syllogismen bei Aristoteles,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 90.2, 247–297.Google Scholar
Corcilius, K. (2008b), “Aristoteles' praktische Syllogismen in der zweiten Hälfte des 20. Jahrhunderts,” Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 11, 101–132.Google Scholar
Corcilius, K. (2008c), “Two Jobs for Aristotle's Practical Syllogism?,” Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 11, 163–184.Google Scholar
Cornford, F. M. (1975), Plato's Cosmology, Indianapolis, IN.Google Scholar
Cummins, R. (1999), “Functional Analysis,” in Buller, D. J. (ed.), Function, Selection, and Design, New York, 57–83.Google Scholar
DeMoss, D. and Devereux, D. (1988), “Essence, Existence, and Nominal Definition in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics II.8–10,” Phronesis 33, 133–154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Depew, D. (1995), “Humans and other Political Animals in Aristotle's History of Animals,” Phronesis 40, 156–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Depew, D. (1997), “Etiological Approaches to Biological Aptness in Aristotle and Darwin,” in Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.), Aristotelische Biologie, Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, Stuttgart, 209–227.Google Scholar
Deslauriers, M. (2007), Aristotle on Definition, Leiden.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Detel, W. (1993), Aristoteles Analytica Posteriora, Berlin.Google Scholar
Detel, W. (1997), “Why all Animals have a Stomach: Demonstration and Axiomatization in Aristotle's Parts of Animals,” in Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.), Aristotelische Biologie: Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, Stuttgart, 63–84.Google Scholar
Detel, W. (1999), “Aristotle on Zoological Explanation,” Philosophical Topics 25, 43–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Detel, W. (2006), “Aristotle's Logic and Theory of Science,” in Gill, M. L. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, Blackwell Companions to Philosophy, Malden, MA, 245–269.Google Scholar
Devereux, D. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.) (1990), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote, Paris.Google Scholar
Dudley, J. (1997), The Evolution of the Concept of Change in the Physics and Ethics of Aristotle: A Commentary on Phys II, IV–VI, Nijmegen.Google Scholar
Düring, I. (ed.) (1969), Naturphilosophie bei Aristoteles und Theophrast, 4th Symposium Aristotelicum, Heidelberg.Google Scholar
Eijk, Der, Ph. J. (1997), “The Matter of Mind: Aristotle on the Biology of ‘Psychic’ Processes,” in Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.), Aristotelische Biologie: Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, Stuttgart, 231–258.Google Scholar
Eijk, Der, Ph. J. (2001), Diocles of Carystus: A Collection of the Fragments with Translation and Commentary, Leiden.Google Scholar
Everson, S. (1997), Aristotle on Perception, Oxford.Google Scholar
Falcon, A. (2005), Aristotle and the Science of Nature: Unity without Uniformity, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Falcon, A. (2006), “Aristotle on Causality,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 1–11.Google Scholar
Ferejohn, M. (1990), The Origins of Aristotelian Science, New Haven, CT.Google Scholar
Ferguson, J. (1985), “Teleology in Aristotle's Politics,” in Gotthelf, A. (ed.), Aristotle on Nature and Living Things, Bristol, 259–276.Google Scholar
Fine, G. (1987), “Forms as Causes: Plato and Aristotle,” in Graeser, A. (ed.), Mathematics and Metaphysics in Aristotle, Bern, 69–112.Google Scholar
Fortenbaugh, W. W. (1966), “Nicomachean Ethics I, 1096b26–29,” Phronesis 11.2, 185–194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fortenbaugh, W. W., Huby, P. M. and Long, A. A. (eds.) (1985), Theophrastus of Eresus: On his Life and Work, New Brunswick, NJ.Google Scholar
Fraassen, van, B. (1980), “A Re-examination of Aristotle's Philosophy of Science,” Dialogue 19, 20–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frede, D. (1992), “The Cognitive Role of Phantasia in Aristotle,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 279–295.Google Scholar
Frede, M. (1980), “The Original Notion of Cause,” in Schofield, M., Burnyeat, M., and Barnes, J. (eds.), Doubt and Dogmatism: Studies in Hellenistic Epistemology, Oxford, 217–249.Google Scholar
Frede, M. (1992), “On Aristotle's Conception of the Soul,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 93–107.Google Scholar
Frede, M. and Patzig, G. (1988), Aristoteles, Metaphysik Z, 2 vols., Munich.Google Scholar
Frede, M. and Stricker, G. (eds.) (1996), Rationality in Greek Thought, Oxford.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. A. (1990), “Scientific Explanation and Empirical Data in Aristotle's Meteorology,” in Devereux, D. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote, Paris, 287–320.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. A. (1991), “Accidental Causes and Real Explanations,” in Judson, L. (ed.), Aristotle's Physics: A Collection of Essays, Oxford, 49–72.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. A. (1992), “Aristotle on the Sense of Touch,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 227–248.Google Scholar
Freeland, C. A. (1995), “Aristotle on Perception, Appetition, and Self-Motion,” in Gill, M. L. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Self-motion from Aristotle to Newton, Princeton, NJ, 35–63.Google Scholar
Friedman, R. (1983), “Matter and Necessity in Physics B 9, 200 a 15–30,” Ancient Philosophy 1, 8–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Furley, D. J. (1985), “The Rainfall Example in Physics II.8,” in Gotthelf, A. (ed.), Aristotle on Nature and Living Things, Pittsburgh, PA, 177–182; reprinted in D. J. Furley (1989), Cosmic Problems, Cambridge, 115–120.Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. (1989), Cosmic Problems, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. (1994), “Self-Movers,” in Gill, M. L. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Self-Motion From Aristotle to Newton, Princeton, NJ, 3–14.Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. (1996), “What Kind of Cause is Aristotle's Final Cause?,” in Frede, M. and Stricker, G. (eds.), Rationality in Greek Thought, Oxford, 59–79.Google Scholar
Furley, D. J. (2004), “Aristotle and the Atomists on Forms and Final Causes,” in Sharples, R. W. (ed.), Perspectives on Greek Philosophy, Aldershot and Burlington, VT, 70–84.Google Scholar
Furth, M. (1987), “Aristotle's Biological Universe: An Overview,” in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 21–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaiser, K. (1969), “Das zweifache Telos bei Aristoteles,” in Düring, I. (ed.), Naturphilosophie bei Aristoteles und Theophrast, 4th Symposium Aristotelicum, Heidelberg, 97–113.Google Scholar
Gallop, D. (1988), “Aristotle on Sleep, Dreams, and Final Causes,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 4, 257–290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gerson, L. P. (ed.) (2005), Aristotle and Other Platonists, Ithaca, NY, and London.Google Scholar
Gerson, L. P. (1999), Aristotle: Critical Assessments, London.Google Scholar
Gentzler, J. (ed.), Method in Ancient Philosophy, Oxford.
Gill, M. L. (1980), “Aristotle's Theory of Causal Action in Physics III.3,” Phronesis 25, 129–147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gill, M. L. (1991), “Aristotle on Self-Motion,” in Judson, L. (ed.), Aristotle's Physics: A Collection of Essays, Oxford, 243–265.Google Scholar
Gill, M. L. (1997), “Material Necessity and Meteorology IV.12,” in Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.), Aristotelische Biologie, Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, Stuttgart, 145–161.Google Scholar
Gill, M. L. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.) (1995), Self-motion from Aristotle to Newton, Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Gill, M. L. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.) (2006), A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, Blackwell Companions to Philosophy, Malden, MA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldin, O. (1996), Explaining an Eclipse: Aristotle's Posterior Analytics 2.1–10, Ann Harbor, MI.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (1976–7), “Aristotle's Conception of Final Causality,” Review of Metaphysics 30, 226–254; reprinted with additional notes and a postscript in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.) (1987), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 204–242.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (1980). “Review of M. C. Nussbaum, Aristotle's De Motu Animalium,” Journal of Philosophy 77, 365–378.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (ed.) (1985), Aristotle on Nature and Living Things (Philosophical and Historical Studies Presented to David M. Balme on his Seventieth Birthday), Pittsburgh, PA, and Bristol.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (1987), “First Principles in Aristotle's Parts of Animals,” in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 167–198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (1988), “The Place of the Good in Aristotle's Teleology,” in Cleary, J. J. and Shartin, D. C. (eds.), Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 4, 113–139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (1989), “Teleology and Spontaneous Generation: A Discussion,” in Kraut, R. and Penner, T. (eds.), Nature, Knowledge and Virtue: Apeiron, Special Issue 22.4, 181–193.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (1997a), “The Elephant's Nose: Further Reflections on the Axiomatic Structure of Biological Explanations in Aristotle,” in Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.), Aristotelische Biologie: Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, Stuttgart, 85–95.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. (1997b), “Understanding Aristotle's Teleology,” in Hassing, R. (ed.), Final Causality in Nature and Human Affairs, Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy 30, Washington DC, 71–82.Google Scholar
Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.) (1987), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graeser, A. (ed.), Mathematics and Metaphysics in Aristotle, Bern.
Granger, H. (1993), “Aristotle on the Analogy between Action and Nature,” Classical Quarterly 43, 168–176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grene, M. and Depew, D. (2004), The Philosophy of Biology: An Episodic History, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guthrie, W. K. C. (1939), Aristotle: On the Heavens, London.Google Scholar
Hamlyn, D. W. (2001), Aristotle De Anima, Books II and III (with Passages from Book I), translated with introduction and notes, with a report on recent work and a revised bibliography by Christopher Shields, Oxford.Google Scholar
Hankinson, R. J. (1995a), “Philosophy of Science,” in Barnes, J. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, Cambridge, 109–139.Google Scholar
Hankinson, R. J. (1995b), “Science,” in Barnes, J. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle, Cambridge, 140–167.Google Scholar
Hankinson, R. J. (1998), Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought, Oxford.Google Scholar
Hankinson, R. J. (2002–3), “Xenarchus, Alexander, and Simplicius on Simple Motions, Bodies and Magnitudes,” Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies 46, 19–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hankinson, R. J. (2009), “Natural, Unnatural, and Preternatural Motions: Contrariety and the Argument for the Elements in De Caelo 1.2–4,” in Bowen, A. C. and Wildberg, C. (eds.), New Perspectives on Aristotle's De Caelo, Leiden, 89–132.Google Scholar
Hassing, R. (ed.) (1997), Final Causality in Nature and Human Affairs, Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy 30, Washington DC.Google Scholar
Heath, Sir T. L. (1932), Greek Astronomy, New York.Google Scholar
Henry, D. (2006), “Understanding Aristotle's Reproductive Hylomorphism,” Apeiron 39.3, 257–287.Google Scholar
Hett, W. S. (1936), Aristotle On the Soul, Parva Naturalia, On Breath, Cambridge and London.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J. (1989), “Concepts of Scientific Method from Aristotle to Newton,” in Asztalos, M., Murdoch, J. and Niiniluoto, I. (eds.), Proceedings of the 1987 Congress of Medieval Philosophy, Acta Philosophica Fennica, Societas Philosophica Fennica, Helsinki, 72–84.Google Scholar
Hocutt, M. (1974), “Aristotle's Four Becauses,” Philosophy 49, 385–399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hutchinson, D. S. (1987), “Restoring the Order of Aristotle's De Anima,” Classical Quarterly 37, 373–381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ierodiakonou, K. (2005), “Ancient Thought Experiments: A First Approach,” Ancient Philosophy 25, 125–140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, T. (1988), Aristotle's First Principles, Oxford.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. (1998), Aristotle on the Sense-Organs, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Johansen, T. K. (2004), Plato's Natural Philosophy: A Study of the Timaeus-Critias, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johansen, T. K. (2009), “From Plato's Timaeus to Aristotle's De caelo: The Case of the Missing World Soul,” in Bowen, A. C. and Wildberg, C. (eds.), New Perspectives on Aristotle's De Caelo, Leiden, 1–24.Google Scholar
Johnson, M. R. (2005), Aristotle on Teleology, Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Judson, L. (ed.) (1991a), Aristotle's Physics: A Collection of Essays, Oxford.Google Scholar
Judson, L. (1991b), “Chance and Always or for the most Part,” Judson, L. (ed.), Aristotle's Physics: A Collection of Essays, Oxford, 73–100.Google Scholar
Judson, L. (2005), “Aristotelian Teleology,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 29, 341–366.Google Scholar
Kahn, C. H. (1985), “The Place of the Prime Mover in Aristotle's Teleology,” in Gotthelf, A. (ed.), Aristotle on Nature and Living Things, Pittsburgh, PA, and Bristol, 183–205.Google Scholar
Katayama, E. G. (1999), Aristotle on Artifacts: A Metaphysical Puzzle, New York.Google Scholar
Kelsey, S. (2003), “Aristotle's Definition of Nature,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 25, 59–87.Google Scholar
Kosman, L. A. (1987), “Animals and Other Beings in Aristotle,” in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 360–391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. and Penner, T. (eds.) (1989), Nature, Knowledge and Virtue: Apeiron, Special Issue 22.4.
Kullmann, W. (1974), Wissenschaft und Methode, Interpretationen zur Aristotelischen Theorie der Naturwissenschaft, Berlin.Google Scholar
Kullmann, W. (1979), Die Teleologie in der Aristotelischen Biologie: Aristoteles als Zoologe, Embryologe und Genetiker, Heidelberg.Google Scholar
Kullmann, W. (1985), “Different Concepts of the Final Cause in Aristotle,” in Gotthelf, A. (ed.), Aristotle on Nature and Living Things, Pittsburgh, PA, 170–175.Google Scholar
Kullmann, W. (1990), “Bipartite Science in Aristotle's Biology,” in Devereux, D. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote, Paris, 335–347.Google Scholar
Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.) (1997), Aristotelische Biologie: Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, Stuttgart.Google Scholar
Kupreeva, I. (forthcoming), “Causation and Conditional Necessity: Analytica Posteriora (Posterior Analytics). II 12,” in Haas, F. A. J., Leunissen, M., and Martijn, M. (eds.), Interpreting Aristotle's Posterior Analytics in Late Antiquity and the Byzantine Period, Leiden.
Lang, H. S. (1989), “Aristotelian Physics: Teleological Procedure in Aristotle, Thomas, and Buridan,” Review of Metaphysics 42, 569–591.Google Scholar
Lang, H. S. (1998), The Order of Nature in Aristotle's Physics: Place and the Elements, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leggatt, S. (1995), Aristotle On the Heavens I&II, with an introduction, translation and commentary, Warminster.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1982), “Teleology, Chance, and Aristotle's Theory of Spontaneous Generation,” Journal of History of Philosophy 20, 219–238; reprinted in J. G. Lennox (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, 229–249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1984), “Aristotle on Chance,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 66, 52–60; reprinted in J. G. Lennox (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, 250–258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1985a), “Plato's Unnatural Teleology,” Studies in Philosophy and the History of Philosophy 13, 195–218; reprinted in J. G. Lennox (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, 280–302.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1985b), “Theophrastus on the Limits of Teleology,” in Fortenbaugh, W. W., Huby, P. M. and Long, A. A. (eds.), Theophrastus of Eresus: on his Life and Work, New Brunswick, NJ, 143–163; reprinted in J. G. Lennox (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, 259–279.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1985c), “Are Aristotelian Species Eternal?,” in Gotthelf, A. (ed.), Aristotle on Nature and Living Things, Pittsburgh, PA, and Bristol, 67–94; reprinted in J. G. Lennox (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, 131–159.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1987a), “Divide and Explain: The Posterior Analytics in Practice,” in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.) (1987), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 90–119; reprinted in J. G. Lennox (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, 7–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1987b), “Kinds, Forms of Kinds, and the More and the Less in Aristotle's Biology,” in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.) (1987), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 339–359; reprinted in J. G. Lennox (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, 160–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1990), “Notes on David Charles on Historia Animalium (History of Animals),” in Devereux, D. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote, Paris, 169–183.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1991), “Between Data and Demonstration: The Analytics and the Historia Animalium,” in Bowen, A. (ed.), Science and Philosophy in Classical Greece, New York, 261–295; reprinted in J. G. Lennox (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, 39–71.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1994), “Aristotelian Problems,” Ancient Philosophy 14, 53–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1996a), “Material and Formal Natures in Aristotle's De Partibus Animalium,” in Cleary, J. J. and Wians, W. (eds.), Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 12; reprinted in J. G. Lennox (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, 182–204.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1996b), “Aristotle's Biological Development: The Balme Hypothesis,” in Wians, W. (ed.), Aristotle's Philosophical Development, Problems and Prospects, London, 229–248.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1997a), “Putting Philosophy of Science to the Test: The Case of Aristotle's Biology,” in Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.), Aristotelische Biologie: Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, Stuttgart, 163–182; reprinted in J. G. Lennox (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, 98–109.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1997b), “Nature Does Nothing in Vain,” in Günther, H.-C. and Rengakos, A. (eds.), Beitraege zur antiken Philosophie: Festschrift für Wolfgang Kullmann (mit einer Einleitung von Ernst Vogt), Stuttgart, 199–214; reprinted in J. G. Lennox (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology, Cambridge, 205–223.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (1999), “The Place of Mankind in Aristotle's Zoology,” Philosophical Topics 27, 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (2001a), Aristotle's Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Science, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (2001b), Aristotle on the Parts of Animals I–IV, translated with an introduction and commentary by J. G. Lennox, Oxford.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (2001c), “Aristotle on the Unity and Disunity of Science,” International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15.2, 133–144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (2004a), “The Place of Zoology in Aristotle's Natural Philosophy,” in Sharples, R. W. (ed.), Philosophy and the Sciences in Antiquity, London, 58–70.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (2004b), “Getting A Science Going: Aristotle on Entry Level Kinds,” in Wolters, G. (ed.), Homo Sapiens und Homo Faber (Festschrift Mittelstrass), Berlin, 87–100.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (2006), “Aristotle's Biology and Aristotle's Philosophy,” in Gill, M. L. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), A Companion to Ancient Philosophy, Blackwell Companions to Philosophy Series, London, 292–315.Google Scholar
Lennox, J. G. (2009), “De caelo 2.2 and its Debt to De incessu animalium,” in Bowen, A. C. and Wildberg, C. (eds.), New Perspectives on Aristotle's De Caelo, Leiden, 211–243.Google Scholar
Leunissen, M. (2007), “The Structure of Teleological Explanations in Aristotle: Theory and Practice,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 33, 145–178.Google Scholar
Leunissen, M. (2009), “Why Stars have no Feet: Teleological Explanations in Aristotle's Cosmology,” in Bowen, A. C. and Wildberg, C. (eds.), New Perspectives on Aristotle's De Caelo, Leiden, 245–271.Google Scholar
Leunissen, M. (2010), “Aristotle's Syllogistic Model of Knowledge and the Biological Sciences: Demonstrating Natural Processes,” in Lesher, J. (ed.), Apeiron, Special Issue: “From Inquiry to Demonstrative Knowledge: New Essays on Aristotle's Posterior Analytics” 43.2–3.CrossRef
Leunissen, M. and Gotthelf, A. (2010), “What's Teleology Got to Do with It? A Reinterpretation of Aristotle's Generation of Animals V,” Phronesis 55.
Lewis, F. A. (1988), “Teleology and Material/Efficient Causes in Aristotle,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 69, 54–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Liatsi, M. (2000), Aristoteles, De Generatione Animalium, Buch V, Einleitung und Kommentar, Trier.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1966), Polarity and Analogy: Two Types of Argumentation in Early Greek Thought, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1978), “The Empirical Basis of the Physiology of the Parva Naturalia,” in Lloyd, G. E. R. and Owens, G. E. L. (eds.), Aristotle on Mind and the Senses, Proceedings of the 7th Symposium Aristotelicum, Cambridge, 215–239.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1983), Science, Folklore, and Ideology: Studies in the Life Sciences in Ancient Greece, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1987), “Empirical Research in Aristotle's Biology,” in Gotthelf, A. and Lennox, J. G. (eds.), Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology, Cambridge, 53–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1990), “Aristotle's Zoology and his Metaphysics: The Status Quaestionis; A Critical Review of some Recent Theories,” in Devereux, D. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote, Paris, 7–35.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1991), Methods and Problems in Greek Science, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1992), “Aspects of the Relationship between Aristotle's Psychology and his Zoology,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 147–167.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1995), “Ancient Greek Concepts of Causation in Comparativist Perspective,” in Sperber, D., Premack, D., and Premack, A. J. (eds.), Causal Cognition, Oxford, 205–233.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. (1996), Aristotelian Explorations, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Lloyd, G. E. R. and Owens, G. E. L. (eds.) (1978), Aristotle on Mind and the Senses, Proceedings of the 7th Symposium Aristotelicum, Cambridge.Google Scholar
Löbl, R. (2003), TEXNH – TECHNE, Untersuchungen zur Bedeutung dieses Worts in der Zeit von Homer bis Aristoteles, Band II: Von den Sophisten bis zu Aristoteles, Würzburg.Google Scholar
Mansfeld, J. (2002), “Deconstructing Doxography,” Philologus 146, 277–286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, A. and Primavesi, O. (1999), L'Empédocle de Strasbourg (P. Strasb. Gr. Inv. 1665–1666), introduction, édition et commentaire, with an English summary, New York.Google Scholar
Matthen, M. (ed.) (1987), Aristotle Today, Essays on Aristotle's Ideal of Science, Edmonton, AB.Google Scholar
Matthen, M. (1989), “The Four Causes in Aristotle's Embryology,” in Kraut, R. and Penner, T. (eds.), Nature, Knowledge and Virtue: Apeiron, Special Issue 22.4, 159–180.Google Scholar
Matthen, M. (2001), “The Holistic Presuppositions of Aristotle's Cosmology,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 20, 171–199.Google Scholar
Matthen, M. (2009), “Teleology in Living Things,” in Anagnostopoulus, G. (ed.), A Companion to Aristotle, Blackwell Guides to Philosophy, Oxford, 335–347.Google Scholar
Matthen, M. and Hankinson, R. J. (1993), “Aristotle's Universe: Its Form and Matter,” Synthese 96, 417–435; reprinted in Gerson, L. P. (ed.) (1999), Aristotle: Critical Assessments, London, 209–226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthews, G. (1992), “De Anima 2.2–4 and the Meaning of Life,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 185–93.Google Scholar
Mayhew, R. (2004), The Female in Aristotle's Biology: Reason or Rationalization, Chicago.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKirahan, R. (1992), Principles and Proofs: Aristotle's Theory of Demonstrative Science, Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Menn, S. (1994), “The Origins of Aristotle's Concept of Energeia: Energeia and Dunamis,” Ancient Philosophy 14, 73–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menn, S. (2002), “Aristotle's Definition of Soul and the Programme of the De Anima,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 22, 83–139.Google Scholar
Miller, F. D. (1995), Nature, Justice, and Rights in Aristotle's Politics, Oxford.Google Scholar
Mirus, C. V. (2004), “The Metaphysical Roots of Aristotle's Teleology,” Review of Metaphysics 57, 699–724.Google Scholar
Moraux, P. (1961), “La méthode d'Aristote dans l'Étude du Ciel, De Caelo I.1–II.12,” in Mansion, S. (ed.), Aristote et les problèmes de méthode, Louvain, 173–195.Google Scholar
Moravcsik, J. M. (1974a), “Aristotle on Adequate Explanations,” Synthese 28, 3–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moravcsik, J. M. (1974b), “Aitia as Generative Factor in Aristotle's Philosophy,” Dialogue 14, 622–638.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moravcsik, J. M. (1991), “What Makes Reality Intelligible? Reflections on Aristotle's Theory of Aitia,” in Judson, L. (ed.), Aristotle's Physics: A Collection of Essays, Oxford, 31–47.Google Scholar
Moravcsik, J. M. (1994), “Essences, Powers, and Generic Propositions,” in Scaltas, T., Charles, D., and Gill, M. L. (eds.), Unity, Identity, and Explanation in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Oxford, 229–244.Google Scholar
Moravcsik, J. M. (1995), “Philosophic Background of Aristotle's Aitia,” in Sim, M. (ed.), The Crossroads of Norm and Nature: Essays on Aristotle's Ethics and Metaphysics, Boston, 237–246.Google Scholar
Morison, B, (2002), On Location: Aristotle's Concept of Place, Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mouracade, J. (ed.) (2008), Aristotle on Life, Apeiron, Special Issue 41.3.
Mueller, I. (2006), “Physics and Astronomy: Aristotle's Physics II.2, 193b22–194a12,” Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 16, 175–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mure, G. R. G. (1975), “Cause and Because in Aristotle,” Philosophy 50, 356–357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Natali, C. (2001), The Wisdom of Aristotle, translated by Gerald Parks, New York.Google Scholar
Nielsen, K. M. (2008), “The Private Parts of Animals: Aristotle on the Teleology of Sexual Difference,” Phronesis 53, 373–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. (1978), Aristotle's De Motu Animalium, Princeton, NJ.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. and Putnam, H. (1992), “Changing Aristotle's Mind,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 27–56.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.) (1992), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, M. C. and Schofield, M. (eds.) (1982), Language and Logos, Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Ogle, W. (1912), Aristotle: De Partibus Animalium, Oxford.Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. (1961), “Tithenai ta Phainomena,” in Mansion, S. (ed.), Aristote et les problèmes de méthode, Louvain.Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. (1986), Logic, Science, and Dialectic, ed. Nussbaum, M. C., New York.Google Scholar
Owens, J. (1968), “The Teleology of Nature,” Monist 52, 159–173; reprinted in Catan, J. R. (ed.) (1981), Aristotle: The Collected Papers of J. Owens, New York, 136–147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pavlopoulos, M. (2003), “Aristotle's Natural Teleology and Metaphysics of Life,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 23, 133–181.Google Scholar
Pellegrin, P. (1986), Aristotle's Classification of Animals: Biology and the Conceptual Unity of the Aristotelian Corpus, tranlated by A. Preuss, Berkeley, CA.Google Scholar
Pellegrin, P. (2002), “Les ruses de la nature et l'éternité du mouvement: encore quelques remarques sur la finalité chez Aristote,” in Canto-Sperber, M. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Le style de la pensée: recueil des textes en hommage à Jacques Brunschwig, Paris, 296–323.Google Scholar
Polansky, R. (1999), “Analogy and Disanalogy of the Soul's Faculties in Aristotle's De Anima,” Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 15, 57–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polansky, R. (2007), Aristotle's De Anima, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Preus, A. (1975), Science and Philosophy in Aristotle's Biological Works, New York.Google Scholar
Preus, A. (1990), “Man and Cosmos in Aristotle: Metaphysics L and the Biological Works,” in Devereux, D. and Pellegrin, P. (eds.), Biologie, logique et métaphysique chez Aristote, Paris, 471–490.Google Scholar
Quarantotto, D. (2001), “Ontologia della causa finale aristotelica,” Elenchos 22.2, 329–365.Google Scholar
Quarantotto, D. (2005), Causa finale, sostanza, essenza in Aristotele: saggi sulla struttura dei processi teleologici naturali e sulla funzione dei telos, Naples.Google Scholar
Richardson, H. (1992), “Desire and the Good in De Anima,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 381–399.Google Scholar
Rijksbaron, A., Slings, S. R., Stork, P., and Wakker, G. C. (2000), Beknopte Syntaxis van het klassiek Grieks, Lunteren.Google Scholar
Rist, J. M. (1965), “Some Aspects of Aristotelian Teleology,” Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association 96, 337–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ritter, W. E. (1932; 1934), “Why Aristotle Invented the Word Entelecheia,” Quarterly Review of Biology 7, 377–404; 9, 1–35.Google Scholar
Rorty, A. Oksenberg (1992), “De Anima: Its Agenda and Its Recent Interpreters,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 7–13.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1924), Aristotle's Metaphysics, Oxford.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1936), Aristotle's Physics: A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary, Oxford.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1949), Aristotle's Prior and Posterior Analytics: A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary, Oxford.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1961), Aristotle's De Anima, Oxford.Google Scholar
Salles, R. (ed.) (2005), Metaphysics, Soul, and Ethics (Festschrift for Richard Sorabji), Oxford.Google Scholar
Santas, G. (1969), “Aristotle on Practical Inference, the Explanation of Action, and Akrasia,” Phronesis 14, 162–189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sauvé Meyer, S. (1992), “Aristotle, Teleology, and Reduction,” Philosophical Review 101, 791–825; reprinted in Irwin, T. (ed.) (1995), Classical Philosophy: Collected Papers, New York and London, 81–116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scaltsas, T., Charles, D., and Gill, M. L. (eds.) (1994), Unity, Identity, and Explanation in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Oxford.Google Scholar
Scharle, M. (2008), “Elemental Teleology in Aristotle's Physics II.8,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 34, 147–183.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. (1991), “Explanatory Projects in Physics, 2.3 and 2.7,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 1991, 29–40.
Schofield, M. (1992), “Aristotle on the Imagination,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 249–277.Google Scholar
Schofield, M., Burnyeat, M., and Barnes, J. (eds.) (1980), Doubt and Dogmatism: Studies in Hellenistic Epistemology, Oxford.Google Scholar
Schofield, M. and Nussbaum, M. (eds.) (1982), Language and Logos, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedley, D. (1989), “Teleology and Myth in the Phaedo,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 5, 359–383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedley, D. (1991), “Is Aristotle's Teleology Anthropocentric?,” Phronesis 36, 179–197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedley, D. (1998), “Platonic Causes,” Phronesis 43, 114–132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sedley, D. (2000), “Metaphysics L.10,” in Frede, M. and Charles, D. (eds.), Aristotle's Metaphysics Lambda, Symposium Aristotelicum, Oxford, 327–350.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. (2003), “Lucretius and the New Empedocles,” Leeds International Classical Studies 2.4, 1–12.Google Scholar
Sedley, D. (2007), Creationism and its Critics in Antiquity, Berkeley, CA.Google Scholar
Sfendoni-Mentzou, D. (ed.) (2000), Aristotle and Contemporary Science, vol. I, Frankfurt am Main.Google Scholar
Sfendoni-Mentzou, D., Hattiangadi, J., and Johnson, D. M. (eds.) (2001), Aristotle and Contemporary Science, vol. II, Frankfurt am Main.Google Scholar
Sharples, R. W. (ed.) (2004a), Philosophy and the Sciences in Antiquity, London.Google Scholar
Sharples, R. W. (ed.) (2004b), Perspectives on Greek Philosophy, Aldershot and Burlington, VT.Google Scholar
Shields, C. (1988), “Soul and Body in Aristotle,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 6, 103–137.Google Scholar
Shields, C. (1990), “The First Functionalist,” in Smith, J.-C. (ed.), Historical Foundations of Cognitive Science, Boston, 19–34.Google Scholar
Shields, C. (1993), “Some Recent Approaches to Aristotle's De Anima,” in Hamlyn, D. W., Aristotle De Anima, Books II and III (with Passages from Book I), translated with introduction and notes, Oxford, 157–181.Google Scholar
Shields, C. (1999), Order in Multiplicity: Homonymy in the Philosophy of Aristotle, Oxford.Google Scholar
Simpson, P. L. P. (1998), A Philosophical Commentary on the Politics of Aristotle, Chapel Hill, NC, and London.Google Scholar
Sluiter, I. (1990), Ancient Grammar in Context: Contributions to the Study of Ancient Linguistic Thought, Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Smith, R. (1989), Prior Analytics, translation with introduction, notes, and commentary, Indianapolis, IN.Google Scholar
Solmsen, F. (1960), Aristotle's System of the Physical World: A Comparison with his Predecessors, Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Solmsen, F. (1963), “Nature as Craftsman in Greek Thought,” Journal of the History of Ideas 24, 473–496; reprinted in F. Solmsen, Kleine Schriften, Hildesheim and New York, 332–351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1974), “Body and Soul in Aristotle,” Philosophy 49, 63–89.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sorabji, R. (1980), Necessity, Cause, and Blame: Perspectives on Aristotle's Theory, Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Sorabji, R. (1993), Animal Minds and Human Morals: The Origins of the Western Debate, Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Sprague, R. K. (1968), “The Four Causes: Aristotle's Exposition and Ours,” Monist 52, 298–300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sprague, R. K. (1991), “Plants as Aristotelian Substances,” Illinois Classical Studies 56, 221–229.Google Scholar
Suppes, P., Moravcsik, J. M., and Mendell, H. (eds.) (2000), Ancient and Medieval Traditions in the Exact Sciences: Essays in Memory of Wilbur Knorr, Stanford, CA.Google Scholar
Tierney, R. (2001), “Aristotle's Scientific Demonstrations as Expositions of Essence,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 20, 149–170.Google Scholar
Turnbull, R. G. (1958), “Aristotle's Debt to the ‘Natural Philosophy’ of the Phaedo,” Philosophical Quarterly 8, 131–143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wardy, R. (1993), “Aristotelian Rainfall or the Lore of Averages,” Phronesis 38, 18–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waterlow, S. (1982), Nature, Change and Agency in Aristotle's Physics: A Philosophical Study. Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whiting, J. (1992), “Living Bodies,” in Nussbaum, M. C. and Rorty, A. O. (eds.), Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima, Oxford, 76–91.Google Scholar
Whiting, J. (2002), “Locomotive Soul: the Parts of Soul in Aristotle's Scientific Works,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 22, 141–200.Google Scholar
Wians, W. (1996), “Scientific Examples in the Posterior Analytics,” in Wians, W. (ed.), Aristotle's Philosophical Development: Problems and Prospects, London, 131–150.Google Scholar
Wieland, W. (1975), “The Problem of Teleology,” in Barnes, J., Schofield, M., and Sorabji, R. (eds.), Articles on Aristotle, vol. I: Science, London, 141–160; originally published as “Zum Teleologieproblem,” in W. Wieland (1962), Die aristotelische Physik, Göttingen.Google Scholar
Witt, C. (1994a), Substance and Essence in Aristotle, Ithaca, NY.Google Scholar
Witt, C. (1994b), “The Priority of Actuality in Aristotle,” in Scaltsas, T., Charles, D., and Gill, M. L. (eds.), Unity, Identity, and Explanation in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Oxford, 215–228.Google Scholar
Witt, C. (1998), “Teleology in Aristotelian Metaphysics,” in Gentzler, J. (ed.), Method in Ancient Philosophy, Oxford, 253–269.Google Scholar
Woodfield, A. (1976), Teleology, London.Google Scholar
Wright, L. (1973–4), “The Astronomy of Eudoxus: Geometry or Physics?,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 4, 165–172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wright, L. (1976), Teleological Explanations, Berkeley, CA.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Mariska Leunissen, Washington University, St Louis
  • Book: Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle's Science of Nature
  • Online publication: 07 September 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511762499.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Mariska Leunissen, Washington University, St Louis
  • Book: Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle's Science of Nature
  • Online publication: 07 September 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511762499.009
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Mariska Leunissen, Washington University, St Louis
  • Book: Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle's Science of Nature
  • Online publication: 07 September 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511762499.009
Available formats
×