Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-fnpn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-29T08:31:26.323Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

XII - Seminar from March 2, 1983

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 October 2023

John Garner
Affiliation:
University of West Georgia
María-Constanza Garrido Sierralta
Affiliation:
University of New Mexico
Get access

Summary

Today we will once again turn, as with Anaximander, to the texts themselves, with this difference, namely that instead of analyzing a single passage in a deep way, I will try to collect and comment on what remains with us from Heraclitus, namely a bit less than a 140 fragments (I’ll come back to this). If I wanted to take up Heraclitus here, it was for several reasons. First of all, it’s because it interests me passionately. Next, it’s because this is the first philosopher in Western history whose transmitted corpus allows for a work of interpretation that goes beyond the exercise of divination about a singular fragment or (as with Xenophanes) about a handful of lines. Thirdly and above all, it’s because with him we already find ourselves fully within philosophy, with all its splendor and indeed its obscurity. And this is especially because, as I told you last time, in this perpetual circle that philosophy and simply thinking travel, Heraclitus marks the achievement of a first movement; he completes—forgive me if I abuse the image—a first turn. For, let’s repeat that Heraclitus, the same as Anaximander, didn’t write in a void, as lots of interpreters seem tacitly to presuppose, particularly Heidegger. He takes full account of the world that surrounds him and of all that preceded him, all while separating himself very strongly from it. We could say that he made a sort of synthesis out of it in the Hegelian sense, i.e. what he denies isn’t ignored by him but—while being refuted and abolished—is implicitly contained in his own thinking. Heraclitus arrives at a crucial moment, which is (to take up the traditional terminology, which is inadequate in my view) at the end of the archaic period and the start of the great classical period. According to the doxographic tradition, he was born around 540 and thrived around 505–500. He is thus about forty years old at the turn of the century. To situate things, I’ll remind you of some other dates: Xenophanes was born around 570 and died around 470; Pythagoras was born around 570 and died around 490; Aeschylus was born around 525 and died in 456; Pindar was born in 518 (or 522); Parmenides, around 515; Herodotus, around 485.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Greek Imaginary
From Homer to Heraclitus, Seminars 1982-1983
, pp. 201 - 224
Publisher: Edinburgh University Press
Print publication year: 2023

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×