Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-848d4c4894-8kt4b Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-06-26T20:05:23.383Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

2 - Are the Cognitive Sciences Relevant for Law?

from I - Metatheory and Methodology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 April 2021

Bartosz Brożek
Affiliation:
Jagiellonian University, Krakow
Jaap Hage
Affiliation:
Universiteit Maastricht, Netherlands
Nicole Vincent
Affiliation:
Macquarie University, Sydney
Get access

Summary

This chapter addresses the question of whether the cognitive sciences are relevant for law. The answer to this question will turn out to be a threefold ‘yes’. First, if law is traditionally conceived as a set of rules that prescribe what ought to be done, there is a role for the cognitive sciences in determining the facts of the cases to which the law is to be applied (evidential reasoning). Legal decision making often involves the application of open-textured concepts, and the cognitive sciences can study the psychological processes and perhaps also the biases involved in such an application. Moreover, the results of the cognitive sciences may also be important for the evaluation of law, and for determining what good law might be.

A perhaps more ambitious role for cognitive sciences in law has to do with the determination of the content of the law. If law is a social phenomenon, and if social phenomena depend on what goes on in human minds, cognitive sciences can, at least in theory, study the content of the law. Some would argue that the cognitive sciences could never fulfil this more ambitious role, because law has to do with what OUGHT to be done, or ought to be the case, while sciences, including cognitive sciences, can only study what IS the case. It will be argued that this fundamental objection against this role for the cognitive sciences is misguided: there is no hard difference between IS and OUGHT and even if law belongs to the realm of OUGHT, cognitive sciences may still be relevant for determining the content of the law.

Finally, the cognitive sciences may disrupt the image of humankind that underlies law. It turns out that people are less rational than they may seem at first glance, that they often do not know what motivates them, that it is not obvious what actions and agents are and that it is unclear what the best level of explanation is for human actions or bodily movements. A change in the image of humankind that underlies law, to reflect the recent insights of the cognitive sciences but also of ancient philosophical debates, may have important consequences for the contents of law.

Type
Chapter
Information
Law and Mind
A Survey of Law and the Cognitive Sciences
, pp. 17 - 49
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alexy, R. (1978). Theorie der juristischen Argumentation. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Amaya, Amalia. (2015). The Tapestry of Reason. Oxford: Hart.Google Scholar
Amaya, Amalia. (2018). Coherence and Systematization in Law. In Bongiovanni, G., Postema, G., Rotolo, A., Sartor, G., Valentini, C. & Walton, D. (eds.) (2018), Handbook of Legal Reasoning and Argumentation. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 637–72.Google Scholar
Ariely, Dan. (2009). Predictably Irrational: The Hidden Forces that Shape Our Decisions. New York: Harper.Google Scholar
Bagnoli, Carla. (2017). Constructivism in Metaethics. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/constructivism-metaethics/Google Scholar
Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy. (1970). An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, ed. Burns, J. H. & Hart, H. L. A.. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon. (1984). Spreading the Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of Language. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bowles, Samuel, & Gintis, Herbert. (2011). A Cooperative Species: Human Reciprocity and Its Evolution. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Brożek, Bartosz. (2013). Rule-Following. Kraków: Copernicus Press.Google Scholar
Claessen, Jacques. (2019). Theories of Punishment. In Keiler, Johannes & Roef, David (eds.), Comparative Concepts of Criminal Law, 3rd ed. Cambridge: Intersentia, pp. 1134.Google Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. (1991). Consciousness Explained. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Di Bello, M., & Verheij, B. (2018). Evidential Reasoning. In Bongiovanni, G., Postema, G., Rotolo, A., Sartor, G., Valentini, C., & Walton, D. (eds.) (2018), Handbook of Legal Reasoning and Argumentation. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 447–93.Google Scholar
Doris, John M., & the Moral Psychology Research Group. (2010). The Moral Psychology Handbook. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Epstein, Richard A. (2006). The Optimal Complexity of Legal Rules. In Gigerenzer, G. & Engel, C. (eds.), Heuristics and the Law. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 141–57.Google Scholar
Estabrooks, G. H. (1943). Hypnotism. New York: E. P. Dutton.Google Scholar
Fenton, Norman, Neil, Martin, & Berger, Daniel. (2016). Bayes and the Law. Annual Review of Statistics and its Application 3, 5177.Google Scholar
Friedman, David D. (2000). Law’s Order. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gallagher, Shaun (ed.) (2011). The Oxford Handbook of the Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gazzaniga, M. S., & LeDoux, J. E. (1978). The Integrated Mind. New York: Plenum.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. (2006). Heuristics. In Gigerenzer, G. & Engel, C. (eds.), Heuristics and the Law. Cambridge: MIT Press, p. 1744.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gigerenzer, G. (2008). Moral Intuition = Fast and Frugal Heuristics? In Sinnott-Armstrong, 2008a, pp. 126.Google Scholar
Golding, Martin P. (1975). Philosophy of Law. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Goodenough, Oliver R., & Tucker, Micaela. (2010). Law and Cognitive Neuroscience. In Annual Review of Law and Social Science 6, 6192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grossi, Davide, Meyer, John-Jules, & Dignum, Frank. (2008). The Many Faces of Counts-As: A Formal Analysis of Constitutive Rules. Journal of Applied Logic 6, 192217. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jal.2007.06.008CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hage, Jaap. (2005). Law and Coherence. In Studies in Legal Logic. Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 3368.Google Scholar
Hage, Jaap. (2017). Tort Law. In Hage, Jaap, Waltermann, Antonia, & Akkermans, Bram (eds.), Introduction to Law, 2nd ed. Cham: Springer, pp. 109–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hage, Jaap. (2018). Foundations and Building Blocks of Law. The Hague: Eleven.Google Scholar
Hage, Jaap, Waltermann, Antonia, & Akkermans, Bram (eds.) (2017). Introduction to Law, 2nd ed. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haidt, Jonathan. (2012). The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and Religion. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Haidt, Jonathan, & Bjorklund, Fredrik. (2008). Social Intuitionists Answer Six Questions about Moral Psychology. In Sinnott-Armstrong 2008a, pp. 181218.Google Scholar
Haji, Ishtiyaque. (2002). Compatibilist Views of Freedom and Responsibility. In Kane, 2002, pp. 202–28.Google Scholar
Hart, Herbert L. A. (2012). The Concept of Law, 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press (1st ed. 1961).Google Scholar
Hoefer, Carl. (2019). Causal Determinism. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/determinism-causal/Google Scholar
Hofstadter, Douglas R. (1980). Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Hume, David. (1978). A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Selby-Bigge, L. A. & Nidditch, P. H.. Oxford: Oxford University Press (1st ed. 1738–40).Google Scholar
Joyce, Richard. (2016). Moral Anti-Realism. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/moral-anti-realism/Google Scholar
Kahneman, Daniel. (2012). Thinking, Fast and Slow. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982). Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kane, Robert (ed.). (2002). The Oxford Handbook of Free Will, 1st ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. (1934). Reine Rechtslehre, 1st ed. Leipzig: Franz Deuticke.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. (1960). Reine Rechtslehre, 2nd ed. Vienna: Franz Deuticke.Google Scholar
Kelsen, Hans. (1992). Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. Translation of the first (1934) edition of the Reine Rechtslehre by Paulson, Bonnie Litschewsky and Paulson, Stanley. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (2012). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press (1st ed. 1962).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, Imre. (1970). Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programs. In Lakatos, I., & Musgrave, A. (eds.) (1970). Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 91196.Google Scholar
MacCormick, Neil. (1978). Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
MacCormick, Neil. (2005). Rhetoric and the Rule of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mackor, Anne Ruth. (2013). What Can Neurosciences Say About Responsibility? Taking the Distinction Between Theoretical and Practical Reason Seriously. In Vincent, Nicole A. (ed.), Neuroscience and Legal Responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 5384.Google Scholar
Morse, Stephen J. (2013). Introduction. In Morse, Stephen J. & Roskies, Adina L. (eds.), A Primer on Criminal Law and Neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. xvxxiii.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. (1970). The Possibility of Altruism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review 84, 231–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pardo, Michael S., & Patterson, Dennis. (2013) Minds. Brains and Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, Derek. (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, Derk. (2001). Living Without Free Will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prakken, H. (2001). Modelling Reasoning About Evidence in Legal Procedure. In Proceedings of the Eighth International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law. New York: ACM Press, pp. 119–28.Google Scholar
Rachlinski, J. J., Guthrie, C., & Wistrich, A. J. (2007). Heuristics and Biases in Bankruptcy Judges. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 163, 167–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rachlinski, J. J., Johnson, S., Wistrich, A., & Guthrie, C. (2009). Does Unconscious Racial Bias Affect Trial Judges? Notre Dame Law Review, 84, 11951246.Google Scholar
Radden, Jennifer. (2011). Multiple Selves. In Gallagher, 2011, pp. 547–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, Peter. (2006). Humean Theory of Practical Rationality. In Copp, David (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 265–81.Google Scholar
Rosati, Connie S. (2016). Moral Motivation. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/moral-motivation/Google Scholar
Roskies, Adina L. (2013). Brain Imaging Techniques. In Morse, Stephen J. & Roskies, Adina L. (eds.), A Primer on Criminal Law and Neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 3774.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ross, Alf. (1946). Towards a Realistic Jurisprudence. Copenhagen: Einar Munksgaard.Google Scholar
Ruiter, Dick W. P. (1993). Institutional Legal Facts. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sapolsky, Robert M. (2017). Behave: The Biology of Humans at Our Best and Worst. London: Bodley Head.Google Scholar
Schlosser, Markus. (2015). Agency. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/agency/Google Scholar
Searle, John R. (1995). The Construction of Social Reality. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (ed.) (2008a). Moral Psychology, vol. 2, The Cognitive Science of Morality: Intuition and Diversity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (ed.) (2008b). Moral Psychology, vol. 3, The Neuroscience of Morality: Emotion, Brain Disorders, and Development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Strawson, Galen. (2011). The Minimal Subject. In Gallagher, 2011, pp. 253–78.Google Scholar
Taleb, Nassim Nicholas. (2008). The Black Swan: The Impact of the Highly Improbable. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Timpe, Kevin. (n.d.) Free Will. https://iep.utm.edu/freewill/#SH2cGoogle Scholar
Wagenaar, Willem A., Van Koppen, Peter J., & Crombag, Hans F. M. (1993). Anchored Narratives: The Psychology of Criminal Evidence. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Wallace, R. Jay. (2020). Practical Reason. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/practical-reason/Google Scholar
Wilson, Eric Entrican, & Denis, Lara. (2018). Kant and Hume on Morality. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/kant-hume-morality/Google Scholar
Wilson, Timothy D. (2002). Strangers to Ourselves: Discovering the Adaptive Unconsciousness. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Wróblewski, Jerzy. (1992). The Judicial Application of Law, eds. Bankowski, Zenon and MacCormick, Neil. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Zaluski, Wojciech. (2009). Evolutionary Theory and Legal Philosophy. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.Google Scholar
Zaluski, Wojciech. (2013). Game Theory in Jurisprudence. Kraków: Copernicus Center Press.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×