Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-c654p Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-27T01:09:56.394Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

6 - DEFINING RATIONALITY

personal and group decision making

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 May 2010

Earl Hunt
Affiliation:
University of Washington
Get access

Summary

AXIOMATIC REASONING

One of my favorite plays is Christopher Fry's 1948 London hit The Lady's Not for Burning. The play takes place in medieval times. A young woman, Jenny Jourdemain, has been accused of being a witch. She then observes some very unusual behavior, including the request of a soldier who wants to be executed because he is weary of life. Jenny, who prides herself on her own logical approach to life, says that she cannot believe that rational people are behaving the way that the people around her are behaving. She is particularly concerned about the magistrates' certainty that she should be burned at the stake. Jenny regards this as illogical, for if she were a witch, she would simply fly away.

People raised in the Western European–North American tradition, and particularly those raised in the more secular branches of that tradition, generally see rational behavior as good and irrational behavior as bad. But who defines rationality? How do we connect rationality to behavior? This chapter will explore these questions, with respect to individual and group decisions.

The approach that will be taken was established by one of the greatest mathematicians of all time, the legendary geometer Euclid of Alexandria (325?–265? b.c.e.), whose work has been studied for more than 2,300 years! Euclid did not invent geometery. Pythagoras preceded Euclid by about 200 years.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • DEFINING RATIONALITY
  • Earl Hunt, University of Washington
  • Book: The Mathematics of Behavior
  • Online publication: 04 May 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511618222.007
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • DEFINING RATIONALITY
  • Earl Hunt, University of Washington
  • Book: The Mathematics of Behavior
  • Online publication: 04 May 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511618222.007
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • DEFINING RATIONALITY
  • Earl Hunt, University of Washington
  • Book: The Mathematics of Behavior
  • Online publication: 04 May 2010
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511618222.007
Available formats
×