Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-tdptf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-17T00:09:25.820Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

1 - The materialist's problem and some non-reductive solutions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 May 2010

Get access

Summary

INTRODUCTION

William James divided philosophers into two psychological types, the tender-minded and the tough-minded. One of the characteristics of the tough-minded is a disposition to believe in philosophical materialism, whilst the tender-minded prefer dualism or idealism. The epithets ‘tender-minded’ and ‘tough-minded’ are not meant as evaluations of the arguments used to defend the theories each type is inclined to adopt; rather they describe the temperaments which are prone to accept and defend those theories: they are a psychological not a rational evaluation. Despite their association with the toughminded temperament, materialist theories have tended to get the worst of the argument a bout the nature of the mind, if we judge by influence on the history of philosophy. Plato and Aristotle, for example, have had a greater appeal for philosophers through the ages than have the epicureans or the atomists: Descartes's influence is much greater than Hobbes's. This has been so despite the influence on modern philosophy of the materialistically inclined physical sciences. James also classified the approach and doctrines normally labelled ‘empiricist’ as tough-minded, yet empiricists have tended not to be materialists. The modern philosopher most representative of traditional empiricism, Sir Alfred Ayer, can both declare that his only object of faith is science and express a reluctant pessimism about the possibility of a coherent materialist theory of the human mind.1 One may be tempted to cynicism and suspect that otherwise hardnosed philosophers become tender-minded when dealing with their own souls.

Type
Chapter
Information
Matter and Sense
A Critique of Contemporary Materialism
, pp. 1 - 19
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×