Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-gq7q9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-21T08:16:25.929Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - A Materialist Interpretation of the History of Modern Philosophy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

John Abromeit
Affiliation:
State University of New York, Buffalo State
Get access

Summary

Having examined Horkheimer’s childhood, youth, and student years in the first two chapters, we turn now in the following three chapters to the development of his Critical Theory in the period 1925–31. In contrast to studies of Horkheimer’s work that begin with his assumption of the directorship of the Institute for Social Research in 1931, I would like to argue in the following three chapters that his Critical Theory took shape in the period following his break with Hans Cornelius in 1925. Although Horkheimer continued to test, refine, and develop his Critical Theory through his collaborative work at the Institute, its basic contours were already in place when he became the director in 1931. In contrast to arguments that maintain that Horkheimer’s Critical Theory remained beholden to the tradition of “consciousness philosophy,” a closer examination of his work during this time reveals that it developed precisely as a critique of consciousness philosophy along two interrelated yet distinct axes: one diachronic and historical, the other synchronic and social. In his move beyond the consciousness philosophy of both his philosophical mentor, Hans Cornelius, and almost the entirety of contemporary German academic philosophy, Horkheimer placed consciousness firmly within the larger objective and dynamic structures of history and society – without, however, eliminating the active role of subjective consciousness in reproducing and transforming these structures. This chapter examines how Horkheimer moved beyond consciousness philosophy along the diachronic, historical axis in his lectures and writings on the history of modern philosophy in the late 1920s. The following two chapters address the ways in which Horkheimer moved beyond consciousness philosophy along the synchronic, social axis: through an examination of his theory of contemporary society (Chapter four) and his integration of psychoanalysis into that theory (Chapter five).

Horkheimer’s break with consciousness philosophy and his turn toward history and society

Horkheimer’s dissertation and Habilitationsschrift marked the culmination of his exploration of the debates on neo-Kantianism and phenomenologythat dominated German academic philosophy in the mid-1920s. Although Horkheimer was skeptical of these debates from early on, he delayed explicitly developing his own position until he had completed his Habilitationsschrift in 1925, due to the tacit tactical truce he made with Cornelius. However, with the completion of his academic requirements and his attainment of the status of Privatdozent, Horkheimer no longer felt obliged to play the role of Cornelius’s disciple. He continued to teach with Cornelius until the latter retired in 1929, and relations between the two of them remained cordial until Cornelius’s death in 1948. Yet after 1925, Horkheimer was definitely ready to return to the incipient critique of consciousness philosophy he had begun to develop several years before. Evidence of this readiness can be found in a passage from Horkheimer’s philosophical diary from September 16, 1925, which is worth quoting at length because it so clearly illustrates this crucial juncture in Horkheimer’s intellectual development.

Immanence philosophy, any type of “world” view, which equates the “world” with phenomena of consciousness, with relations or functions of phenomena of consciousness, has to have the courage for solipsism…. Separately and privately our philosopher senses of course that he is not at all a world creator, but rather a simple human being in the world.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2011

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Dubiel, HelmutTheory and Politics: Studies in the Development of Critical TheoryCambridgeMIT Press 1985Google Scholar
1999
Habermas: A Critical ReaderDews, PeterOxford and Malden, MA 1999
Habermas, JürgenTheory of Communicative ActionBoston 1984Google Scholar
Horkheimer, MaxBetween Philosophy and Social Science: Selected Early WritingsCambridge, MA and London 1993Google Scholar
1977
Kelly, JoanWomen, History and TheoryChicagoUniversity of Chicago Press 1984Google Scholar
1858
Gay, PeterThe Rise of Modern PaganismNew York 1966Google Scholar
1969
Nietzsche, FriedrichOn the Advantage and Disadvantage of History for LifeIndianapolis 1980Google Scholar
Cassirer, ErnstPhilosophy of the EnlightenmentKoelln, C.A.Pettegrove, J.P.Boston 1955Google Scholar
Marx, The Marx-Engels ReaderTucker, R.New YorkNorton 1978Google Scholar
1994
Marcuse, HerbertReason and Revolution: Hegel and Origins of Social TheoryBoston 1960Google Scholar
Köhnke, Klaus ChristianEntstehung und Aufstieg des Neukantianismus: Die deutsche Universitätsphilosophie zwischen Idealismus und PositivismusFrankfurt 1986Google Scholar
2002
Marcuse, Herbert Marcuse: Heideggerian MarcuseWolin, R.Abromeit, J.University of Nebraska Press 2005Google Scholar
Brunkhorst, HaukeDialektischer Positivismus des GlücksZeitschrift für philosophische Forschung 39 1985 353Google Scholar
Dahms, Hans-JoachimPositivismusstreitFrankfurt 1994Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×