Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-wxhwt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-15T20:23:28.691Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

3 - Against human rights: liberty in the western tradition

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2014

John Milbank
Affiliation:
University of Nottingham
Costas Douzinas
Affiliation:
Birkbeck, University of London
Conor Gearty
Affiliation:
London School of Economics and Political Science
Get access

Summary

Prelude: liberalism, sovereignty and political economy

Political economy, the most developed form of liberalism, was, in the longest perspective, built upon two specifically modern concepts: first of all rights, and secondly sympathy. The notion of sympathy is in many ways in tension with the notion of rights and even derives from sources resistant to ideas of subjective right and cognate concepts of social contract as founding the political order. Indeed, for the most part a direct, interpersonal exercise of sympathy was relegated by Adam Smith and other thinkers of the Scottish Enlightenment to the sphere of ‘civil society’ which lies outside the economic order, even though the latter was still crucially regarded as embedded within it – an assumption later lost to view within a later, more drastic elaboration of the liberal credo. Already for Smith, within the order of the properly ‘economic’, sympathetic, mutual goals are to be achieved indirectly, through a ‘providential’ and unintended co-ordination of sheerly egotistic purposes, politically legitimated in terms of ideas of subjective entitlement.

Such a notion of ‘right’ grounds the politically economic idea of person, property and contract. But here one can claim that, whenever the notion of sympathy was subordinated through indirection – or, in other terms, the idea of a reciprocalist pursuit of common ends is denied to be constitutive of the political foundation – then the idea of individually based natural rights, appealing to the normativity of negative freedom, was from the outset correlated with an absolutist account of the sovereignty of the centralised state. In the case of Scots political economy this link re-emerges with James Stewart, who gave a more honest account than Adam Smith of the role that the state, empire and military conquest must play in processes of primacy accumulation. He explicitly stated that ‘the Republic of Lycurgus [ancient Sparta] represents the more perfect plan of political economy – anywhere to be met with, either in ancient or modern times’.

Type
Chapter
Information
The Meanings of Rights
The Philosophy and Social Theory of Human Rights
, pp. 39 - 70
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2014

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Milbank, John, ‘The Invocation of Clio’, in The Future of Love (Eugene, Oreg. and London: Wipf and Stock/SCM, 2008–2009), 175–220.Google Scholar
Milbank, John, ‘Hume versus Kant: Faith, Reason and Feeling’, Modern Theology, 27(2) (2011), 276–297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elshtain, Jean Bethke, Sovereignty: God, State and Self (New York: Basic Books, 2008).Google Scholar
Stewart, James, The Works (New York: Augustus M. Kelley, 1967), vol. I, 51, 97–98, 344–346, 352.Google Scholar
Perelman, Michael, Classical Political Economy: Positive Accumulation and the Social Division of Labour (Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allenheld, 1984).Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, (ed.) Tuck, Richard (Cambridge University Press, 1991), 125, 225, 228.Google Scholar
Strauss, Leo, Natural Right and History (Chicago University Press, 1953), 165–251.Google Scholar
Locke, John, Two Treatises of Government, (ed.) Laslett, Peter (Cambridge University Press, 2000), 195–199, 350–351.Google Scholar
Tierney, Brian, The Idea of Natural Rights: Studies on Natural Rights, Natural Law and Church Law 1150–1625 (Grand Rapids, Mich: Eerdmans, 1997), 170–194.Google Scholar
Fichte, J.G., Foundations of Natural Right, (trans.) Baur, Michael (Cambridge University Press, 2000), 254–263Google Scholar
Vulliamy, Ed, Amexica: War Along the Borderline (London: Vintage, 2010).Google Scholar
Polanyi, Karl, The Great Transformation (Boston Mass.: Beacon, 2001).Google Scholar
Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Felix, A Thousand Plateaus, (trans.) Massumi, Brian (London: Athlone, 1987), 424–500.Google Scholar
Howell, Martha C., Commerce Before Capitalism in Europe: 1300–1600 (Cambridge University Press, 2010).Google Scholar
Webster, Charles, The Great Instauration: Science, Medicine and Reform 1626–1660 (London: Duckworth, 1975).Google Scholar
Žižek, Slavoj, The Parallax View (Cambridge Mass.: MIT 2006), 383–384.Google Scholar
Wolterstorff, Nicholas, Justice: Rights and Wrongs (Princeton University Press, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Witte, Jr. John, The Reformation of Rights: Law, Religion and Human Rights in Early Modern Calvinism (Cambridge University Press, 2010).Google Scholar
Fortin, Ernest L., ‘On the Presumed Medieval Origin of Individual Rights’, in his Classical Christianity and the Political Order; Reflections on the Theologico-Political Problem (Lanham Md.: Rowman Littlefield, 1996), 243–264.Google Scholar
Villey, Michel, La formation de la pensée juridique moderne (Paris: PUF, 2006);Google Scholar
Bastit, Michel, ‘Michel Villey et les ambiguités d’Occam’, in Garcin, Michael, (ed.), Droit, nature, histoire (Aix-en-Provence/Marseilles: Presses Universitaires D’Aix-Marseilles, 1985), 65–72;Google Scholar
Gutmann, Daniel, ‘La question du droit subjective chez Guillaume D’Occam’, in Le droit des modernes (XIVe –XVIIIe siècles), (ed.) Rials, Stéphane (Paris: Droit, 1998), 11–29.Google Scholar
Reid, Jr. Charles, ‘The Canonistic Contribution to the Western Rights Tradition: An Historical Inquiry’, Boston College Law Review, 33 (1991), 37–92;Google Scholar
Oakley, Francis, Natural Law, Laws of Nature, Natural Rights: Continuity and Discontinuity in the History of Ideas (New York: Continuum, 2005), 87–109.Google Scholar
Brett, Annabel S., Liberty, Right and Nature: Individual Rights in Later Scholastic Thought (Cambridge University Press, 2003)Google Scholar
Haakonssen, Knud, Natural Law and Moral Philosophy: From Grotius to the Scottish Enlightenment (Cambridge University Press, 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, Viscount Stair, The Institutions of the Law of Scotland (1693) (Edinburgh and Glasgow: Edinburgh University Press and Glasgow University Press, 1981)Google Scholar
Blackstone, William, On the Laws and Constitution of England (1796) (London: Elibron, 2005)Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair in Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (London: Duckworth, 1998), 228.Google Scholar
Thompson, Augustine, Cities of God (University Park, Pa.: Penn State University Press, 2006).Google Scholar
Milbank, John, ‘On Complex Space’, in Milbank, John, The Word Made Strange: Theology, Language, Culture (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997), 268–292.Google Scholar
Tuck, Richard, Natural Rights Theories: Their Origin and Development (Cambridge University Press, 1979);CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milbank, John, Theology and Social Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006), xxxii, 9–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finnis, John, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford University Press, 1980).Google Scholar
de Lagarde, Georges, La naissance de l’esprit laïque au déclin du Moyen Age, III Secteur Social de la Scolastique (Paris: Éditions Beatrice, 1942), 116–145.Google Scholar
Oakley, Francis, Natural Law, Laws of Nature, Natural Rights: Continuity and Discontinuity in the History of Ideas (New York: Continuum, 2005), 87–109.Google Scholar
William, , Opus nonaginta dierum, in Opera Politica, vol. I, (ed.) Offler, H.S. (Manchester University Press, 1956), 366.Google Scholar
Ockham, , Opus nonaginta dierum, vol. II, (ed.) Offler, (Manchester University Press, 1956), 573, 586.Google Scholar
Rousselot, Pierre, The Problem of Love in the Middle Ages, (trans.) Vincelette, Alan (Milwaukee,Wis.: Marquette University Press, 2006), 155–211;Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel, The Birth of Biopolitics, (trans.) Burchell, Graham (London: PalgraveMacmillan, 2008).Google Scholar
Moyn, Samuel, The Last Utopia: Human Rights in History (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2010).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×