Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-788cddb947-2s2w2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-19T13:07:25.749Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - The historical roots of the medieval concept of an infinite, extracosmic void space

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 October 2011

Edward Grant
Affiliation:
Indiana University
Get access

Summary

ARISTOTLE'S REJECTION OF EXTRACOSMIC VOID AND THE REACTION IN GREEK ANTIQUITY

The idea of extracosmic void space reached the Latin West from a number of sources during the Middle Ages. As with so much else, it was Aristotle who conveyed the concept in the form that would be most widely known and that would be central to all subsequent discussion. In the course of rejecting the existence of a plurality of worlds in De caelo, Aristotle declared categorically that “neither place, nor void, nor time” can exist “outside the heaven.” He had earlier argued that no bodily mass could come into being beyond the heavens, or outermost circumference of the universe, and inferred from this that neither place nor vacuum could exist there because “in every place a body can be present” (no body, therefore no place) and because “void is said to be that in which the presence of body, though not actual, is possible” (no possibility of body, therefore no vacuum). Aristotle concluded that absolutely nothing existed beyond the universe, a nothing that was best characterized as a privation. His denial of extracosmic existence to place, void, time, and body was frequently repeated. Special reliance was placed upon the necessary connection between body and void. By definition, vacuum was conceived as a place devoid of body but capable of receiving it.

Type
Chapter
Information
Much Ado about Nothing
Theories of Space and Vacuum from the Middle Ages to the Scientific Revolution
, pp. 105 - 115
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1981

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×