Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-dtkg6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-13T23:20:20.188Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2012

John Woods
Affiliation:
University of British Columbia, Vancouver
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Paradox and Paraconsistency
Conflict Resolution in the Abstract Sciences
, pp. 341 - 358
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2002

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ackermann, W., “Beggrüdung einer strengere Implikation,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 21 (1956), 113–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ainslie, G., “A Behavioral Economic Approach to the Defense Mechanism: Freud's Energy Theory Revisited,” Social Science Information, 21, 6 (1982), 735–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alchourrón, C. E., Gärdenfors, P., and Makinson, D., “On the Logic of Theory Change: Partial Meet Functions for Contraction and Revision.,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50 (1985), 510–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Alan RossMathematics and the ‘Language Game’,” Review of Metaphysics, 11 (1958), 446–58Google Scholar
Anderson, Alan Ross, and Belnap, Nuel D. Jr., Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, Vol. 1, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1975
Anderson, Alan Ross and Belnap, Nuel D. Jr., “A Simple Treatment of Truth Functions,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 24 (1959), 301–12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Alan Ross, and Belnap, Nuel D. Jr., Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, Vol. 2, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995
Apostoli, Peter, and Brown, Bryson, “A Solution to the Completeness Problem for Weakly Aggregative Modal Logic,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 60–3 (1995), 832–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle, Sophistical Refutations and Prior Analytics, Rhetoric, On Interpretation, Posterior Analytics and Metaphysics, in Jonathan Barnes (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle, The Revised Oxford Translation, Vols. 1 and 2., Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1984
Arrow, Kenneth J., Social Choice and Individual Values, New York: John Wiley, 1951
Avron, Arnon, “Whither Relevance Logic?,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 21 (1992), 243–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-Hillel, Y. (ed.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1965
Barnes, Jonathan (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle, The revised Oxford translation Vol. 1 and 2., Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1984
Barth, E. M., The Logic of Articles in Traditional Philosophy, Dordrecht and Boston: Reidel, 1974
Barth, E. M., and Krabbe, E. C. W. (eds.), Logic and Political Culture, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1990
Barth, E. M., and Krabbe, E. C. W., From Axiom to Dialogue: A philosophical study of logic and argumentation., Berlin: de Gruyter, 1992
Bartlett, F. C., Remembering, Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1932
Bartley, W. W., III (ed.), The Retreat to Commitment, revised and enlarged, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1984
Barwise, John (ed.), Handbook of Mathematical Logic, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1977
Barwise, John, and Etchemendy, John, The Liar, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984
Barwise, John, and Moss, Lawrence, Vicious Circles, Stanford, Calif.: CSLI Publications 1996
Batens, D., “Extensional Paraconsistent Logics,” Logique et Analyse, 90–91 (1980), 195–234Google Scholar
Becherand, W., and Essler, W. K. (eds.), Konzepte der Dialektik, Frankfurt/Main: Klostermann, 1981
Bell, John S., “On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Paradox,” Physics, 1 (1964), 195CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, J. L., “Category Theory and the Foundation of Mathematics,” British Journal of the Philosophy of Science, 32 (1981), 349–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Belnap, Nuel D., Jr., An Analysis of Questions: Preliminary Report, Santa Monica, Calif.: System Development Corporation, 1963
Belnap, Nuel D. Jr., “Gupta's Rule of Revision Theory of Truth,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 11 (1982), 103–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Belnap, Nuel D., Jr., and Steel, Thomas B., The Logic of Questions and Answers, New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1976
Benacerraf, Paul, “Mathematical Truth,” Journal of Philosophy, ⅬXX (1973), 661–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benardete, José A., Metaphysics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989
Beth, Evert W., “Towards An Up-to-date Philosophy of Natural Sciences,” Methods 1 (1949), 178–84Google Scholar
Birkhoff, G., “Lattices in Applied Mathematics,” American Mathematical Society, Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, 2 (1961), 155–84Google Scholar
Black, Max, “A Critical Review of [Quine's] Mathematical Logic,” Mind, 52 (1943), 264–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bläu, Ulrich, Die dreiwertige Logik der Sprache: Ihre Syntax, Semantik und Anwendung in der Sprachanalyse, Berlin: deGruyer, 1978
Bohm, David, Special Theory of Relativity, Amsterdam: W. A. Benjamins, 1965
Boolos, George S., “On Second Order Logic,” Journal of Philosophy, 72, 16 (1975), 509–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boolos, George, “Saving Frege From Contradiction,” in Richard Jeffrey (ed.), Logic, Logic and Logic, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998, 171–82
Boolos, George, and Jeffrey, Richard, Computability and Logic, 3rd edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989
Brady, R. T., “Depth Relevance of Some Paraconsistent Logics,” Studia Logica, 43 (1984), 63–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brady, R. T., “The Non-triviality of Dialectical Set Theory,” in Priest, Routley, and Norman (eds.), Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent., Münich: Philosophia Verlag, 1989, 437–71
Brady, R. T., Universal Logic, unpublished
Bradley, F. H., The Principles of Logic, two volumes, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1883; corrected impression 1922
Brown, Bryson, “Simple Natural Deduction for Weakly Aggregative Paraconsistent Logics,” in Dov Gabbay (ed.), Frontiers of Paraconsistent Logic, London: Research Studies Press, 2001
Brown, Bryson, “Approximate Truth: A Paraconsistent Account,” in Joke Meheus (ed.), Inconsistency in Science, vol. 2 in the series Origins: Studies in the Sources of Scientific Creativity, Amsterdam: Kluwer Academic, 2002
Brown, Bryson, and Schotch, Peter, “Logic and Aggregation,” The Journal of Philosophical Logic, 28 (1999), 265–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burali-Forti, “Una Questione Sui Numeri Transfiniti,” Rendiconti del Circolo Mathematico di Palermo, 11 (1897), translated as “A Question on Transfinite Numbers,” Jean van Heijenoort (trans.), in van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967, 104–12
Burge, Tyler, “Semantic Paradox,” Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), 169–98, reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), Recent Essays on Truth and The Liar Paradox, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984, 83–117
Burgess, John P., “Introduction to Part II,” in Richard Jeffrey (ed.), Logic, Logic and Logic, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998, 135–42
Cantor, George, “Beiträge zer Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre,” parts one and two, Mathematischen Annalen, 46 (1895), 481–512 and 49 (1897), 207–46; translated as Contributions to the Founding of the Theory of Transfinite Numbers, by P. E. B. Jourdain (trans.), Chicago: Open Court, 1915; reprinted New York: Dover, 1952, 85–201
Cantor, George, “Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre,” Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung 1 (1890–91), 75–8, reprinted in Ernst Zermelo (ed.), Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts, Berlin: Springer, 1932, 278–81
Cargile, James, Paradoxes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979
Carlsen, Laurie, Dialogue Games: An Approach to Discourse Analysis., Dordrecht: Reidel, 1983
Carlsen, Laurie, and ter Meulen, Alice, “Informational Independence in Intensional Contexts” in E. Saarinen et al. (eds.), Essays In Honor of Jaakko Hintikka, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979, 61–72
Carlson, Gregory N., and Pelletier, Francis Jeffry (eds.), The Generic Book, Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1995
Carnap, Rudolf, The Logical Syntax of Language, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1937
Cartwright, N., How the Laws of Physics Lie, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983
Cartwright, Richard, “Implications and Entailments,” in Richard Cartwright, Philosophical Essays, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987, 237–58
Cartwright, Richard, Philosophical Essays, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987
Cartwright, Richard L., “Propositions,” R. J. Butler (ed.), Analytical Philosophy, 1st Series, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1962, 81–103
Cartwright, Richard L., “Propositions Again,” Nôus 2 (1968), 229–46Google Scholar
Castañeda, Hector-Neri, “Fiction and Reality: Their Fundamental Connections,” in John Woods and Thomas Pavel (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics 8 (1979), 31–62
Cézanne, Paul, in W. Hess (ed.), Über die Kunst: Gespräche mit Gasquet, Mittenwald: Mäander, 1980
Chellas, Brian F., Modal Logic: An Introduction., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980CrossRef
Cherniak, Christopher, Minimal Rationality, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1986
Church, Alonzo, “The Weak Theory of Implication,” in Albert Menne, Alexander Wilhelmy, and Helmut Angstil (eds.), Untersuchungen zum Logikkalkül und zur Logik der Einzelwissenschaften, Freiburg: Kontrolliertes Denken, 1951, 22–37
Churchland, Paul M., “Eliminative Materialism,” Journal of Philosophy, 78 (1981), 67–90Google Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan, “On the Psychology of Prediction: Whose Is the Fallacy?,” Cognition 7 (1979), 385–407CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan, “Can Human Irrationality Be Experimentally Demonstrated?,” The Behavior and Brain Sciences 4 (1981), 317–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan, The Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon, 1986
Cohen, L. Jonathan, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Induction and Probability, Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1989
Cohen, L. Jonathan, “Reply to Stein,” Synthese 99 (1994), 173–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, A., and Quillam, M., “Retrieval Time From Semantic Memory,” Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 8 (1969), 240–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, WilliamOn Axiomatizability Within a System,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 (1953), 1, 30–2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, William, “Three Uses of the Herbrand-Gentzen Theorem,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (1957), 269–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Currie, Gregory, The Nature of Fiction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990
Curry, Haskell B., “The Paradox of Kleene and Rosser,” Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 50 (1941), 454–516CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curry, Haskell B., “The Inconsistency of Certain Formal Logics,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 7 (1942), 115–117CrossRefGoogle Scholar
da Costa, Newton C. A., “On the Theory of Inconsistent Formal Systems,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, XV (1974), 497–510CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dalla Chiara, M. L., “The Relevance of Quantum Logic,” Proceedings of the International Congress for Logic, Methodology and the Philosophy of Science, Salzburg: North-Holland, forthcoming
Davidson, Donald, “Theories of Meaning and Learnable Languages,” in Y. Bar-Hillel (ed.), Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, Amsterdam: North Holland, 1965, 383–94
Davidson, Donald, “Truth and Meaning,” Synthese, 17 (1967), 304–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald, “Psychology as Philosophy,” in J. Glover (ed.), The Philosophy of Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976, 101–10
DeVidi, David, and Solomon, Graham, “On Confusions About Bivalence and Excluded Middle,” Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, ⅹⅹⅹⅷ (1999), 785–99
Diaz, M. Richard, Topics in the Logic of Relevance, Munich: Philosophia Verlag, 1981
Doležel, Lubomír, “Extensional and Intentional Narrative Worlds,” John Woods and Thomas Pavel (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics, 8 (1979), 193–211
duBois-Reymond, Paul, “Eine neue Theorie der Convergenz und Divergenz von Reihen mit poitiven Gliedern,” Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik 76 (1873), 61–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dummet, Michael, Frege: Philosophy of Language, London: Duckworth, 1973
Dunn, J. Michael, “Relevant Logic and Entailment,” in D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol. 3: Alternatives to Classical Logic, Synthese Library, Vol. 166, Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 986, 117–224
Dunn, J. Michael, “Intuitive Semantics for First Degree Entailments and ‘Coupled Trees,’” Philosophical Studies, 29 (1976), 149–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eagleton, Terry, The Illusions of Postmodernism, Oxford: Blackwell, 1996
Einstein, AlbertIst die Traegheit eines Koerpers von seinem Energieinhalt abhaengig?,” Annalen der Physik 18 (1905), 639–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elgin, Catherine Z., Considered Judgement, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1996
Elster, Jon, Sour Grapes: Studies in the Subversion of Rationality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, “Self Reliance,” in Essays, London: Aldine Press, 1967
Feferman, Solomon, “Toward Useful Type-Free Theories, I,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 49 (1984), 75–111, reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), Truth and the Liar Paradox, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 237–87
Festinger, Leon, A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1957
Feyerabend, Paul, Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge, London: Verso, 1978
Fine, Kit, “Incompleteness for Quantified Relevance Logics,” in Jean Norman and Richard Sylvan (eds.), Directions in Relevant Logic, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 1989, 205–25
Flew, Anthony (ed.), Essays in Conceptual Analysis, London: Macmillan, 1960
Forrest, Peter, Quantum Metaphysics, Oxford: Blackwell, 1988
Frege, Gottlob, 1893–1903 partial translation as The Basic Laws of Arithmetic: Exposition of the System (Montgomery Furth, ed. and trans.), Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1964
Frege, Gottlob, Grundgeseze der Arithmetik, Jena: Pohle, 1903; partial translation as The Basic Laws of Arithmetic: Exposition of the System, Montgomery Furth (trans. and ed.), Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1964
Frege, Gottlob, Letter to Russell, in van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967, 127–8
Frege, Gottlob, Foundations of Arithmetic, J. L. Austin (trans.), Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1950
French, Simon, Decision Theory: An Introduction to the Mathematics of Rationality, Chichester, U.K.: Ellis Horwood, 1986
Friedman, Harvey, and Meyer Robert K., “Can We Implement Relevant Arithmetic?,” Technical Report TF-ARP-12/88, Automated Reasoning Project, Research School of Social Science, Australian National University, 1988
Frye, Northrop, The Great Code, Toronto: Academic Press, 1981
Fuhrmann, A., Relevant Logics, Modal Logics and Theory Change, Ph.D. Thesis, Australian National University, 1988
Gabbay, Dov M., “Dynamics of Practical Reasoning: A Position Paper,” in Advances in Modal Logic 2, K. Segerberg, M. Zkharayashev, M. de Rijke, and H. Wansing, (eds.), CSLI Publications, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, 179–224
Gabbay, Dov M., and Guenthner, F. (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol. 3, Dordrecht and Boston: Reidel, 1984
Gabbay, Dov M., and Hunter, Anthony, “Making Inconsistency Respectable, Part I,” in P. Jorrand and J. Kelemen (eds.), Fundamentals of Artificial Intelligence Research (FAIR '91), LNAI, Vol. 535, Springer-Verlag, 1991
Gabbay, Dov M., and Hunter, Anthony, “Making Inconsistency Respectable, Part II,” in M. Clarke, R. Kruse, and S. Seraffin (eds.), Symbolic and Quantitative Approaches to Reasoning and Uncertainty: European Conference ECSQARU '93, Granada, Spain, LNCS, Vol. 747, Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 1993
Gabbay, Dov M., and Woods, John, “Non-cooperation in Dialogue Logic: Getting Beyond the Goody Two-Shoes Model of Argument,” Synthese, forthcoming
Gabbay, Dov M., and Woods, John, “More on Non-cooperation in Dialogue Logic,” Logic Journal of the IGPL, 9 (2001), 321–39CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gabriel, GottfriedFiction: A Semantic Approach,” Poetics: Journal of Empirical Research on Literature, the Media and the Arts, 8.2 (1979), 245–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaifman, Haim, “Operational Pointer Semantics: Solution to Self-referential Puzzlers I,” M. Vardi (ed.), Proceedings of the Second Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning About Knowledge, Los Altos, Calif.: Morgan Kaufman, 1988, 43–60
Gäredenfors, Peter, Knowledge in Flux: Modeling the Dynamics of Epistemic States, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987
Garey, Michael R., and Johnson, David S., Computers and Intractability, San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1979
Peter, Geach, “Entailment,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Vol. 32 (1958), 143–72; reprinted in Peter Geach, Logic Matters, Oxford: Blackwell, 1972, 174–86Google Scholar
Gellner, Ernest, Words and Things, Harmondsworth, U.K.: Penguin, 1968
Gibbins, PeterA User-Friendly Quantum Logic,” Logique et Analyse, 112 (1985), 353–62Google Scholar
Gilles, Donald, Philosophy of Science in the Twentieth Century: Four Central Themes, Oxford: Blackwell, 1993
Gilbert, Margaret, On Social Facts, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1993
Gilmore, P. C., “The Consistency of Partial Set Theory Without Extensionality,” in Dana Scott (ed.), Symposium in Pure Mathematics, University of California, Los Angeles, 1967; Axiomatic Set Theory, Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, XIII Pt. 2, American Mathematical Society, 1974
Girle, Roderic A., “Dialogue and Entrenchment,” Proceedings of the Sixth Florida Artificial Intelligence Research Symposium, Fort Lauderdale, 1993, 105–89
Girle, Roderic A., “Knowledge: Organized and Disorganized,” Proceedings of the Seventh Florida Artificial Intellegence Research Symposium, Pensacola Beach, Fla., 1994, 198–203Google Scholar
Girle, Roderic A., “Commands in Dialogue Logic,” Proceedings of the International Conference on Formal and Applied Practical Reasoning, Bonn, 1996, 246–60
Girle, Roderic A., “Belief Sets and Commitment Stores,” in Hans V. Hansen, Christopher W. Tindale, and Athena V. Colman (eds.), Argumentation and Rhetoric, St. Catharines, Ont.: OSSA, 1998
Glover, J. (ed.), The Philosophy of Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976
Gochet, Paul, Ascent to Truth, Münich: Philosophia Verlag, 1986
Gödel, Kurt, “What Is Cantor's Continuum Problem?,” American Mathematical Monthly, 54 (1947), 515–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goghossian, DaveWhat the Sokal Hoax Ought to Teach Us,” Times Literary Supplement December 13 (1996), 14–15Google Scholar
Goodman, Nelson, Fact, Fiction and Forecast, 2nd ed., New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965
Grattan-Guiness, Ivor, “How Bertrand Russell Discovered His Paradox,” Historia Mathematica, 5 (1978), 127–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, Nicholas, Russell's Idealist Apprenticeship, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991
Gupta, Anil, “Truth and Paradox,” in Robert L. Martin (ed.) Recent Essays on Truth and the Liar Paradox, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 175–236
Gupta, Anil, and Belnap, Nuel D., Jr., The Revision of Theory of Truth, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993
Haack, Susan, Deviant Logic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1974
Hacking, IanWhat Is Logic?,” The Journal of Philosophy, ⅬXXVI (1979), 285–319CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, Ian, Representing and Intervening, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983
Hahn, Lewis Edwin (ed.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, second rev. ed., LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1998
Hahn, Lewis Edwin, and Schilpp, Paul Arthur (eds.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986
Hallett, Michael, Cantorian Set Theory and Limitation of Size, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984
Hamblin, C. L., Fallacies, London: Methuen, 1970
Hansen, Hans V., and Pinto, Robert C. (eds.), Fallacies: Classical and Contemporary Readings, University Park: Pennsylvania State University, 1995
Harman, GilbertIs Modal Logic Logic?,” Philosophia 2 (1972), 75–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, Gilbert, The Nature of Morality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977
Harman, Gilbert, Change in View, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1986
Harrah, David, Communication: A Logical Model, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1963
Hart, W. D., “Access and Inference,” in W. D. Hart (ed.), Philosophy of Mathematics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996, 52–62
Hausman, Daniel M., “Introduction” in Daniel M. Hausman (ed.), The Philosophy of Economics: An Anthology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984, 1–50
Heintz, John, “Reference and Inference in Fiction,” John Woods and Thomas Pavel (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics 8 (1979), 85–99
Henkin, LeonSome Remarks on Infinitely Long Formulas,” in Infinite Models, New York: Pergamon, 1961, 167–83Google Scholar
Henson, C. Ward, “Reviews of Jensen, R. B. reply to Quine and Quine to Jenson,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 40 (1975), 241–2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hermes, Hans, Kambartel, Friedrich, and Kaulbach, Friedrich (eds.), Frege: Posthumous Writings, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979
Herzberger, Hans G., “Paradoxes of Grounding in Semantics,” Journal of Philosophy 67 (1970), 145–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herzberger, Hans G., “Notes on Naive Semantics,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 11 (1982), 62–102, reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), Recent Essays on Truth and The Liar Paradox, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 134–74
Hilbert, David, Grundlagen der Geometrie, Leipzig: Teubner; translated as The Foundations of Geometry, E. J. Townsend (trans.), Chicago: Open Court, 1902; 10th edition, with a supplement by Paul Bernays translated under the previous English title, La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1971
Hinman, P., Kim, J., and Stich, S., “Logical Truth Revisited,” The Journal of Philosophy, ⅬXV (1968), 495–500CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, Knowledge and Belief, Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1962
Hintikka, JaakkoA Counter-example to Tarski-type Truth definitions as Applied to Natural Languages,” Philosophia, 5 (1975), 207–12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, The Semantics of Questions and the Questions of Semantics [= Acta Philosophica Fernica 28 (1976)]
Hintikka, JaakkoThe Role of Logic in Argumentation,” The Monist, 72 (1989), 3–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, “Information-Seeking Dialogues,” in W. Becherand and W. K. Essler (eds.), Konzepte der Dialektik, Frankfurt/Main: Klostermann, 1981, 212–31
Hintikka, Jaakko, The Principles of Mathematics Revisited, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996
Holland, J. H., Holyoak, K. J., Nisbett, R. E., and Thagard, P. R., Induction: Processes of Inference, Learning and Discovery, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987
Hooker, C. A. (ed.), The Logico-Algebraic Approach to Quantum Mechanics, Vol. 1: Historical Evolution, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979
Hookway, Christopher, Quine, Oxford: Polity Press, 1988
Howe, M., Introduction to Human Memory, New York: Harper & Row, 1970
Howell, Robert, “Fictional Objects: How They Are and How They Aren't,” in John Woods and Thomas Pavel (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics 8 (1979), 50–72
Howell, Robert, “Review of [Parsons's] ‘Non-existent Objects,’” Journal of Philosophy, 80 (1983), 163–73Google Scholar
Hughes, G. E., and Cresswell, M. J., An Introduction to Modal Logic, London: Methuen, 1968
Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, Ernest C. Mossner (ed.), Harmondsworth, U.K.: Penguin Books, 1969
Hylton, Peter, Russell, Idealism and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990
Iseminger, GaryRelatedness Logic and Entailment,” The Journal of Non-Classical Logic 3 (1986), 5–23Google Scholar
Jacquette, Dale, “Logical Dimensions of Question-Begging Argument,” American Philosophical Quarterly 30 (1993), 317–27Google Scholar
Jáskowski, Leon, “Propositional Calculus for Contradictory Systems,” Studia Logica XXVI (1969), 143–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jech, Thomas J., “About the Axiom of Choice,” in Jon Barwise (ed.), Handbook of Mathematical Logic, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1977, 345–70
Johnson-Liard, P. H., and Byrne, R. M. J., Deduction, Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1991
Johnson-Laird, P. N., and Wason, P. C. (eds.), Thinking: Readings in Cognitive Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977
Johnstone, Henry W., Jr., Validity and Rhetoric in Philosophical Argument, University Park, Penn.: The Dialogue Press of Man and World, 1978
Johnston, Davidand Jennings, R. E., “Paradox Tolerant LogicsLogique et Analyse 26 (1983), 291–308Google Scholar
Kalish, Donald, Montague, Richard, and Mar, Gary, Logic: Techniques of Formal Reasoning, 2nd ed., San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1980
Kanigel, Robert, The Man Who Knew Infinity: A Life of the Genius Ramanujan, New York: Scribner, 1991
Kant, Imanuel, Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of Principles of Natural Theology and Morality, and Logic, Indianapolis, Ind.: Bobbs-Merrill, 1764/1800/1974
Kant, Imanuel, Hartman, Robert S., and Schwartz, Wolfgang (trans. with introduction) Logic, Indianapolis, Ind.: Bobbs-Merrill, 1974
Kaplan, David, “Bob and Carl and Ted and Alice,” in Jaakko Hintikka et al. (eds.), Approaches to Natural Languages, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1973, 490–518
Kaplan, David, and Montague, Richard, “A Paradox Regained,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 1 (1960), 79–90; reprinted in Richard Montague, Formal Philosophy, New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1974, 271–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaufmann, W., “Uber die Konstitution des Elektrons,” Annalen der Physik, 19 (1906), 487
Keynes, John Maynard, “Letter to R. F. Harrod, 4 July 1938,” in Moggridge (ed.), Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes, Vol. 14, The General Theory and After: Part II: Defense and Development, London: Macmillan, 1973
A., Klatzley, Human Memory: Structures and Processes, San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1975
Kline, Morris, Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty, New York: Oxford University Press, 1980
Koryé, A., “The Liar,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 6 (1946), 344–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul, “Outline of a Theory of Truth,” Journal of Philosophy, 72 (1975), 690–716 reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), The Paradox of the Liar, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 134–74
Kripke, Saul A., Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980
Lakatos, Imre, Mathematics, Science and Epistemology, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1980
Lambert, Karel, “Logic and Microphysics,” in Karel Lambert (ed.), The Logical Way of Doing Things, New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1969, 93–117
Lester, R., “Shortcomings of Marginal Analysis for Wage-Employment Problems,” American Economic Review, 36 (1946), 63–82Google Scholar
Lester, R., “Marginalism, Minimum Wages. and Labour Markets,” American Economic Review, 37 (1947), 135–48Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I., “Implication and the Algebra of Logic,” Mind 21 (1912), 522–531. Collected Papers, pp. 351–359CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, C. I., and Langford, C. H., Symbolic Logic, New York: Dover, 1932
Lewis, David, “Truth in Fiction,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 15 (1978), 37–46, reprinted with postscripts in David Lewis (ed.), Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983, 261–75Google Scholar
Lewis, David K., Convention, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969
Lieber, J., and Stoller, M., “Is that all there is?,” recorded on Capital Records by Peggy Lee in 1969Google Scholar
Lindsay, P., and Norman, D., Human Information Processing, New York: Academic Press, 1977
Lindstrom, PerOn Extensions of Elementary Logic,” Theoria, XXXV (1969), 1–11Google Scholar
Löb, M. H., “Solution of a Problem of Leon Henken,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 20 (1955), 115–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John, Essay On Human Understanding, Peter H. Niddith (ed. with introduction), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975
Lorentz, Hendrik Antoon, The Theory of Electrons and Its Application to the Phenomena of Light and Radiant Heat, 3rd ed., New York: Dover, 1952
Mackenzie, J. D., “Question-Begging in Non-Cumulative Systems,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8 (1979), 117–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackenzie, J. D., “Begging the Question in Dialogue,” Australian Journal of Philosophy, 62 (1984), 174–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Donald, “Review of Jean van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel,” Journal of Philosophy, 67 (1970), 113
Martin, Robert L. (ed.), Recent Essays On Truth and the Liar Paradox, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984
Martin, Robert, and Woodruff, Peter, “On Representing ‘True-in-L’ in L,” Philosophia 5 (1975), 213–17, reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), The Paradox of the Liar, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 47–51
McGee, Vann, Truth, Vagueness and Paradox, Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1990
McKinsey, J. C. C., Sugar, A. C., and Suppes, Patrick, “Axiomatic Foundations of Classical Particle Mechanics,” Journal of Rational Mechanics and Analysis, 2 (1953), 253–72Google Scholar
Menne, Albert, Wilhelmy, Alexander, and Angstil, Helmut (eds.), Untersuchungen zum Logikkalkül und zur Logik der Einzelwissenschaften, Freiburg: Kontrolliertes Denken, 1951
Mermin, N. B., “Quantum Mysteries for Everyone,” Journal of Philosophy, 78 (1981), 397–408CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyer, R. K., “Entailment,” The Journal of Philosophy, 68 (1971), 808–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyer, Robert, and Routley, Richard, “Dialectical Logic and Consistency of the World,” Studies in Soviet Thought, 16 (1975), 1–25Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart, “On the Definition of Political Economy and the Method of Investigation Proper to It,” in John Robson (ed.), Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Vol. IV, Essays on Economics and Society 1824–1845, Toronto: Toronto University Press, 1967, 309–39
Mill, John Stuart, A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive, in John Robson (ed.) Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Vol. VIII Book II of Reasoning and Book III of Induction, Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1974, 157–640
Millikan, Ruth Garrett, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1984
Minsky, Marvin, The Society of the Mind, New York: Simon and Schuster, 1987
Moore, G. E., “The Nature of Judgement,” Mind 7 (1898), 176–93Google Scholar
Moore, G. E., “Critical Notice on Russell's An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry,” Mind 8 (1899), 397–405Google Scholar
Moore, G. E., Principia Ethica, Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1903
Moore, G. E., “The Refutation of Idealism,” Mind 12 (1903), 433–53; reprinted in G. E. Moore, Philosophical Studies, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1922, 1–30
Moore, G. E., Philosophical Studies, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1922
Moore, G. E., Philosophical Papers, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1959
Moore, G. E., “Russell's Theory of Descriptions,” in G. E. Moore, Philosophical Papers, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1959, 151–95
Mortensen, Chris, Inconsistent Mathematics, Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer, 1995
Mortensen, Chris, “Paraconsistency and C1,” in Graham Priest, Richard Routely, and Jean Norman (eds.), Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, Münich: Philosophia Verlag, 1989, 289–305
Myrdal, Gunnar, Objectivity in Social Research, London: Duckworth, 1970
Nagel, Ernest, Suppes, Patrick, and Tarski, Alfred (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1962
Nekham, Alexander, De Naturis Rerum, T. Wright (ed.), London: Longman, 1863
Newell, Allen, and Simon, Herbert A., Human Problem Solving, Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1972
Nisbett, R., and Ross, L., Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgement, Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1980
Norman, Jean, and Sylvan, Richard, Directions in Relevant Logic, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 1989
Nozick, Robert, “Experience, Theory and Language,” in Lewis Edwin Hahn and Paul Arthur Schilpp (eds.), The Philosophy of Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986, 339–63
Parsons, Charles, “The Liar Paradox,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 3 (1974), 381–412, reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), Truth and The Liar Paradox, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 9–45
Parsons, Terence, Non-existent Objects, New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1980
Parsons, TerenceTrue Contradictions,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 20 (1990), 335–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pavel, Thomas, Fictional Worlds, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986
Peacocke, ChristopherWhat Is a Logical Constant?”, The Journal of Philosophy, ⅬXXIII (1976), 221–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin, The Nature of Necessity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974
Plantinga, Alvin, Warrant and Proper Function, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993
Plato, Meno, in E. Hamilton and H. Cairns (eds.), Plato: The Collected Dialogues., Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1980, 353–84
Post, John F., “A Gödelian Theorem for Theories of Rationality,” in G. Radnitzky and W. W. Bartley, III (eds.), Evolutionary Epistemology, Rationality, and the Sociology of Knowledge, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1987
Priest, Graham, “The Logic of Paradox,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8 (1979), 219–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Priest, Graham, In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 1987
Priest, Graham, Beyond the Limits of Thought, Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1995
Priest, Graham, and Routley, Richard, “Applications of Paraconsistent Logic,” in Graham Priest, Richard Routley, and Jean Norman (eds.) Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, München: Philosophia Verlag, 1989, 367–93
Priest, Graham, and Routley, Richard, “Systems of Paraconsistent Logic” in Graham Priest, Richard Routley, and Jean Norman (eds.), Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, Münich: Philosophia Verlag, 1989, 151–86
Priest, Graham, Routley, Richard, and Norman, Jean, Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, Münich: Philosophia Verlag, 1989
Putnam, Hilary, “The Logic of Quantum Mechanics,” in Mathematics, Matter and Method: Philosophical Papers, Vol. I, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975, 174–97Google Scholar
Quine, W. V., “Truth by Convention,” in O. H. Lee (ed.), Philosophical Essays for A. N. Whitehead, New York: Longmans, 1936, 90–124
Quine, W. V., “Notes on Existence and Necessity,” Journal of Philosophy, 40 (1943), 113–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V., “The Problem of Interpreting Modal Logic,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 12 (1947), 43–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V., “Review of Geach, Subject and Predicate,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 16 (1951), 138Google Scholar
Quine, W. V., Mathematical Logic, rev. ed., Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1951
Quine, W. V., From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1953
Quine, W. V., “New Foundations for Mathematical Logic,” reprinted with additions in From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1953, 80–101Google Scholar
Quine, W. V., Word and Object, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1960
Quine, W. V., The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, rev. and enlarged ed., Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1976
Quine, W. V., Selected Logic Papers, New York: Random House, 1966; enlarged edition, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995
Quine, W. V., Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, New York: Columbia University Press, 1969
Quine, W. V., Set Theory and Its Logic, rev. ed., Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969
Quine, W. V., Philosophy of Logic, Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1970; second ed., Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986
Quine, W. V., Roots of Reference: The Paul Carus Lectures, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court 1973
Quine, W. V., “Reply to Manley Thompson,” in Lewis Edwin Hahn and Paul Arthur Schilpp (eds.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court 1986, 564–8
Quine, W. V., “Empirically Equivalent Systems of the World,” Erkenntnis 9 (1975), 313–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V., “Reply to Robert Nozick,” in Lewis Edwin Hahn and Paul Aurthur Schilpp (eds.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986, 364–8
Quine, W. V., Theories and Things, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1981
Quine, W. V., “Things and Their Place in Theories,” Theories and Things, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1981, 1–23Google Scholar
Quine, W. V., “Ontology and Ideology Revisited,” Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983), 499–501CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V., Quiddities, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1987
Quine, W. V., The Pursuit of Truth, revised edition, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990/1992
Quine, W. V., “Structure and Nature,” The Journal of Philosophy, ⅬXXIX (1992), 5–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V., From Stimulus to Science, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995
Quine, W. V., and Ullian, J. W., The Web of Belief, New York: Random House, 1970
Raiffa, Howard, Decision Analysis, Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1968
Ramsey, Frank P., The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1931
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971
Rawls, JohnThe Independence of Moral Theory,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 48 (1974–5), 5–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Read, Stephen, Relevant Logic: A Philosophical Examination of Inference, Oxford: Blackwell, 1988
Rescher, N. (ed.), Studies in the Philosophy of Mind, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1972
Rescher, Nicholas, and Brandon, Robert, The Logic of Inconsistency: A Study in Non-standard Possible-world Semantics and Ontology, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980
Richard, Jules, “The Principles of Mathematics and the Problem of Sets,” in Jean van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1967, 143–4
Rips, Lance J., The Psychology of Proof: Deductive Reasoning in Human Thinking, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1994
Ross, W. D., Aristotle, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1953
Rosser, BarkleyThe Burali-Forti Paradox,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 7 (1942), 1–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Routley, Richard, “Some Things Do Not Exist,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, VII (1966), 251–76
Routley, Richard, “The Semantic Structure of Fictional Discourse,” in John Woods and Thomas Pavel (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics, 8 (1979), 3–30
Routley, Richard, and Routley, Val, “The Semantics of First Degree Entailment,” NoÛs, 6 (1972), 335–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, Bertrand, “On The Axioms of Geometry,” in Nicholas Griffin and Albert C. Lewis (eds.), The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell Volume II, Philosophical Papers 1896–99, London: G. Allen and Unwin, 1983, 390–415
Russell, Bertrand, A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1900; republished London: George Allen and Unwin, 1937
Russell, Bertrand, The Principles of Mathematics, 2nd ed., London: Allen and Unwin, 1937
Russell, BertrandOn Denoting,” Mind N.S. XIV (1905), 479–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, Bertrand, An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry, New York: Dover, 1956
Russell, Bertrand, My Philosophical Development, London: Allen and Unwin, 1959
Russell, Bertrand, Our Knowledge of the External World: As a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy, London: Allen and Unwin, 1961
Russell, Bertrand, “Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types,” in Jean van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967, 152–82
Ryle, Gilbert, “Are There Propositions?,” in Collected Papers 2: Collected Essays 1929–1968, London: Hutchinson and Co., 1971, 12–38. Reprinted from the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. ⅹⅹⅹ, 1930
Ryle, Gilbert, Philosophical Arguments, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1945
Ryle, GilbertOrdinary Language,” The Philosophical Review ⅬⅫ (1953), 167–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert, “Proofs in Philosophy,” in Gilbert Ryle (ed.) Collected Papers 2: Collected Essays 1929–1968, London: Hutchinson, 1972, 319–25
Ryle, GilbertUse, Usage and Meaning,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary vol. XXXV (1961), 223–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sainsbury, R. M., Paradoxes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988
Savage, Leonard J., The Foundations of Statistics, New York: John Wiley, 1954
Schotch, P. K., “Paraconsistent Logic: The View from the Right,” Philosophy of ScienceAssociation 2 (1993), 421–9Google Scholar
Schotch, P. K., and Jennings, R. E., “On Detonating,” in Graham Priest, Richard Routley, and Jean Norman (eds.), Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, Munich: Philosophia, 1989, 306–27
Sen, Amartya, “Social Choice Theory,” in Kenneth J. Arrow and M. D. Intriligator (eds.), Handbook of Mathematical Economics, Vol. III, Los Altos, Calif.: Morgan Kaufmann, 1986, 1070–181
Sen, Amartya, On Ethics and Economics, Oxford: Blackwell, 1987
Sher, Gila, The Bounds of Logic, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1991
Shoenfield, Joseph R., Mathematical Logic, Reading, Mass.: Allison-Wesley, 1967
Simmons, Keith, Universality of the Liar, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993
Skolem, Th., “Untersuchungen über die Axiome des Klassenlalkuss,” in Th. Skolem (ed.), Selected Works in Logic, Oslo: Universitetsforlaget 1970, 67–101
Slater, B. H., “Paraconsistent Logics?,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 24 (1995), 451–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smiley, Timothy J., “Entailment and Deducibility,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Vol. 32 (1958), 123–42Google Scholar
Soames, Scott, Understanding Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999
Sorenson, Roy A., Blindspots, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988
Sperber, Dan, and Wilson, Deirdre, Relevance, Oxford: Blackwell, 1986
Starmans, Richard, Logic, Argumentation and Common Sense, Tilburg: Tilburg University Print, 1996
Stein, EdwardRationality and Reflective Equilibrium,” Synthese, 99 (1994), 137–72Google Scholar
Stich, Stephen, The Fragmentation of Reason, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990
Stich, Stephen, and Nisbett, Richard, “Justification and Psychology of Human Reasoning,” Philosophy of Science, 47 (1980), 188–202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suppes, Patrick, Introduction to Logic, New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold, 1957
Suppes, Patrick, “Models of Data,” in Ernest Nagel, Patrick Suppes, and Alfred Tarski (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1962, 252–61
Suppes, Patrick, “A Comparison of the Meaning and Uses of Models in Mathematics and the Empirical Sciences,” Synthese 12 (1960), 287–301CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suppes, Patrick, “The Philosophical Relevance of Decision Theory,” The Journal of Philosophy, 58 (1960), 606–14Google Scholar
Suppes, Patrick, “Logics Appropriate to Empirical Theories,” in C. A. Hooker (ed.), The Logico-Algebraic Approach to Quantum Mechanics Vol I: Historical Evaluation, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979, 329–40
Suppes, Patrick, Studies in the Methodology and Foundations of Science, New York: Humanities Press, 1969
Tarski, Alfred, “On the Concept of Logical Consequence,” in Alfred Tarski, Logic, Semantics, Metamathemathics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, J. H. Woodger (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press: 2nd ed., John Corcoran (ed.), Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1983, 409–20
Tarski, Alfred, Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, J. H. Woodger (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press: 2nd ed., John Corcoran (ed.), Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1983
Tarski, Alfred, “The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages,” in Alfred Tarski, Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, J. H. Woodger (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press: 2nd ed., John Corcoran (ed.), Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1983, 152–278
Tennant, Neil, “Natural Deduction and Gentzen Sequent Systems for Intuitionistic Relevant Logic,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 52 (1987), 665–80CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tennant, Neil, Autologic, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1993
ter Meulen, Alice G. B. (ed.), Studies in Model Theoretic Semantics, Dordrecht: Foris, 1983
Turkle, Sherry, “Artificial Intelligence and Psychoanalysis,” in Graubard (ed.), The Artificial Intelligence Debate: False Starts, Real Foundations, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988, 260–1
Ullian, Joseph S., “Quine and the Field of Mathematical Logic,” Lewis E. Hahn and Paul A. Schilpp (eds.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986, 569–89
Urmson, J. O., Philosophical Analysis: Its Development Between the Two World Wars, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1956
Urquhart, Alasdair, “The Undecidability of Entailment and Relevant Implication,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (1984), 1059–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Benthem, Johan, “Five Easy Pieces,” in Johan van Benthem and Alice G. B. ter Meulen (eds.), Studies in Model Theoretic Semantics, Dordrecht: Foris, 1983, 1–17
Benthem, Johany, “What Is Dialectical Logic?,” Erkenntnis 14 (1979), 333–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Benthem, Johan, and ter Meulen, Alice G. B. (eds.), Generalized Quantifiers in Natural Language, Dordrecht: Foris, 1985
van Eemeren Frans H., et al., Fundamentals of Argumentation Theory: A Handbook of Historical Backgrounds and Contemporary Developments, Mahwah, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1996
van Eemeren, Frans H., and Grootendorst, Rob, Speech Acts in Argumentation Discussions, Dordrecht: Foris, 1984
Fraassen, Bas C., “Meaning Relations Among Predicates,” NoÛs 1 (1967), 161–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C., Formal Semantics and Logic, New York: Macmillan, 1971
van Fraassen, Bas C., “The Labyrinth of Quantum Logics,” in C. A. Hooker (ed.), The Logico-Algebraic Approach to Quantum Mechanics Vol. I: Historical Evolution, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1975, 577–607
van Fraassen, Bas C., The Scientific Image, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980
van Heijenoort, Jean (ed.), From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book of Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967
Inwagen, Peter, “Creatures of Fiction,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 14 (1997), 299–308Google Scholar
Veyne, Paul, Le Pain et le Cirque, Paris: Seuil, 1976
von Mises, Ludwig, Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1949
von Mises, Ludwig, Epistemological Problems of Economics, G. Riseman (trans.), New York: New York University Press, 1981
von Neumann, John, Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1953
Wright, G. H., “The Concept of Entailment,” Logical Studies, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1957, 166–91Google Scholar
Walton, D. N., Logical Dialogue – Games and Fallacies, London: University Press of America, 1984
Walton, D. N., “Burden of Proof,” Argumentation, 2 (1988), 233–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walton, D. N., and Krabbe, E. C. W., Commitment in Dialogue, Albany: State University of New York, 1995
Walton, Douglas, A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy, Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press, 1995
Walton, Kendall, Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990
Wang, Hao, “Quine's Logical Ideas in Historical Perspective,” in Lewis E. Hahn and Paul A. Schilpp (eds.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986, 623–43
Whately, Richard, Elements of Logic, 1st edition, Book 3, Section 13, New York: Harper and Row, 1826/1853
Wilson, N. L., “Substances Without Substrata,” Review of Metaphysics, 12 (1959), 521–39Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, London: Routledge and Keagan Paul, 1958
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, Oxford: Blackwell, 1964
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, in C. Diamond (ed.), Wittgenstein's Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge, 1939, Hassocks, U.K.: Harvester Press 1976
Woods, John, “The Contradiction-Exterminator,” Analysis, XXV (1965), 49–53CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, JohnFictionality and the Logic of Relations,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 7 (1969), 51–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, John, “Essentialism, Self-Identity, and Quantifying In,” in Milton K. Muntitz (ed.), Identity and Individuation, New York: New York University Press, 1971, 165–98
Woods, John, The Logic of Fiction: A Philosophical Sounding of Deviant Logic, The Hague and Paris: Mouton, 1974
Woods, JohnIdentity and Modality,” Philosophia V (1975), 69–120CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, John, “Critical Notice of Deviant Logic,” Canadian Journal of Philsophy VII (1977), 651–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, John, Engineered Death: Abortion, Suicide, Euthanasia, Senecide, Ottawa, Ont.: University of Ottawa Press, 1978
Woods, John, “Ideals of Rationality in Dialogic,” Argumentation, 2 (1988), 419–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, John, “The Relevance of Relevant Logic,” in J. Norman and R. Sylvan (eds.), Directions in Relevant Logics, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher, 1989, 77–86
Woods, John, “And So Indeed Are Perfect Cheat,” Argumentation, 9 (1995), 654–68
Woods, John, “Semantic Intuitions” in Johan van Bentham, Frans H. van Eemeren, Rob Grootendorst, and Frank Veltman (eds.), Logic and Argumentation, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1996, 179–208
Woods, John, “A Captious Nicety of Argument: The Philosophy of W. V. Quine,” in Lewis E. Hahn (ed.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, Library of Living Philosophers, 2nd rev. ed., LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court Press, 1998, 687–725
Woods, John, Aristotle's Earlier Logic, Oxford: Hermes Science Publications, 2001
Woods, John, and Pavel, Thomas (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics 8 (1979)
Woods, John, and Peacock, Kent, “What Physics Does to Logic: The Current State of Quantum Logic Is Incompatible With,” forthcoming
Woods, John, and Walton, Douglas, “Arresting Circles in Formal Dialogues,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 7 (1978), 73–90; reprinted in John Woods and Douglas Walton, Fallacies: Selected Papers 1972–1982, Berlin: Foris/deGruyter, 1988, 143–159
Woods, John, and Walton, Douglas, “Question-Begging and Cumulativeness in Dialectical Games,” Nôus 16 (1982), 585–606; reprinted in John Woods and Douglas Walton, Fallacies: Selected Papers 1972–1982, Berlin: Foris/deGruyter 1988, 253–72
Woods, John, and Walton, Douglas, Argument: The Logic of Fallacies., Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson, 1982
Woods, John, and Walton, Douglas, Fallacies: Selected Papers 1972–1982, Berlin: Foris/de Gruyter, 1988
Wright, Crispin, Frege's Conception of Numbers as Objects, Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press, 1983
Zalta, Edward N., Abstract Objects: An Introduction to Axiomatic Metaphysics, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1983
Zermelo, Ernst, “Beweis, das jede Menge wohlgeoronet werden kann,” Mathematischen Annalen 59 (1904), 514–16; translated as “Proof That Every Set Can Be Well-ordered,” S. Bauer-Mengelburge (trans.), in Jean van Heijenvoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967, 139–41
Zermelo, Ernst, “Uber Grenzzahlen und Megenbereiche: neue Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre,” Fundamentae Mathematicae, 16 (1930), 29–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zucker, J., “The Adequacy Problem for Classical Logic,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 7, 4 (1978), 517–35Google Scholar
Ackermann, W., “Beggrüdung einer strengere Implikation,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 21 (1956), 113–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ainslie, G., “A Behavioral Economic Approach to the Defense Mechanism: Freud's Energy Theory Revisited,” Social Science Information, 21, 6 (1982), 735–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alchourrón, C. E., Gärdenfors, P., and Makinson, D., “On the Logic of Theory Change: Partial Meet Functions for Contraction and Revision.,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50 (1985), 510–30CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Alan RossMathematics and the ‘Language Game’,” Review of Metaphysics, 11 (1958), 446–58Google Scholar
Anderson, Alan Ross, and Belnap, Nuel D. Jr., Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, Vol. 1, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1975
Anderson, Alan Ross and Belnap, Nuel D. Jr., “A Simple Treatment of Truth Functions,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 24 (1959), 301–12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Alan Ross, and Belnap, Nuel D. Jr., Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, Vol. 2, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995
Apostoli, Peter, and Brown, Bryson, “A Solution to the Completeness Problem for Weakly Aggregative Modal Logic,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 60–3 (1995), 832–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aristotle, Sophistical Refutations and Prior Analytics, Rhetoric, On Interpretation, Posterior Analytics and Metaphysics, in Jonathan Barnes (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle, The Revised Oxford Translation, Vols. 1 and 2., Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1984
Arrow, Kenneth J., Social Choice and Individual Values, New York: John Wiley, 1951
Avron, Arnon, “Whither Relevance Logic?,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 21 (1992), 243–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bar-Hillel, Y. (ed.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1965
Barnes, Jonathan (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle, The revised Oxford translation Vol. 1 and 2., Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1984
Barth, E. M., The Logic of Articles in Traditional Philosophy, Dordrecht and Boston: Reidel, 1974
Barth, E. M., and Krabbe, E. C. W. (eds.), Logic and Political Culture, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1990
Barth, E. M., and Krabbe, E. C. W., From Axiom to Dialogue: A philosophical study of logic and argumentation., Berlin: de Gruyter, 1992
Bartlett, F. C., Remembering, Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1932
Bartley, W. W., III (ed.), The Retreat to Commitment, revised and enlarged, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1984
Barwise, John (ed.), Handbook of Mathematical Logic, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1977
Barwise, John, and Etchemendy, John, The Liar, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984
Barwise, John, and Moss, Lawrence, Vicious Circles, Stanford, Calif.: CSLI Publications 1996
Batens, D., “Extensional Paraconsistent Logics,” Logique et Analyse, 90–91 (1980), 195–234Google Scholar
Becherand, W., and Essler, W. K. (eds.), Konzepte der Dialektik, Frankfurt/Main: Klostermann, 1981
Bell, John S., “On the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Paradox,” Physics, 1 (1964), 195CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, J. L., “Category Theory and the Foundation of Mathematics,” British Journal of the Philosophy of Science, 32 (1981), 349–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Belnap, Nuel D., Jr., An Analysis of Questions: Preliminary Report, Santa Monica, Calif.: System Development Corporation, 1963
Belnap, Nuel D. Jr., “Gupta's Rule of Revision Theory of Truth,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 11 (1982), 103–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Belnap, Nuel D., Jr., and Steel, Thomas B., The Logic of Questions and Answers, New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1976
Benacerraf, Paul, “Mathematical Truth,” Journal of Philosophy, ⅬXX (1973), 661–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benardete, José A., Metaphysics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989
Beth, Evert W., “Towards An Up-to-date Philosophy of Natural Sciences,” Methods 1 (1949), 178–84Google Scholar
Birkhoff, G., “Lattices in Applied Mathematics,” American Mathematical Society, Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, 2 (1961), 155–84Google Scholar
Black, Max, “A Critical Review of [Quine's] Mathematical Logic,” Mind, 52 (1943), 264–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bläu, Ulrich, Die dreiwertige Logik der Sprache: Ihre Syntax, Semantik und Anwendung in der Sprachanalyse, Berlin: deGruyer, 1978
Bohm, David, Special Theory of Relativity, Amsterdam: W. A. Benjamins, 1965
Boolos, George S., “On Second Order Logic,” Journal of Philosophy, 72, 16 (1975), 509–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boolos, George, “Saving Frege From Contradiction,” in Richard Jeffrey (ed.), Logic, Logic and Logic, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998, 171–82
Boolos, George, and Jeffrey, Richard, Computability and Logic, 3rd edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989
Brady, R. T., “Depth Relevance of Some Paraconsistent Logics,” Studia Logica, 43 (1984), 63–74CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brady, R. T., “The Non-triviality of Dialectical Set Theory,” in Priest, Routley, and Norman (eds.), Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent., Münich: Philosophia Verlag, 1989, 437–71
Brady, R. T., Universal Logic, unpublished
Bradley, F. H., The Principles of Logic, two volumes, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1883; corrected impression 1922
Brown, Bryson, “Simple Natural Deduction for Weakly Aggregative Paraconsistent Logics,” in Dov Gabbay (ed.), Frontiers of Paraconsistent Logic, London: Research Studies Press, 2001
Brown, Bryson, “Approximate Truth: A Paraconsistent Account,” in Joke Meheus (ed.), Inconsistency in Science, vol. 2 in the series Origins: Studies in the Sources of Scientific Creativity, Amsterdam: Kluwer Academic, 2002
Brown, Bryson, and Schotch, Peter, “Logic and Aggregation,” The Journal of Philosophical Logic, 28 (1999), 265–87CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burali-Forti, “Una Questione Sui Numeri Transfiniti,” Rendiconti del Circolo Mathematico di Palermo, 11 (1897), translated as “A Question on Transfinite Numbers,” Jean van Heijenoort (trans.), in van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967, 104–12
Burge, Tyler, “Semantic Paradox,” Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), 169–98, reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), Recent Essays on Truth and The Liar Paradox, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984, 83–117
Burgess, John P., “Introduction to Part II,” in Richard Jeffrey (ed.), Logic, Logic and Logic, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998, 135–42
Cantor, George, “Beiträge zer Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre,” parts one and two, Mathematischen Annalen, 46 (1895), 481–512 and 49 (1897), 207–46; translated as Contributions to the Founding of the Theory of Transfinite Numbers, by P. E. B. Jourdain (trans.), Chicago: Open Court, 1915; reprinted New York: Dover, 1952, 85–201
Cantor, George, “Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre,” Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung 1 (1890–91), 75–8, reprinted in Ernst Zermelo (ed.), Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts, Berlin: Springer, 1932, 278–81
Cargile, James, Paradoxes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979
Carlsen, Laurie, Dialogue Games: An Approach to Discourse Analysis., Dordrecht: Reidel, 1983
Carlsen, Laurie, and ter Meulen, Alice, “Informational Independence in Intensional Contexts” in E. Saarinen et al. (eds.), Essays In Honor of Jaakko Hintikka, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979, 61–72
Carlson, Gregory N., and Pelletier, Francis Jeffry (eds.), The Generic Book, Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1995
Carnap, Rudolf, The Logical Syntax of Language, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1937
Cartwright, N., How the Laws of Physics Lie, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983
Cartwright, Richard, “Implications and Entailments,” in Richard Cartwright, Philosophical Essays, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987, 237–58
Cartwright, Richard, Philosophical Essays, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987
Cartwright, Richard L., “Propositions,” R. J. Butler (ed.), Analytical Philosophy, 1st Series, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1962, 81–103
Cartwright, Richard L., “Propositions Again,” Nôus 2 (1968), 229–46Google Scholar
Castañeda, Hector-Neri, “Fiction and Reality: Their Fundamental Connections,” in John Woods and Thomas Pavel (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics 8 (1979), 31–62
Cézanne, Paul, in W. Hess (ed.), Über die Kunst: Gespräche mit Gasquet, Mittenwald: Mäander, 1980
Chellas, Brian F., Modal Logic: An Introduction., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980CrossRef
Cherniak, Christopher, Minimal Rationality, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1986
Church, Alonzo, “The Weak Theory of Implication,” in Albert Menne, Alexander Wilhelmy, and Helmut Angstil (eds.), Untersuchungen zum Logikkalkül und zur Logik der Einzelwissenschaften, Freiburg: Kontrolliertes Denken, 1951, 22–37
Churchland, Paul M., “Eliminative Materialism,” Journal of Philosophy, 78 (1981), 67–90Google Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan, “On the Psychology of Prediction: Whose Is the Fallacy?,” Cognition 7 (1979), 385–407CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan, “Can Human Irrationality Be Experimentally Demonstrated?,” The Behavior and Brain Sciences 4 (1981), 317–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan, The Dialogue of Reason: An Analysis of Analytical Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon, 1986
Cohen, L. Jonathan, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Induction and Probability, Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1989
Cohen, L. Jonathan, “Reply to Stein,” Synthese 99 (1994), 173–6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, A., and Quillam, M., “Retrieval Time From Semantic Memory,” Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 8 (1969), 240–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, WilliamOn Axiomatizability Within a System,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 (1953), 1, 30–2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craig, William, “Three Uses of the Herbrand-Gentzen Theorem,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (1957), 269–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Currie, Gregory, The Nature of Fiction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990
Curry, Haskell B., “The Paradox of Kleene and Rosser,” Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 50 (1941), 454–516CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Curry, Haskell B., “The Inconsistency of Certain Formal Logics,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 7 (1942), 115–117CrossRefGoogle Scholar
da Costa, Newton C. A., “On the Theory of Inconsistent Formal Systems,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, XV (1974), 497–510CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dalla Chiara, M. L., “The Relevance of Quantum Logic,” Proceedings of the International Congress for Logic, Methodology and the Philosophy of Science, Salzburg: North-Holland, forthcoming
Davidson, Donald, “Theories of Meaning and Learnable Languages,” in Y. Bar-Hillel (ed.), Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, Amsterdam: North Holland, 1965, 383–94
Davidson, Donald, “Truth and Meaning,” Synthese, 17 (1967), 304–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald, “Psychology as Philosophy,” in J. Glover (ed.), The Philosophy of Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976, 101–10
DeVidi, David, and Solomon, Graham, “On Confusions About Bivalence and Excluded Middle,” Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, ⅹⅹⅹⅷ (1999), 785–99
Diaz, M. Richard, Topics in the Logic of Relevance, Munich: Philosophia Verlag, 1981
Doležel, Lubomír, “Extensional and Intentional Narrative Worlds,” John Woods and Thomas Pavel (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics, 8 (1979), 193–211
duBois-Reymond, Paul, “Eine neue Theorie der Convergenz und Divergenz von Reihen mit poitiven Gliedern,” Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik 76 (1873), 61–91CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dummet, Michael, Frege: Philosophy of Language, London: Duckworth, 1973
Dunn, J. Michael, “Relevant Logic and Entailment,” in D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol. 3: Alternatives to Classical Logic, Synthese Library, Vol. 166, Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 986, 117–224
Dunn, J. Michael, “Intuitive Semantics for First Degree Entailments and ‘Coupled Trees,’” Philosophical Studies, 29 (1976), 149–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eagleton, Terry, The Illusions of Postmodernism, Oxford: Blackwell, 1996
Einstein, AlbertIst die Traegheit eines Koerpers von seinem Energieinhalt abhaengig?,” Annalen der Physik 18 (1905), 639–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elgin, Catherine Z., Considered Judgement, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1996
Elster, Jon, Sour Grapes: Studies in the Subversion of Rationality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, “Self Reliance,” in Essays, London: Aldine Press, 1967
Feferman, Solomon, “Toward Useful Type-Free Theories, I,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 49 (1984), 75–111, reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), Truth and the Liar Paradox, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 237–87
Festinger, Leon, A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1957
Feyerabend, Paul, Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge, London: Verso, 1978
Fine, Kit, “Incompleteness for Quantified Relevance Logics,” in Jean Norman and Richard Sylvan (eds.), Directions in Relevant Logic, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 1989, 205–25
Flew, Anthony (ed.), Essays in Conceptual Analysis, London: Macmillan, 1960
Forrest, Peter, Quantum Metaphysics, Oxford: Blackwell, 1988
Frege, Gottlob, 1893–1903 partial translation as The Basic Laws of Arithmetic: Exposition of the System (Montgomery Furth, ed. and trans.), Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1964
Frege, Gottlob, Grundgeseze der Arithmetik, Jena: Pohle, 1903; partial translation as The Basic Laws of Arithmetic: Exposition of the System, Montgomery Furth (trans. and ed.), Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1964
Frege, Gottlob, Letter to Russell, in van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967, 127–8
Frege, Gottlob, Foundations of Arithmetic, J. L. Austin (trans.), Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1950
French, Simon, Decision Theory: An Introduction to the Mathematics of Rationality, Chichester, U.K.: Ellis Horwood, 1986
Friedman, Harvey, and Meyer Robert K., “Can We Implement Relevant Arithmetic?,” Technical Report TF-ARP-12/88, Automated Reasoning Project, Research School of Social Science, Australian National University, 1988
Frye, Northrop, The Great Code, Toronto: Academic Press, 1981
Fuhrmann, A., Relevant Logics, Modal Logics and Theory Change, Ph.D. Thesis, Australian National University, 1988
Gabbay, Dov M., “Dynamics of Practical Reasoning: A Position Paper,” in Advances in Modal Logic 2, K. Segerberg, M. Zkharayashev, M. de Rijke, and H. Wansing, (eds.), CSLI Publications, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, 179–224
Gabbay, Dov M., and Guenthner, F. (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Vol. 3, Dordrecht and Boston: Reidel, 1984
Gabbay, Dov M., and Hunter, Anthony, “Making Inconsistency Respectable, Part I,” in P. Jorrand and J. Kelemen (eds.), Fundamentals of Artificial Intelligence Research (FAIR '91), LNAI, Vol. 535, Springer-Verlag, 1991
Gabbay, Dov M., and Hunter, Anthony, “Making Inconsistency Respectable, Part II,” in M. Clarke, R. Kruse, and S. Seraffin (eds.), Symbolic and Quantitative Approaches to Reasoning and Uncertainty: European Conference ECSQARU '93, Granada, Spain, LNCS, Vol. 747, Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 1993
Gabbay, Dov M., and Woods, John, “Non-cooperation in Dialogue Logic: Getting Beyond the Goody Two-Shoes Model of Argument,” Synthese, forthcoming
Gabbay, Dov M., and Woods, John, “More on Non-cooperation in Dialogue Logic,” Logic Journal of the IGPL, 9 (2001), 321–39CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gabriel, GottfriedFiction: A Semantic Approach,” Poetics: Journal of Empirical Research on Literature, the Media and the Arts, 8.2 (1979), 245–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gaifman, Haim, “Operational Pointer Semantics: Solution to Self-referential Puzzlers I,” M. Vardi (ed.), Proceedings of the Second Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning About Knowledge, Los Altos, Calif.: Morgan Kaufman, 1988, 43–60
Gäredenfors, Peter, Knowledge in Flux: Modeling the Dynamics of Epistemic States, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987
Garey, Michael R., and Johnson, David S., Computers and Intractability, San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1979
Peter, Geach, “Entailment,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Vol. 32 (1958), 143–72; reprinted in Peter Geach, Logic Matters, Oxford: Blackwell, 1972, 174–86Google Scholar
Gellner, Ernest, Words and Things, Harmondsworth, U.K.: Penguin, 1968
Gibbins, PeterA User-Friendly Quantum Logic,” Logique et Analyse, 112 (1985), 353–62Google Scholar
Gilles, Donald, Philosophy of Science in the Twentieth Century: Four Central Themes, Oxford: Blackwell, 1993
Gilbert, Margaret, On Social Facts, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1993
Gilmore, P. C., “The Consistency of Partial Set Theory Without Extensionality,” in Dana Scott (ed.), Symposium in Pure Mathematics, University of California, Los Angeles, 1967; Axiomatic Set Theory, Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, XIII Pt. 2, American Mathematical Society, 1974
Girle, Roderic A., “Dialogue and Entrenchment,” Proceedings of the Sixth Florida Artificial Intelligence Research Symposium, Fort Lauderdale, 1993, 105–89
Girle, Roderic A., “Knowledge: Organized and Disorganized,” Proceedings of the Seventh Florida Artificial Intellegence Research Symposium, Pensacola Beach, Fla., 1994, 198–203Google Scholar
Girle, Roderic A., “Commands in Dialogue Logic,” Proceedings of the International Conference on Formal and Applied Practical Reasoning, Bonn, 1996, 246–60
Girle, Roderic A., “Belief Sets and Commitment Stores,” in Hans V. Hansen, Christopher W. Tindale, and Athena V. Colman (eds.), Argumentation and Rhetoric, St. Catharines, Ont.: OSSA, 1998
Glover, J. (ed.), The Philosophy of Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976
Gochet, Paul, Ascent to Truth, Münich: Philosophia Verlag, 1986
Gödel, Kurt, “What Is Cantor's Continuum Problem?,” American Mathematical Monthly, 54 (1947), 515–25CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goghossian, DaveWhat the Sokal Hoax Ought to Teach Us,” Times Literary Supplement December 13 (1996), 14–15Google Scholar
Goodman, Nelson, Fact, Fiction and Forecast, 2nd ed., New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965
Grattan-Guiness, Ivor, “How Bertrand Russell Discovered His Paradox,” Historia Mathematica, 5 (1978), 127–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, Nicholas, Russell's Idealist Apprenticeship, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991
Gupta, Anil, “Truth and Paradox,” in Robert L. Martin (ed.) Recent Essays on Truth and the Liar Paradox, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 175–236
Gupta, Anil, and Belnap, Nuel D., Jr., The Revision of Theory of Truth, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1993
Haack, Susan, Deviant Logic, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1974
Hacking, IanWhat Is Logic?,” The Journal of Philosophy, ⅬXXVI (1979), 285–319CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, Ian, Representing and Intervening, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983
Hahn, Lewis Edwin (ed.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, second rev. ed., LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1998
Hahn, Lewis Edwin, and Schilpp, Paul Arthur (eds.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986
Hallett, Michael, Cantorian Set Theory and Limitation of Size, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984
Hamblin, C. L., Fallacies, London: Methuen, 1970
Hansen, Hans V., and Pinto, Robert C. (eds.), Fallacies: Classical and Contemporary Readings, University Park: Pennsylvania State University, 1995
Harman, GilbertIs Modal Logic Logic?,” Philosophia 2 (1972), 75–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, Gilbert, The Nature of Morality, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977
Harman, Gilbert, Change in View, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1986
Harrah, David, Communication: A Logical Model, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1963
Hart, W. D., “Access and Inference,” in W. D. Hart (ed.), Philosophy of Mathematics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996, 52–62
Hausman, Daniel M., “Introduction” in Daniel M. Hausman (ed.), The Philosophy of Economics: An Anthology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984, 1–50
Heintz, John, “Reference and Inference in Fiction,” John Woods and Thomas Pavel (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics 8 (1979), 85–99
Henkin, LeonSome Remarks on Infinitely Long Formulas,” in Infinite Models, New York: Pergamon, 1961, 167–83Google Scholar
Henson, C. Ward, “Reviews of Jensen, R. B. reply to Quine and Quine to Jenson,” The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 40 (1975), 241–2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hermes, Hans, Kambartel, Friedrich, and Kaulbach, Friedrich (eds.), Frege: Posthumous Writings, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979
Herzberger, Hans G., “Paradoxes of Grounding in Semantics,” Journal of Philosophy 67 (1970), 145–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Herzberger, Hans G., “Notes on Naive Semantics,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 11 (1982), 62–102, reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), Recent Essays on Truth and The Liar Paradox, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 134–74
Hilbert, David, Grundlagen der Geometrie, Leipzig: Teubner; translated as The Foundations of Geometry, E. J. Townsend (trans.), Chicago: Open Court, 1902; 10th edition, with a supplement by Paul Bernays translated under the previous English title, La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1971
Hinman, P., Kim, J., and Stich, S., “Logical Truth Revisited,” The Journal of Philosophy, ⅬXV (1968), 495–500CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, Knowledge and Belief, Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1962
Hintikka, JaakkoA Counter-example to Tarski-type Truth definitions as Applied to Natural Languages,” Philosophia, 5 (1975), 207–12CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, The Semantics of Questions and the Questions of Semantics [= Acta Philosophica Fernica 28 (1976)]
Hintikka, JaakkoThe Role of Logic in Argumentation,” The Monist, 72 (1989), 3–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hintikka, Jaakko, “Information-Seeking Dialogues,” in W. Becherand and W. K. Essler (eds.), Konzepte der Dialektik, Frankfurt/Main: Klostermann, 1981, 212–31
Hintikka, Jaakko, The Principles of Mathematics Revisited, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996
Holland, J. H., Holyoak, K. J., Nisbett, R. E., and Thagard, P. R., Induction: Processes of Inference, Learning and Discovery, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987
Hooker, C. A. (ed.), The Logico-Algebraic Approach to Quantum Mechanics, Vol. 1: Historical Evolution, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979
Hookway, Christopher, Quine, Oxford: Polity Press, 1988
Howe, M., Introduction to Human Memory, New York: Harper & Row, 1970
Howell, Robert, “Fictional Objects: How They Are and How They Aren't,” in John Woods and Thomas Pavel (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics 8 (1979), 50–72
Howell, Robert, “Review of [Parsons's] ‘Non-existent Objects,’” Journal of Philosophy, 80 (1983), 163–73Google Scholar
Hughes, G. E., and Cresswell, M. J., An Introduction to Modal Logic, London: Methuen, 1968
Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, Ernest C. Mossner (ed.), Harmondsworth, U.K.: Penguin Books, 1969
Hylton, Peter, Russell, Idealism and the Emergence of Analytic Philosophy, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990
Iseminger, GaryRelatedness Logic and Entailment,” The Journal of Non-Classical Logic 3 (1986), 5–23Google Scholar
Jacquette, Dale, “Logical Dimensions of Question-Begging Argument,” American Philosophical Quarterly 30 (1993), 317–27Google Scholar
Jáskowski, Leon, “Propositional Calculus for Contradictory Systems,” Studia Logica XXVI (1969), 143–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jech, Thomas J., “About the Axiom of Choice,” in Jon Barwise (ed.), Handbook of Mathematical Logic, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1977, 345–70
Johnson-Liard, P. H., and Byrne, R. M. J., Deduction, Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1991
Johnson-Laird, P. N., and Wason, P. C. (eds.), Thinking: Readings in Cognitive Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977
Johnstone, Henry W., Jr., Validity and Rhetoric in Philosophical Argument, University Park, Penn.: The Dialogue Press of Man and World, 1978
Johnston, Davidand Jennings, R. E., “Paradox Tolerant LogicsLogique et Analyse 26 (1983), 291–308Google Scholar
Kalish, Donald, Montague, Richard, and Mar, Gary, Logic: Techniques of Formal Reasoning, 2nd ed., San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1980
Kanigel, Robert, The Man Who Knew Infinity: A Life of the Genius Ramanujan, New York: Scribner, 1991
Kant, Imanuel, Inquiry Concerning the Distinctness of Principles of Natural Theology and Morality, and Logic, Indianapolis, Ind.: Bobbs-Merrill, 1764/1800/1974
Kant, Imanuel, Hartman, Robert S., and Schwartz, Wolfgang (trans. with introduction) Logic, Indianapolis, Ind.: Bobbs-Merrill, 1974
Kaplan, David, “Bob and Carl and Ted and Alice,” in Jaakko Hintikka et al. (eds.), Approaches to Natural Languages, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1973, 490–518
Kaplan, David, and Montague, Richard, “A Paradox Regained,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 1 (1960), 79–90; reprinted in Richard Montague, Formal Philosophy, New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1974, 271–85CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaufmann, W., “Uber die Konstitution des Elektrons,” Annalen der Physik, 19 (1906), 487
Keynes, John Maynard, “Letter to R. F. Harrod, 4 July 1938,” in Moggridge (ed.), Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes, Vol. 14, The General Theory and After: Part II: Defense and Development, London: Macmillan, 1973
A., Klatzley, Human Memory: Structures and Processes, San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1975
Kline, Morris, Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty, New York: Oxford University Press, 1980
Koryé, A., “The Liar,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 6 (1946), 344–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul, “Outline of a Theory of Truth,” Journal of Philosophy, 72 (1975), 690–716 reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), The Paradox of the Liar, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 134–74
Kripke, Saul A., Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980
Lakatos, Imre, Mathematics, Science and Epistemology, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1980
Lambert, Karel, “Logic and Microphysics,” in Karel Lambert (ed.), The Logical Way of Doing Things, New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1969, 93–117
Lester, R., “Shortcomings of Marginal Analysis for Wage-Employment Problems,” American Economic Review, 36 (1946), 63–82Google Scholar
Lester, R., “Marginalism, Minimum Wages. and Labour Markets,” American Economic Review, 37 (1947), 135–48Google Scholar
Lewis, C. I., “Implication and the Algebra of Logic,” Mind 21 (1912), 522–531. Collected Papers, pp. 351–359CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, C. I., and Langford, C. H., Symbolic Logic, New York: Dover, 1932
Lewis, David, “Truth in Fiction,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 15 (1978), 37–46, reprinted with postscripts in David Lewis (ed.), Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983, 261–75Google Scholar
Lewis, David K., Convention, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969
Lieber, J., and Stoller, M., “Is that all there is?,” recorded on Capital Records by Peggy Lee in 1969Google Scholar
Lindsay, P., and Norman, D., Human Information Processing, New York: Academic Press, 1977
Lindstrom, PerOn Extensions of Elementary Logic,” Theoria, XXXV (1969), 1–11Google Scholar
Löb, M. H., “Solution of a Problem of Leon Henken,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 20 (1955), 115–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John, Essay On Human Understanding, Peter H. Niddith (ed. with introduction), Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975
Lorentz, Hendrik Antoon, The Theory of Electrons and Its Application to the Phenomena of Light and Radiant Heat, 3rd ed., New York: Dover, 1952
Mackenzie, J. D., “Question-Begging in Non-Cumulative Systems,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8 (1979), 117–33CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackenzie, J. D., “Begging the Question in Dialogue,” Australian Journal of Philosophy, 62 (1984), 174–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Donald, “Review of Jean van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel,” Journal of Philosophy, 67 (1970), 113
Martin, Robert L. (ed.), Recent Essays On Truth and the Liar Paradox, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984
Martin, Robert, and Woodruff, Peter, “On Representing ‘True-in-L’ in L,” Philosophia 5 (1975), 213–17, reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), The Paradox of the Liar, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 47–51
McGee, Vann, Truth, Vagueness and Paradox, Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1990
McKinsey, J. C. C., Sugar, A. C., and Suppes, Patrick, “Axiomatic Foundations of Classical Particle Mechanics,” Journal of Rational Mechanics and Analysis, 2 (1953), 253–72Google Scholar
Menne, Albert, Wilhelmy, Alexander, and Angstil, Helmut (eds.), Untersuchungen zum Logikkalkül und zur Logik der Einzelwissenschaften, Freiburg: Kontrolliertes Denken, 1951
Mermin, N. B., “Quantum Mysteries for Everyone,” Journal of Philosophy, 78 (1981), 397–408CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyer, R. K., “Entailment,” The Journal of Philosophy, 68 (1971), 808–18CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyer, Robert, and Routley, Richard, “Dialectical Logic and Consistency of the World,” Studies in Soviet Thought, 16 (1975), 1–25Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart, “On the Definition of Political Economy and the Method of Investigation Proper to It,” in John Robson (ed.), Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Vol. IV, Essays on Economics and Society 1824–1845, Toronto: Toronto University Press, 1967, 309–39
Mill, John Stuart, A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive, in John Robson (ed.) Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Vol. VIII Book II of Reasoning and Book III of Induction, Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1974, 157–640
Millikan, Ruth Garrett, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories: New Foundations for Realism, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1984
Minsky, Marvin, The Society of the Mind, New York: Simon and Schuster, 1987
Moore, G. E., “The Nature of Judgement,” Mind 7 (1898), 176–93Google Scholar
Moore, G. E., “Critical Notice on Russell's An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry,” Mind 8 (1899), 397–405Google Scholar
Moore, G. E., Principia Ethica, Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1903
Moore, G. E., “The Refutation of Idealism,” Mind 12 (1903), 433–53; reprinted in G. E. Moore, Philosophical Studies, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1922, 1–30
Moore, G. E., Philosophical Studies, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1922
Moore, G. E., Philosophical Papers, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1959
Moore, G. E., “Russell's Theory of Descriptions,” in G. E. Moore, Philosophical Papers, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1959, 151–95
Mortensen, Chris, Inconsistent Mathematics, Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer, 1995
Mortensen, Chris, “Paraconsistency and C1,” in Graham Priest, Richard Routely, and Jean Norman (eds.), Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, Münich: Philosophia Verlag, 1989, 289–305
Myrdal, Gunnar, Objectivity in Social Research, London: Duckworth, 1970
Nagel, Ernest, Suppes, Patrick, and Tarski, Alfred (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1962
Nekham, Alexander, De Naturis Rerum, T. Wright (ed.), London: Longman, 1863
Newell, Allen, and Simon, Herbert A., Human Problem Solving, Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1972
Nisbett, R., and Ross, L., Human Inference: Strategies and Shortcomings of Social Judgement, Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1980
Norman, Jean, and Sylvan, Richard, Directions in Relevant Logic, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 1989
Nozick, Robert, “Experience, Theory and Language,” in Lewis Edwin Hahn and Paul Arthur Schilpp (eds.), The Philosophy of Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986, 339–63
Parsons, Charles, “The Liar Paradox,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 3 (1974), 381–412, reprinted in Robert L. Martin (ed.), Truth and The Liar Paradox, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, 9–45
Parsons, Terence, Non-existent Objects, New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1980
Parsons, TerenceTrue Contradictions,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 20 (1990), 335–82CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pavel, Thomas, Fictional Worlds, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986
Peacocke, ChristopherWhat Is a Logical Constant?”, The Journal of Philosophy, ⅬXXIII (1976), 221–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin, The Nature of Necessity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1974
Plantinga, Alvin, Warrant and Proper Function, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993
Plato, Meno, in E. Hamilton and H. Cairns (eds.), Plato: The Collected Dialogues., Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1980, 353–84
Post, John F., “A Gödelian Theorem for Theories of Rationality,” in G. Radnitzky and W. W. Bartley, III (eds.), Evolutionary Epistemology, Rationality, and the Sociology of Knowledge, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1987
Priest, Graham, “The Logic of Paradox,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8 (1979), 219–41CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Priest, Graham, In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 1987
Priest, Graham, Beyond the Limits of Thought, Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 1995
Priest, Graham, and Routley, Richard, “Applications of Paraconsistent Logic,” in Graham Priest, Richard Routley, and Jean Norman (eds.) Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, München: Philosophia Verlag, 1989, 367–93
Priest, Graham, and Routley, Richard, “Systems of Paraconsistent Logic” in Graham Priest, Richard Routley, and Jean Norman (eds.), Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, Münich: Philosophia Verlag, 1989, 151–86
Priest, Graham, Routley, Richard, and Norman, Jean, Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, Münich: Philosophia Verlag, 1989
Putnam, Hilary, “The Logic of Quantum Mechanics,” in Mathematics, Matter and Method: Philosophical Papers, Vol. I, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975, 174–97Google Scholar
Quine, W. V., “Truth by Convention,” in O. H. Lee (ed.), Philosophical Essays for A. N. Whitehead, New York: Longmans, 1936, 90–124
Quine, W. V., “Notes on Existence and Necessity,” Journal of Philosophy, 40 (1943), 113–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V., “The Problem of Interpreting Modal Logic,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 12 (1947), 43–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V., “Review of Geach, Subject and Predicate,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 16 (1951), 138Google Scholar
Quine, W. V., Mathematical Logic, rev. ed., Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1951
Quine, W. V., From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1953
Quine, W. V., “New Foundations for Mathematical Logic,” reprinted with additions in From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1953, 80–101Google Scholar
Quine, W. V., Word and Object, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1960
Quine, W. V., The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, rev. and enlarged ed., Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1976
Quine, W. V., Selected Logic Papers, New York: Random House, 1966; enlarged edition, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995
Quine, W. V., Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, New York: Columbia University Press, 1969
Quine, W. V., Set Theory and Its Logic, rev. ed., Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1969
Quine, W. V., Philosophy of Logic, Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1970; second ed., Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1986
Quine, W. V., Roots of Reference: The Paul Carus Lectures, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court 1973
Quine, W. V., “Reply to Manley Thompson,” in Lewis Edwin Hahn and Paul Arthur Schilpp (eds.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court 1986, 564–8
Quine, W. V., “Empirically Equivalent Systems of the World,” Erkenntnis 9 (1975), 313–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V., “Reply to Robert Nozick,” in Lewis Edwin Hahn and Paul Aurthur Schilpp (eds.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986, 364–8
Quine, W. V., Theories and Things, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1981
Quine, W. V., “Things and Their Place in Theories,” Theories and Things, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1981, 1–23Google Scholar
Quine, W. V., “Ontology and Ideology Revisited,” Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983), 499–501CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V., Quiddities, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1987
Quine, W. V., The Pursuit of Truth, revised edition, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990/1992
Quine, W. V., “Structure and Nature,” The Journal of Philosophy, ⅬXXIX (1992), 5–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V., From Stimulus to Science, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995
Quine, W. V., and Ullian, J. W., The Web of Belief, New York: Random House, 1970
Raiffa, Howard, Decision Analysis, Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1968
Ramsey, Frank P., The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1931
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971
Rawls, JohnThe Independence of Moral Theory,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 48 (1974–5), 5–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Read, Stephen, Relevant Logic: A Philosophical Examination of Inference, Oxford: Blackwell, 1988
Rescher, N. (ed.), Studies in the Philosophy of Mind, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1972
Rescher, Nicholas, and Brandon, Robert, The Logic of Inconsistency: A Study in Non-standard Possible-world Semantics and Ontology, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980
Richard, Jules, “The Principles of Mathematics and the Problem of Sets,” in Jean van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press 1967, 143–4
Rips, Lance J., The Psychology of Proof: Deductive Reasoning in Human Thinking, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1994
Ross, W. D., Aristotle, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1953
Rosser, BarkleyThe Burali-Forti Paradox,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 7 (1942), 1–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Routley, Richard, “Some Things Do Not Exist,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, VII (1966), 251–76
Routley, Richard, “The Semantic Structure of Fictional Discourse,” in John Woods and Thomas Pavel (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics, 8 (1979), 3–30
Routley, Richard, and Routley, Val, “The Semantics of First Degree Entailment,” NoÛs, 6 (1972), 335–59CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, Bertrand, “On The Axioms of Geometry,” in Nicholas Griffin and Albert C. Lewis (eds.), The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell Volume II, Philosophical Papers 1896–99, London: G. Allen and Unwin, 1983, 390–415
Russell, Bertrand, A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1900; republished London: George Allen and Unwin, 1937
Russell, Bertrand, The Principles of Mathematics, 2nd ed., London: Allen and Unwin, 1937
Russell, BertrandOn Denoting,” Mind N.S. XIV (1905), 479–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, Bertrand, An Essay on the Foundations of Geometry, New York: Dover, 1956
Russell, Bertrand, My Philosophical Development, London: Allen and Unwin, 1959
Russell, Bertrand, Our Knowledge of the External World: As a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy, London: Allen and Unwin, 1961
Russell, Bertrand, “Mathematical Logic as Based on the Theory of Types,” in Jean van Heijenoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967, 152–82
Ryle, Gilbert, “Are There Propositions?,” in Collected Papers 2: Collected Essays 1929–1968, London: Hutchinson and Co., 1971, 12–38. Reprinted from the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. ⅹⅹⅹ, 1930
Ryle, Gilbert, Philosophical Arguments, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1945
Ryle, GilbertOrdinary Language,” The Philosophical Review ⅬⅫ (1953), 167–86CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert, “Proofs in Philosophy,” in Gilbert Ryle (ed.) Collected Papers 2: Collected Essays 1929–1968, London: Hutchinson, 1972, 319–25
Ryle, GilbertUse, Usage and Meaning,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary vol. XXXV (1961), 223–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sainsbury, R. M., Paradoxes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988
Savage, Leonard J., The Foundations of Statistics, New York: John Wiley, 1954
Schotch, P. K., “Paraconsistent Logic: The View from the Right,” Philosophy of ScienceAssociation 2 (1993), 421–9Google Scholar
Schotch, P. K., and Jennings, R. E., “On Detonating,” in Graham Priest, Richard Routley, and Jean Norman (eds.), Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent, Munich: Philosophia, 1989, 306–27
Sen, Amartya, “Social Choice Theory,” in Kenneth J. Arrow and M. D. Intriligator (eds.), Handbook of Mathematical Economics, Vol. III, Los Altos, Calif.: Morgan Kaufmann, 1986, 1070–181
Sen, Amartya, On Ethics and Economics, Oxford: Blackwell, 1987
Sher, Gila, The Bounds of Logic, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1991
Shoenfield, Joseph R., Mathematical Logic, Reading, Mass.: Allison-Wesley, 1967
Simmons, Keith, Universality of the Liar, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993
Skolem, Th., “Untersuchungen über die Axiome des Klassenlalkuss,” in Th. Skolem (ed.), Selected Works in Logic, Oslo: Universitetsforlaget 1970, 67–101
Slater, B. H., “Paraconsistent Logics?,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 24 (1995), 451–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smiley, Timothy J., “Entailment and Deducibility,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Vol. 32 (1958), 123–42Google Scholar
Soames, Scott, Understanding Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999
Sorenson, Roy A., Blindspots, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988
Sperber, Dan, and Wilson, Deirdre, Relevance, Oxford: Blackwell, 1986
Starmans, Richard, Logic, Argumentation and Common Sense, Tilburg: Tilburg University Print, 1996
Stein, EdwardRationality and Reflective Equilibrium,” Synthese, 99 (1994), 137–72Google Scholar
Stich, Stephen, The Fragmentation of Reason, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1990
Stich, Stephen, and Nisbett, Richard, “Justification and Psychology of Human Reasoning,” Philosophy of Science, 47 (1980), 188–202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suppes, Patrick, Introduction to Logic, New York: Van Nostrand Reinhold, 1957
Suppes, Patrick, “Models of Data,” in Ernest Nagel, Patrick Suppes, and Alfred Tarski (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1962, 252–61
Suppes, Patrick, “A Comparison of the Meaning and Uses of Models in Mathematics and the Empirical Sciences,” Synthese 12 (1960), 287–301CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suppes, Patrick, “The Philosophical Relevance of Decision Theory,” The Journal of Philosophy, 58 (1960), 606–14Google Scholar
Suppes, Patrick, “Logics Appropriate to Empirical Theories,” in C. A. Hooker (ed.), The Logico-Algebraic Approach to Quantum Mechanics Vol I: Historical Evaluation, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979, 329–40
Suppes, Patrick, Studies in the Methodology and Foundations of Science, New York: Humanities Press, 1969
Tarski, Alfred, “On the Concept of Logical Consequence,” in Alfred Tarski, Logic, Semantics, Metamathemathics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, J. H. Woodger (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press: 2nd ed., John Corcoran (ed.), Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1983, 409–20
Tarski, Alfred, Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, J. H. Woodger (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press: 2nd ed., John Corcoran (ed.), Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1983
Tarski, Alfred, “The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages,” in Alfred Tarski, Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, J. H. Woodger (trans.), Oxford: Oxford University Press: 2nd ed., John Corcoran (ed.), Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett, 1983, 152–278
Tennant, Neil, “Natural Deduction and Gentzen Sequent Systems for Intuitionistic Relevant Logic,” Journal of Symbolic Logic, 52 (1987), 665–80CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tennant, Neil, Autologic, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1993
ter Meulen, Alice G. B. (ed.), Studies in Model Theoretic Semantics, Dordrecht: Foris, 1983
Turkle, Sherry, “Artificial Intelligence and Psychoanalysis,” in Graubard (ed.), The Artificial Intelligence Debate: False Starts, Real Foundations, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988, 260–1
Ullian, Joseph S., “Quine and the Field of Mathematical Logic,” Lewis E. Hahn and Paul A. Schilpp (eds.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986, 569–89
Urmson, J. O., Philosophical Analysis: Its Development Between the Two World Wars, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1956
Urquhart, Alasdair, “The Undecidability of Entailment and Relevant Implication,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (1984), 1059–73CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Benthem, Johan, “Five Easy Pieces,” in Johan van Benthem and Alice G. B. ter Meulen (eds.), Studies in Model Theoretic Semantics, Dordrecht: Foris, 1983, 1–17
Benthem, Johany, “What Is Dialectical Logic?,” Erkenntnis 14 (1979), 333–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Benthem, Johan, and ter Meulen, Alice G. B. (eds.), Generalized Quantifiers in Natural Language, Dordrecht: Foris, 1985
van Eemeren Frans H., et al., Fundamentals of Argumentation Theory: A Handbook of Historical Backgrounds and Contemporary Developments, Mahwah, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1996
van Eemeren, Frans H., and Grootendorst, Rob, Speech Acts in Argumentation Discussions, Dordrecht: Foris, 1984
Fraassen, Bas C., “Meaning Relations Among Predicates,” NoÛs 1 (1967), 161–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas C., Formal Semantics and Logic, New York: Macmillan, 1971
van Fraassen, Bas C., “The Labyrinth of Quantum Logics,” in C. A. Hooker (ed.), The Logico-Algebraic Approach to Quantum Mechanics Vol. I: Historical Evolution, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1975, 577–607
van Fraassen, Bas C., The Scientific Image, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980
van Heijenoort, Jean (ed.), From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book of Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967
Inwagen, Peter, “Creatures of Fiction,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 14 (1997), 299–308Google Scholar
Veyne, Paul, Le Pain et le Cirque, Paris: Seuil, 1976
von Mises, Ludwig, Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1949
von Mises, Ludwig, Epistemological Problems of Economics, G. Riseman (trans.), New York: New York University Press, 1981
von Neumann, John, Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1953
Wright, G. H., “The Concept of Entailment,” Logical Studies, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1957, 166–91Google Scholar
Walton, D. N., Logical Dialogue – Games and Fallacies, London: University Press of America, 1984
Walton, D. N., “Burden of Proof,” Argumentation, 2 (1988), 233–54CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walton, D. N., and Krabbe, E. C. W., Commitment in Dialogue, Albany: State University of New York, 1995
Walton, Douglas, A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy, Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press, 1995
Walton, Kendall, Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990
Wang, Hao, “Quine's Logical Ideas in Historical Perspective,” in Lewis E. Hahn and Paul A. Schilpp (eds.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1986, 623–43
Whately, Richard, Elements of Logic, 1st edition, Book 3, Section 13, New York: Harper and Row, 1826/1853
Wilson, N. L., “Substances Without Substrata,” Review of Metaphysics, 12 (1959), 521–39Google Scholar
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, London: Routledge and Keagan Paul, 1958
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, Oxford: Blackwell, 1964
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, in C. Diamond (ed.), Wittgenstein's Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge, 1939, Hassocks, U.K.: Harvester Press 1976
Woods, John, “The Contradiction-Exterminator,” Analysis, XXV (1965), 49–53CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, JohnFictionality and the Logic of Relations,” The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 7 (1969), 51–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, John, “Essentialism, Self-Identity, and Quantifying In,” in Milton K. Muntitz (ed.), Identity and Individuation, New York: New York University Press, 1971, 165–98
Woods, John, The Logic of Fiction: A Philosophical Sounding of Deviant Logic, The Hague and Paris: Mouton, 1974
Woods, JohnIdentity and Modality,” Philosophia V (1975), 69–120CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, John, “Critical Notice of Deviant Logic,” Canadian Journal of Philsophy VII (1977), 651–66CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, John, Engineered Death: Abortion, Suicide, Euthanasia, Senecide, Ottawa, Ont.: University of Ottawa Press, 1978
Woods, John, “Ideals of Rationality in Dialogic,” Argumentation, 2 (1988), 419–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woods, John, “The Relevance of Relevant Logic,” in J. Norman and R. Sylvan (eds.), Directions in Relevant Logics, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher, 1989, 77–86
Woods, John, “And So Indeed Are Perfect Cheat,” Argumentation, 9 (1995), 654–68
Woods, John, “Semantic Intuitions” in Johan van Bentham, Frans H. van Eemeren, Rob Grootendorst, and Frank Veltman (eds.), Logic and Argumentation, Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1996, 179–208
Woods, John, “A Captious Nicety of Argument: The Philosophy of W. V. Quine,” in Lewis E. Hahn (ed.), The Philosophy of W. V. Quine, Library of Living Philosophers, 2nd rev. ed., LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court Press, 1998, 687–725
Woods, John, Aristotle's Earlier Logic, Oxford: Hermes Science Publications, 2001
Woods, John, and Pavel, Thomas (eds.), Formal Semantics and Literary Theory, a special issue of Poetics 8 (1979)
Woods, John, and Peacock, Kent, “What Physics Does to Logic: The Current State of Quantum Logic Is Incompatible With,” forthcoming
Woods, John, and Walton, Douglas, “Arresting Circles in Formal Dialogues,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 7 (1978), 73–90; reprinted in John Woods and Douglas Walton, Fallacies: Selected Papers 1972–1982, Berlin: Foris/deGruyter, 1988, 143–159
Woods, John, and Walton, Douglas, “Question-Begging and Cumulativeness in Dialectical Games,” Nôus 16 (1982), 585–606; reprinted in John Woods and Douglas Walton, Fallacies: Selected Papers 1972–1982, Berlin: Foris/deGruyter 1988, 253–72
Woods, John, and Walton, Douglas, Argument: The Logic of Fallacies., Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson, 1982
Woods, John, and Walton, Douglas, Fallacies: Selected Papers 1972–1982, Berlin: Foris/de Gruyter, 1988
Wright, Crispin, Frege's Conception of Numbers as Objects, Aberdeen: Aberdeen University Press, 1983
Zalta, Edward N., Abstract Objects: An Introduction to Axiomatic Metaphysics, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1983
Zermelo, Ernst, “Beweis, das jede Menge wohlgeoronet werden kann,” Mathematischen Annalen 59 (1904), 514–16; translated as “Proof That Every Set Can Be Well-ordered,” S. Bauer-Mengelburge (trans.), in Jean van Heijenvoort (ed.), From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1967, 139–41
Zermelo, Ernst, “Uber Grenzzahlen und Megenbereiche: neue Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre,” Fundamentae Mathematicae, 16 (1930), 29–47CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zucker, J., “The Adequacy Problem for Classical Logic,” Journal of Philosophical Logic, 7, 4 (1978), 517–35Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • John Woods, University of British Columbia, Vancouver
  • Book: Paradox and Paraconsistency
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511614002.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • John Woods, University of British Columbia, Vancouver
  • Book: Paradox and Paraconsistency
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511614002.012
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • John Woods, University of British Columbia, Vancouver
  • Book: Paradox and Paraconsistency
  • Online publication: 05 June 2012
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511614002.012
Available formats
×