Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-cx56b Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-06T20:17:59.207Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bibliography

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 September 2009

Eric Christian Barnes
Affiliation:
Southern Methodist University, Texas
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2008

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Achinstein, P. (1991), Particles and Waves: Historical Essays in the Philosophy of Science, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Achinstein, P.(2001), The Book of Evidence, Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, W. (1976), “Two Types of Foundationalism,” Journal of Philosophy 73: 165–168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bamford, G. (1993), “Popper's Explications of Ad Hocness: Circularity, Empirical Content, and Scientific Practice,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 44: 335–355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E. (1996a), “Discussion: Thoughts on Maher's Predictivism,” Philosophy of Science, 63: 401–410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(1996b), “Social Predictivism,” Erkenntnis, 45: 69–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(1998), “Probabilities and Epistemic Pluralism,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48: 31–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(1999), “The Quantitative Problem of Old Evidence,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48: 31–47.Google Scholar
Barnes, E.(2000), “Ockham's Razor and the Anti-Superfluity Principle,” Erkenntnis, 53: 353–374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(2002), “Neither Truth nor Empirical Adequacy Explain Novel Success,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 80 (4): 418–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(2002), “The Miraculous Choice Argument for Realism,” Philosophical Studies, 111 (2): 97–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(2005a), “Predictivism for Pluralists,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 56: 421–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(2005b), “On Mendeleev's Predictions: Comment on Scerri and Worrall,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 36: 801–812.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barret, J. (1996), “Oracles, Aesthetics, and Bayesian Consensus,” Philosophy of Science, Supplement to 63, S273–S280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bensaude-Vincent, B. (1986), “Mendeleev's Periodic System of Chemical Elements,” British Journal for the History of Science, 19: 3–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bensaude-Vincent, B.(2000), “From Teaching to Writing: Lecture Notes and Textbooks at the French Ecole Polytechnique,” in Lundren and Bensaude-Vincent, pp. 273–294.
Bonjour, L. [1976], “The Coherence Theory of Empirical Knowledge,” Philosophical Studies, 30: 281–312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonjour, L. [1978], “Can Empirical Knowledge Have a Foundation?,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 15: 1–13.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. (1981), “Scientific Realism and Naturalistic Epistemology,” PSA 1980 Vol. 2, East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 612–662.Google Scholar
Boyd, R.(1985), “Lex Orandi est Lex Credendi,” in Churchland, and Hooker, (eds.), pp. 612–662.Google Scholar
Boyd, R.(1991), “The Current Status of Scientific Realism,” in Boyd, R., Gasper, P., and Trout, J. D., (eds.) The Philosophy of Science, Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 195–222. Also printed in Leplin, J. (ed.) 1984, Scientific Realism, Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 41–82.Google Scholar
Brush, S. (1996), “The Reception of Mendeleev's periodic law in America and Britain,” Isis, 87: 595–628.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bynum, W. F., Browne, E. J., and Porter, R. (1981), Dictionary of the History of Science, Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, R. and Vinci, T. (1983), “Novel Confirmation,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 34: 315–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cassebaum, H. and Kauffman, G. B. (1971), “The Periodic System of the Chemical Elements: The Search for its Discoverer,” Isis, 62: 314–327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chihara, C. [1987], “Some Problems for Bayesian Confirmation Theory,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 38: 551–560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. and Hooker, C. (eds.) (1985), Images of Science: Essays on Realism and Empiricism with a Reply from Bas C. Van Fraassen, Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Christensen, D. (1999), “Measuring Confirmation,” Journal of Philosophy, 96: 437–461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, F. W. (1884), Elements of Chemistry, New York: Appleton.Google Scholar
Collins, R. (1994), “Against the Epistemic Value of Prediction Over Accommodation,” Nous, 28: 210–224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. (1992), Testimony: A Philosophical Study, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Darden, L. (1991), Theory Change in Science: Strategies from Mendelian Genetics, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Milt, C. (1951), “The Conference at Karlsruhe,” Journal of Chemical Education, 28: 421–424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douven, I. (2000), “The Anti-Realist Argument for Underdetermination,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 50: 371–375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drake, S. (1967), “Galileo Galilei,” The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 3, Edwards, P. (ed.), New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Earman, J. (ed.) (1983), Testing Scientific Theories, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Earman, J.(1992), Bayes or Bust? A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Earman, J.(1993), “Carnap, Kuhn and the Philosophy of Science Methodology,” in Horwich, P. (ed.), World Changes, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.Google Scholar
Earman, J. and Glymour, C. (1980), “Relativity and Eclipses: The British Eclipse Expeditions of 1919 and Their Predecessors,” Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 11: 49–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwards, P. (1967), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, New York: Macmillan Publishing Company and the Free Press.Google Scholar
Eells, E. (1990), “Bayesian Problems of Old Evidence,” in Savage, W. (ed.), Scientific Theories, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Eells, E. and Fitelson, B. (2000), “Measuring Confirmation and Evidence,” Journal of Philosophy, 97: 663–672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farrar, W. V. (1965), “Nineteenth Century Speculations on the Complexity of the Chemical Elements,” The British Journal for the History of Science, 2: 291–323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, A. (1986), “Unnatural Attitudes: Realist and Instrumentalist Attachments to Science,” Mind, 95: 145–179.Google Scholar
Fine, A.(1991), “Piecemeal Realism,” Philosophical Studies, 61: 79–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitelson, B. (1999), “The Plurality of Bayesian Measures of Confirmation and the Problem of Measure Sensitivity,” Philosophy of Science, Supplement to Vol. 66, No. 3, S362–S378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foley, R. (2001), Intellectual Trust in Oneself and Others, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankel, H. (1979), “The Career of Continental Drift Theory,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 10: 21–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garber, D. (1983), “Old Evidence and Logical Omniscience in Bayesian Confirmation Theory,” in Earman [1983].
Gardner, M. (1982), “Predicting Novel Facts,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 33: 1–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, R. (1983), “Testing Theoretical Hypotheses,” in Earman, J. (ed.) Testing Scientific Theories, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 10, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Giere, R.(1984), Understanding Scientific Reasoning, 2nd edn., New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.Google Scholar
Gillespie, C. C. (ed.) (1971), Dictionary of Scientific Biography, New York: Charles Scribner's Sons.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. (1980), Theory and Evidence, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Good, I. J. (1967), “The White Shoe is a Red Herring,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 17: 322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gutting, G. (1985), “Scientific Realism versus Constructive Empiricism,” in Churchland and Hooker (eds.) pp. 118–131.
Grünbaum, A. (1984), The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique, University of California Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1979), “Imre Lakatos's Philosophy of Science,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 30: 381–410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardwig, J. (1985), “Epistemic Independence,” Journal of Philosophy, 82: 335–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardwig, J.(1991), “The Role of Trust in Knowledge,” Journal of Philosophy, 88: 693–708.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harker, D. (2006), “Accommodation and Prediction: The Case of the Persistent Head,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57: 309–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobbes, J. (1993), “Ex Post Facto Explanations,” Journal of Philosophy, 93: 117–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoel, P. G. (1971), Introduction to Mathematical Statistics, New York: John Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
Holden, N. E. (1984), “Mendeleev and the Periodic Classification of the Elements,” Chemical International, 6: 18–31.Google Scholar
Howson, C. (1984), “Bayesianism and Support by Novel Facts,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 35: 245–251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C.(1985), “Some Recent Objections to the Bayesian Theory of Support,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 36: 305–309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C.(1988), “Accommodation, Prediction, and Bayesian Confirmation Theory,” PSA 1988, 2: 381–292.Google Scholar
Howson, C.(1990), “Fitting Your Theory to the Facts: Probably Not Such a Bad Thing After All,” in Savage, W. (ed.), Scientific Theories, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 14. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Howson, C.(1991), “The ‘Old Evidence’ Problem,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 42: 547–555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C.(1996), “Error Probabilities in Error,” Philosophy of Science, Supplement to Vol. 64, pp. S185–S194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. and Franklin, A. (1991), “Maher, Mendeleev and Bayesianism,” Philosophy of Science, 58: 574–585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. and Urbach, P. (1989), Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach, Open Court, La Salle.Google Scholar
Ihde, A. J. (1961), “The Karlsruhe Congress: A Centennial Retrospective,” Journal of Chemical Education, 38 (2): 83–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, R. (1965), The Logic of Decision, McGraw-Hill Book Company.Google Scholar
Kahn, J. A., Landsberg, S. E., and Stockman, A. C. (1990), “On Novel Confirmation,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43: 503–516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kantorovich, A. (1993), Scientific Discovery: Logic and Tinkering, State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Kaplan, M. (1996), Decision Theory as Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keynes, J. M. (1929), A Treatise on Probability, London: Macmillan and Co.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1989), “Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World,” in Kitcher, P. and Salmon, W. (eds.), Scientific Explanation, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P.(1993), The Advancement of Science: Science Without Legend, Objectivity Without Illusions, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Knight, D. M. (1970), Classical Scientific Papers – Chemistry, 2nd Series, New York: American Elsevier.Google Scholar
Knight, D. M.(1992), Ideas in Chemistry: A History of the Science, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1970), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd edn., Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kukla, A. (1998), Studies in Scientific Realism, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kultgen, J. H. (1958), “Philosophic Conceptions in Mendeleev's Principles of Chemistry,” Philosophy of Science, 25: 177–183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kusch, M. (2002), Knowledge by Agreement, Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, J. and Sosa, E. (eds.) (2006), The Epistemology of Testimony, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ladyman, J., Douven, I., Horsten, L., and Fraassen, B. (1997), “A Defense of Van Fraassen's Critique of Abductive Inference: Reply to Psillos,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 47: 305–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1981), Science and Hypothesis, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L.(1984), “Explaining the Success of Science: Beyond Epistemic Realism and Relativism,” in Cushing, J., Delaney, C. F., and Gutting, G. (eds.) Science and Reality, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L.(1990), “Normative Naturalism,” Philosophy of Science, 57: 44–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1970), “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes,” in Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 91–196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I.(1971), “History of Science and its Rational Reconstructions,” Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 8: 91–135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laing, M. (1995), “The Karlsruhe Conference, 1860,” Education in Chemistry, 32: 151–153.Google Scholar
Lange, M. (2001), “The Apparent Superiority of Prediction to Accommodation as a Side Effect: a Reply to Maher,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52: 575–588.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, K. (1974), “Induction, Consensus and Catastrophe,” in Bodgan, R. J. (ed.) Local Induction, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Lehrer, K.(1976), “When Rational Disagreement is Impossible,” Nous, 10: 327–332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, K.(1977), “Social Information,” Monist, 60: 473–487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, K.(1978), “Consensus and Comparison: A Theory of Social Rationality,” in Hooker, C. A., Leach, J. J., and McClennan, E. F. (eds.), Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory, Vol. 1, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Lehrer, K. and Wagner, C. (1981), Rational Consensus in Science and Society, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J. (1975), “The Concept of an Ad Hoc Hypothesis,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 5: 309–345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J.(1982), “The Assessment of Auxiliary Hypotheses,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 33: 235–249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J.(1987), “The Bearing of Discovery on Justification,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 17: 805–814.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J.(1997), A Novel Defense of Scientific Realism, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Leplin, J.(2000), “The Epistemic Status of Auxiliary Hypotheses,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 50: 376–379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1979), “Counterfactual Dependence and Time's Arrow,” Nous, 13: 455–476, reprinted in Lewis, D. (1986) Philosophical Papers, Vol. II, Oxford University Press, pp. 32–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, P. (1991), Inference to the Best Explanation, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lipton, P.(1992–3), “Is the Best Good Enough?,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 93: 89–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, P.(2004), Inference to the Best Explanation, 2nd edn., London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1995), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Amherst, NY: Prometheus Press.Google Scholar
Longino, H. (1990), Science as Social Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Lundgren, A. (2000), “Theory and Practice in Swedish Chemical Textbooks during the Nineteenth Century,” in Lundgren and Bensaude-Vincent, pp. 91–118.
Lundgren, A. and Bensaude-Vincent, B. (2000), Communicating Chemistry: Textbooks and Their Audiences 1789–1939, USA, Science History Publications.Google Scholar
MacDonald, H. (1985), Eating for the Health of It, Priddis, Alberta: Austin Books.Google Scholar
Magnus, P. D. and Callender, C. (2004), “Realist Ennui and the Base Rate Fallacy,” Philosophy of Science, 71: 320–338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maher, P. (1988), “Prediction, Accommodation, and the Logic of Discovery,” PSA 1988, 1: 273–285.Google Scholar
Maher, P.(1990), “How Prediction Enhances Confirmation,” in Dunn, J. M. and Gupta, A. (eds.), Truth or Consequences: Essays in Honor of Nuel Belnap, Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 327–343.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maher, P.(1993), “Howson and Franklin on Prediction,” Philosophy of Science, 60: 329–340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maher, P.[1996], “Subjective and Objective Confirmation,” Philosophy of Science, 63: 149–174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manahan, S. E. (1997), Environmental Science and Technology, Boca Raton, New York: Lewis Publishers.Google Scholar
Marsden, G. (1980), Fundamentalism and American Culture: The Shaping of Twentieth Century Evangelicalism, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Maxwell, G. (1962), “The Ontological Status of Theoretical Entities,” in Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G. (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol 3. Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 12–13.Google Scholar
Mayo, D. (1991), “Novel Evidence and Severe Tests,” Philosophy of Science, 58: 523–553.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D.(1996), Error and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge, University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAllister, J. W. (1996), Beauty and Revolution in Science, Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Meehl, P. (1999), “How to Weight Scientists' Probabilities is Not a Big Problem: Comment on Barnes,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50: 283–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendeleev, D. (1889), “The Periodic Law of the Chemical Elements: Faraday Lecture,” printed in Knight (1970), pp. 322–344.
Merton, R. (1973), “The Normative Structure of Science,” printed in Merton, R. The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations, ed. Storer, N. W., Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1961), System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive, 8th edn., London.Google Scholar
Murphy, N. (1989), “Another Look at Novel Facts,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 20. (3), 385–388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, A. (1974), “Logical versus Historical Theories of Confirmation,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25: 1–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, A.(1985), “Realism versus Constructive Empiricism,” in Churchland and Hooker (eds.), pp. 197–221.
Musgrave, A.(1988), “The Ultimate Argument for Scientific Realism,” in Nola, R. (ed.), Relativism and Realism in Science, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 229–252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T. (1987), “Lakatosian Heuristics and Epistemic Support,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 38: 181–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T.(1988), “Truth or Consequences? Generative Versus Consequential Justification in Science,” PSA 1988, Vol. 2, 393–405.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1983), “Novel Facts and Bayesianism,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 34: 375–379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nunan, R. (1984), “Novel Facts, Bayesian Rationality, and the History of Continental Drift,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 15: 267–307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Partington, J. R. (1964), A History of Chemistry, Vol. 4, London: Macmillan and Co. LTD.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1897), Anonymous Review of Mendeleev's Principles of Chemistry, Nation, 25: 424.Google Scholar
Peters, D. and Ceci, S. (1982), “Peer Review Practices of Psychological Journals: The Fate of Published Articles Submitted Again,” Behavior and Brain Sciences, 5: 187–195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. (1963), Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, New York and Evanston: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975), Mathematics, Matter, and Method, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. (1996), “On Van Fraassen's Critique of Abductive Reasoning,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 46: 31–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Psillos, S.(1997), “How Not to Defend Constructive Empiricism: A Rejoinder,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 47: 369–372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Psillos, S.(1999), Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth, London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1951), “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” The Philosophical Review, 60: 20–43. Reprinted in Quine (1953), From a Logical Point of View, Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O.(1960), Word and Object, Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Redhead, M. (1986), “Novelty and Confirmation,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 37: 115–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richmond, A. (1999), “Between Abduction and the Deep Blue Sea,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 49: 86–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenkranz, R. (1983), “Why Glymour IS a Bayesian,” in Earman, 1983, pp. 69–98.
Salmon, W. (1966), The Foundation of Scientific Inference, University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W.(1981), “Rational Prediction,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 32: 115–125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sambursky, S. (1971), “Structure and Periodicity: Centenary of Mendeleev's Discovery,” Proceedings of the Israel Academy of Sciences and Humanities, 4: 1–13.Google Scholar
Scerri, E. (2005), “Response to Barnes' critique of Scerri and Worrall,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 36: 813–816.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scerri, E.(2007), The Periodic Table: Its Story and its Significance, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scerri, E. and Worrall, J. (2001), “Prediction and the Periodic Table,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 32: 407–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffner, K. (1974), “Einstein versus Lorentz: Research Programmes and the Logic of Theory Evaluation,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25: 45–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlesinger, G. (1987), “Accommodation and Prediction,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 65: 33–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapere, D. (1982), “The Concept of Observation in Science and Philosophy,” Philosophy of Science, 49: 485–525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapin, S. (1994), A Social History of Truth, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Shapin, S. and Schaffer, S. (1985), Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle and the Experimental Life, Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sobel, M. (1987), Light, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1988), Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution and Inference, Cambridge, MA, and London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. and Hitchcock, C. (2004), “Prediction Versus Accommodation and the Risk of Overfitting,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55: 1–34.Google Scholar
Solov'ev, Y. I. (1984), “D.I. Mendeleev and the English Chemists,” Journal of Chemical Education, 61: 1069–1071.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soyfer, V. (1994), Lysenko and the Tragedy of Soviet Science, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
Speelman, C. (1998), “Implicit Expertise: Do We Expect Too Much From Our Experts?,” in Kirsner, K., Speelman, C., Maybery, M., O'Brien-Malone, A., Anderson, M., MacLeod, C. (eds.), Implicit and Explicit Mental Processes, Mahwah, NJ, London: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publishers, pp. 135–148.Google Scholar
Spring, R. J. (1975), “Vindicating the periodic law,” Education in Chemistry, 12: 134–138.Google Scholar
Stanford, P. K. (2000), “An Anti-Realist Explanation of the Success of Science,” Philosophy of Science, 67: 266–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strathern, P. (2000), The Quest for the Elements, New York: St. Martin's Press.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. (1998), “The Structure of a Scientific Paper,” Philosophy of Science, 65 (3): 381–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomason, N. (1992), “Could Lakatos, Even With Zahar's Criterion for Novel Fact, Evaluate the Copernican Research Programme?,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43: 161–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraassen, B. (1980), The Scientific Image, Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Fraassen, B.(1988), “The Problem of Old Evidence,” in Austin, D. F. (ed.)., Philosophical Analysis, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraassen, B.(1989), Laws and Symmetry, Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velikovsky, I. (1950), Worlds in Collision, New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Velikovsky, I.(1955), Earth in Upheaval, New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Venable, F. P. (1896), The Development of the Periodic Law, Chemical Publishing Co., Easton, PA.Google Scholar
Spronson, J. W. (1969), The Periodic System of Chemical Elements: A History of the First Hundred Years, Amsterdam, London and New York: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Wagner, C. (1978), “Consensus Through Respect: A Model of Rational Group Decision Making,” Philosophical Studies, 34: 335–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, C.(1981), “The Formal Foundations of Lehrer's Theory of Consensus,” in Bogdan, R. U. (ed.) Profile: Keith Lehrer, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Wagner, C.(1997), “Old evidence and new explanation,” Philosophy of Science, 64: 677–690.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, C.(1999), “Old evidence and new explanation II,” Philosophy of Science, 66: 283–288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, C.(2001), “Old evidence and new explanation III,” Philosophy of Science, 68: s165–s175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walton, D. (1997), Appeal to Expert Opinion: Arguments from Authority, University Park, Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
White, R. (2003), “The Epistemic Advantage of Prediction Over Accommodation,” Mind, 112: 448, 653–683.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, J. (1985), “Scientific Discovery and Theory Confirmation,” in Pitt, J. C. (ed.), Change and Progress in Modern Science, pp. 301–331, D. Reidel Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Worrall, J.(1989), “Fresnel, Poisson and the White Spot: The Role of Successful Predictions in the Acceptance of Scientific Theories,” printed in Gooding, D., Pinch, T. and Schaffer, S. (eds.), The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Worrall, J.(2002), “New Evidence for Old,” in Gardenfors, P., Wolenski, J., and Kihania-Placek, K. (eds.), In the Scope of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, vol. 1, pp. 191–209, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, J.(2005), “Prediction and the ‘Periodic Law’: A Rejoinder to Barnes,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 36: 817–826.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahar, E. (1973), “Why did Einstein's Programme supercede Lorentz's?,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 24: 95–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahar, E.(1989), Einstein's Revolution, La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Achinstein, P. (1991), Particles and Waves: Historical Essays in the Philosophy of Science, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Achinstein, P.(2001), The Book of Evidence, Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alston, W. (1976), “Two Types of Foundationalism,” Journal of Philosophy 73: 165–168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bamford, G. (1993), “Popper's Explications of Ad Hocness: Circularity, Empirical Content, and Scientific Practice,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 44: 335–355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E. (1996a), “Discussion: Thoughts on Maher's Predictivism,” Philosophy of Science, 63: 401–410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(1996b), “Social Predictivism,” Erkenntnis, 45: 69–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(1998), “Probabilities and Epistemic Pluralism,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48: 31–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(1999), “The Quantitative Problem of Old Evidence,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48: 31–47.Google Scholar
Barnes, E.(2000), “Ockham's Razor and the Anti-Superfluity Principle,” Erkenntnis, 53: 353–374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(2002), “Neither Truth nor Empirical Adequacy Explain Novel Success,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 80 (4): 418–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(2002), “The Miraculous Choice Argument for Realism,” Philosophical Studies, 111 (2): 97–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(2005a), “Predictivism for Pluralists,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 56: 421–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, E.(2005b), “On Mendeleev's Predictions: Comment on Scerri and Worrall,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 36: 801–812.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barret, J. (1996), “Oracles, Aesthetics, and Bayesian Consensus,” Philosophy of Science, Supplement to 63, S273–S280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bensaude-Vincent, B. (1986), “Mendeleev's Periodic System of Chemical Elements,” British Journal for the History of Science, 19: 3–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bensaude-Vincent, B.(2000), “From Teaching to Writing: Lecture Notes and Textbooks at the French Ecole Polytechnique,” in Lundren and Bensaude-Vincent, pp. 273–294.
Bonjour, L. [1976], “The Coherence Theory of Empirical Knowledge,” Philosophical Studies, 30: 281–312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonjour, L. [1978], “Can Empirical Knowledge Have a Foundation?,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 15: 1–13.Google Scholar
Boyd, R. (1981), “Scientific Realism and Naturalistic Epistemology,” PSA 1980 Vol. 2, East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 612–662.Google Scholar
Boyd, R.(1985), “Lex Orandi est Lex Credendi,” in Churchland, and Hooker, (eds.), pp. 612–662.Google Scholar
Boyd, R.(1991), “The Current Status of Scientific Realism,” in Boyd, R., Gasper, P., and Trout, J. D., (eds.) The Philosophy of Science, Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 195–222. Also printed in Leplin, J. (ed.) 1984, Scientific Realism, Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 41–82.Google Scholar
Brush, S. (1996), “The Reception of Mendeleev's periodic law in America and Britain,” Isis, 87: 595–628.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bynum, W. F., Browne, E. J., and Porter, R. (1981), Dictionary of the History of Science, Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, R. and Vinci, T. (1983), “Novel Confirmation,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 34: 315–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cassebaum, H. and Kauffman, G. B. (1971), “The Periodic System of the Chemical Elements: The Search for its Discoverer,” Isis, 62: 314–327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chihara, C. [1987], “Some Problems for Bayesian Confirmation Theory,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 38: 551–560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. and Hooker, C. (eds.) (1985), Images of Science: Essays on Realism and Empiricism with a Reply from Bas C. Van Fraassen, Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Christensen, D. (1999), “Measuring Confirmation,” Journal of Philosophy, 96: 437–461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, F. W. (1884), Elements of Chemistry, New York: Appleton.Google Scholar
Collins, R. (1994), “Against the Epistemic Value of Prediction Over Accommodation,” Nous, 28: 210–224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. (1992), Testimony: A Philosophical Study, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Darden, L. (1991), Theory Change in Science: Strategies from Mendelian Genetics, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Milt, C. (1951), “The Conference at Karlsruhe,” Journal of Chemical Education, 28: 421–424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douven, I. (2000), “The Anti-Realist Argument for Underdetermination,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 50: 371–375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drake, S. (1967), “Galileo Galilei,” The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 3, Edwards, P. (ed.), New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Earman, J. (ed.) (1983), Testing Scientific Theories, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Earman, J.(1992), Bayes or Bust? A Critical Examination of Bayesian Confirmation Theory, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Earman, J.(1993), “Carnap, Kuhn and the Philosophy of Science Methodology,” in Horwich, P. (ed.), World Changes, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.Google Scholar
Earman, J. and Glymour, C. (1980), “Relativity and Eclipses: The British Eclipse Expeditions of 1919 and Their Predecessors,” Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 11: 49–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwards, P. (1967), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, New York: Macmillan Publishing Company and the Free Press.Google Scholar
Eells, E. (1990), “Bayesian Problems of Old Evidence,” in Savage, W. (ed.), Scientific Theories, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Eells, E. and Fitelson, B. (2000), “Measuring Confirmation and Evidence,” Journal of Philosophy, 97: 663–672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Farrar, W. V. (1965), “Nineteenth Century Speculations on the Complexity of the Chemical Elements,” The British Journal for the History of Science, 2: 291–323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, A. (1986), “Unnatural Attitudes: Realist and Instrumentalist Attachments to Science,” Mind, 95: 145–179.Google Scholar
Fine, A.(1991), “Piecemeal Realism,” Philosophical Studies, 61: 79–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fitelson, B. (1999), “The Plurality of Bayesian Measures of Confirmation and the Problem of Measure Sensitivity,” Philosophy of Science, Supplement to Vol. 66, No. 3, S362–S378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foley, R. (2001), Intellectual Trust in Oneself and Others, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frankel, H. (1979), “The Career of Continental Drift Theory,” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 10: 21–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garber, D. (1983), “Old Evidence and Logical Omniscience in Bayesian Confirmation Theory,” in Earman [1983].
Gardner, M. (1982), “Predicting Novel Facts,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 33: 1–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, R. (1983), “Testing Theoretical Hypotheses,” in Earman, J. (ed.) Testing Scientific Theories, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 10, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Giere, R.(1984), Understanding Scientific Reasoning, 2nd edn., New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.Google Scholar
Gillespie, C. C. (ed.) (1971), Dictionary of Scientific Biography, New York: Charles Scribner's Sons.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. (1980), Theory and Evidence, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Good, I. J. (1967), “The White Shoe is a Red Herring,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 17: 322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gutting, G. (1985), “Scientific Realism versus Constructive Empiricism,” in Churchland and Hooker (eds.) pp. 118–131.
Grünbaum, A. (1984), The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique, University of California Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1979), “Imre Lakatos's Philosophy of Science,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 30: 381–410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardwig, J. (1985), “Epistemic Independence,” Journal of Philosophy, 82: 335–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardwig, J.(1991), “The Role of Trust in Knowledge,” Journal of Philosophy, 88: 693–708.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harker, D. (2006), “Accommodation and Prediction: The Case of the Persistent Head,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57: 309–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobbes, J. (1993), “Ex Post Facto Explanations,” Journal of Philosophy, 93: 117–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoel, P. G. (1971), Introduction to Mathematical Statistics, New York: John Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
Holden, N. E. (1984), “Mendeleev and the Periodic Classification of the Elements,” Chemical International, 6: 18–31.Google Scholar
Howson, C. (1984), “Bayesianism and Support by Novel Facts,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 35: 245–251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C.(1985), “Some Recent Objections to the Bayesian Theory of Support,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 36: 305–309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C.(1988), “Accommodation, Prediction, and Bayesian Confirmation Theory,” PSA 1988, 2: 381–292.Google Scholar
Howson, C.(1990), “Fitting Your Theory to the Facts: Probably Not Such a Bad Thing After All,” in Savage, W. (ed.), Scientific Theories, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 14. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Howson, C.(1991), “The ‘Old Evidence’ Problem,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 42: 547–555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C.(1996), “Error Probabilities in Error,” Philosophy of Science, Supplement to Vol. 64, pp. S185–S194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. and Franklin, A. (1991), “Maher, Mendeleev and Bayesianism,” Philosophy of Science, 58: 574–585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. and Urbach, P. (1989), Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach, Open Court, La Salle.Google Scholar
Ihde, A. J. (1961), “The Karlsruhe Congress: A Centennial Retrospective,” Journal of Chemical Education, 38 (2): 83–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, R. (1965), The Logic of Decision, McGraw-Hill Book Company.Google Scholar
Kahn, J. A., Landsberg, S. E., and Stockman, A. C. (1990), “On Novel Confirmation,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43: 503–516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kantorovich, A. (1993), Scientific Discovery: Logic and Tinkering, State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Kaplan, M. (1996), Decision Theory as Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keynes, J. M. (1929), A Treatise on Probability, London: Macmillan and Co.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1989), “Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World,” in Kitcher, P. and Salmon, W. (eds.), Scientific Explanation, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P.(1993), The Advancement of Science: Science Without Legend, Objectivity Without Illusions, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Knight, D. M. (1970), Classical Scientific Papers – Chemistry, 2nd Series, New York: American Elsevier.Google Scholar
Knight, D. M.(1992), Ideas in Chemistry: A History of the Science, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1970), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd edn., Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kukla, A. (1998), Studies in Scientific Realism, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kultgen, J. H. (1958), “Philosophic Conceptions in Mendeleev's Principles of Chemistry,” Philosophy of Science, 25: 177–183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kusch, M. (2002), Knowledge by Agreement, Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lackey, J. and Sosa, E. (eds.) (2006), The Epistemology of Testimony, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ladyman, J., Douven, I., Horsten, L., and Fraassen, B. (1997), “A Defense of Van Fraassen's Critique of Abductive Inference: Reply to Psillos,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 47: 305–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1981), Science and Hypothesis, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L.(1984), “Explaining the Success of Science: Beyond Epistemic Realism and Relativism,” in Cushing, J., Delaney, C. F., and Gutting, G. (eds.) Science and Reality, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L.(1990), “Normative Naturalism,” Philosophy of Science, 57: 44–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I. (1970), “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes,” in Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 91–196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, I.(1971), “History of Science and its Rational Reconstructions,” Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 8: 91–135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laing, M. (1995), “The Karlsruhe Conference, 1860,” Education in Chemistry, 32: 151–153.Google Scholar
Lange, M. (2001), “The Apparent Superiority of Prediction to Accommodation as a Side Effect: a Reply to Maher,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52: 575–588.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, K. (1974), “Induction, Consensus and Catastrophe,” in Bodgan, R. J. (ed.) Local Induction, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Lehrer, K.(1976), “When Rational Disagreement is Impossible,” Nous, 10: 327–332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, K.(1977), “Social Information,” Monist, 60: 473–487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, K.(1978), “Consensus and Comparison: A Theory of Social Rationality,” in Hooker, C. A., Leach, J. J., and McClennan, E. F. (eds.), Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory, Vol. 1, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Lehrer, K. and Wagner, C. (1981), Rational Consensus in Science and Society, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J. (1975), “The Concept of an Ad Hoc Hypothesis,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 5: 309–345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J.(1982), “The Assessment of Auxiliary Hypotheses,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 33: 235–249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J.(1987), “The Bearing of Discovery on Justification,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 17: 805–814.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J.(1997), A Novel Defense of Scientific Realism, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Leplin, J.(2000), “The Epistemic Status of Auxiliary Hypotheses,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 50: 376–379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1979), “Counterfactual Dependence and Time's Arrow,” Nous, 13: 455–476, reprinted in Lewis, D. (1986) Philosophical Papers, Vol. II, Oxford University Press, pp. 32–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, P. (1991), Inference to the Best Explanation, London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lipton, P.(1992–3), “Is the Best Good Enough?,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 93: 89–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, P.(2004), Inference to the Best Explanation, 2nd edn., London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1995), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Amherst, NY: Prometheus Press.Google Scholar
Longino, H. (1990), Science as Social Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Lundgren, A. (2000), “Theory and Practice in Swedish Chemical Textbooks during the Nineteenth Century,” in Lundgren and Bensaude-Vincent, pp. 91–118.
Lundgren, A. and Bensaude-Vincent, B. (2000), Communicating Chemistry: Textbooks and Their Audiences 1789–1939, USA, Science History Publications.Google Scholar
MacDonald, H. (1985), Eating for the Health of It, Priddis, Alberta: Austin Books.Google Scholar
Magnus, P. D. and Callender, C. (2004), “Realist Ennui and the Base Rate Fallacy,” Philosophy of Science, 71: 320–338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maher, P. (1988), “Prediction, Accommodation, and the Logic of Discovery,” PSA 1988, 1: 273–285.Google Scholar
Maher, P.(1990), “How Prediction Enhances Confirmation,” in Dunn, J. M. and Gupta, A. (eds.), Truth or Consequences: Essays in Honor of Nuel Belnap, Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 327–343.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Maher, P.(1993), “Howson and Franklin on Prediction,” Philosophy of Science, 60: 329–340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maher, P.[1996], “Subjective and Objective Confirmation,” Philosophy of Science, 63: 149–174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Manahan, S. E. (1997), Environmental Science and Technology, Boca Raton, New York: Lewis Publishers.Google Scholar
Marsden, G. (1980), Fundamentalism and American Culture: The Shaping of Twentieth Century Evangelicalism, New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Maxwell, G. (1962), “The Ontological Status of Theoretical Entities,” in Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G. (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol 3. Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 12–13.Google Scholar
Mayo, D. (1991), “Novel Evidence and Severe Tests,” Philosophy of Science, 58: 523–553.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D.(1996), Error and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge, University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAllister, J. W. (1996), Beauty and Revolution in Science, Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Meehl, P. (1999), “How to Weight Scientists' Probabilities is Not a Big Problem: Comment on Barnes,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50: 283–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mendeleev, D. (1889), “The Periodic Law of the Chemical Elements: Faraday Lecture,” printed in Knight (1970), pp. 322–344.
Merton, R. (1973), “The Normative Structure of Science,” printed in Merton, R. The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations, ed. Storer, N. W., Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1961), System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive, 8th edn., London.Google Scholar
Murphy, N. (1989), “Another Look at Novel Facts,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 20. (3), 385–388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, A. (1974), “Logical versus Historical Theories of Confirmation,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25: 1–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, A.(1985), “Realism versus Constructive Empiricism,” in Churchland and Hooker (eds.), pp. 197–221.
Musgrave, A.(1988), “The Ultimate Argument for Scientific Realism,” in Nola, R. (ed.), Relativism and Realism in Science, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 229–252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T. (1987), “Lakatosian Heuristics and Epistemic Support,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 38: 181–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T.(1988), “Truth or Consequences? Generative Versus Consequential Justification in Science,” PSA 1988, Vol. 2, 393–405.Google Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1983), “Novel Facts and Bayesianism,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 34: 375–379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nunan, R. (1984), “Novel Facts, Bayesian Rationality, and the History of Continental Drift,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 15: 267–307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Partington, J. R. (1964), A History of Chemistry, Vol. 4, London: Macmillan and Co. LTD.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1897), Anonymous Review of Mendeleev's Principles of Chemistry, Nation, 25: 424.Google Scholar
Peters, D. and Ceci, S. (1982), “Peer Review Practices of Psychological Journals: The Fate of Published Articles Submitted Again,” Behavior and Brain Sciences, 5: 187–195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. (1963), Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, New York and Evanston: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975), Mathematics, Matter, and Method, New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. (1996), “On Van Fraassen's Critique of Abductive Reasoning,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 46: 31–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Psillos, S.(1997), “How Not to Defend Constructive Empiricism: A Rejoinder,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 47: 369–372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Psillos, S.(1999), Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth, London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. (1951), “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” The Philosophical Review, 60: 20–43. Reprinted in Quine (1953), From a Logical Point of View, Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O.(1960), Word and Object, Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Redhead, M. (1986), “Novelty and Confirmation,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 37: 115–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Richmond, A. (1999), “Between Abduction and the Deep Blue Sea,” The Philosophical Quarterly, 49: 86–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenkranz, R. (1983), “Why Glymour IS a Bayesian,” in Earman, 1983, pp. 69–98.
Salmon, W. (1966), The Foundation of Scientific Inference, University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W.(1981), “Rational Prediction,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 32: 115–125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sambursky, S. (1971), “Structure and Periodicity: Centenary of Mendeleev's Discovery,” Proceedings of the Israel Academy of Sciences and Humanities, 4: 1–13.Google Scholar
Scerri, E. (2005), “Response to Barnes' critique of Scerri and Worrall,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 36: 813–816.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scerri, E.(2007), The Periodic Table: Its Story and its Significance, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Scerri, E. and Worrall, J. (2001), “Prediction and the Periodic Table,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 32: 407–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffner, K. (1974), “Einstein versus Lorentz: Research Programmes and the Logic of Theory Evaluation,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25: 45–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlesinger, G. (1987), “Accommodation and Prediction,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 65: 33–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapere, D. (1982), “The Concept of Observation in Science and Philosophy,” Philosophy of Science, 49: 485–525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapin, S. (1994), A Social History of Truth, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Shapin, S. and Schaffer, S. (1985), Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle and the Experimental Life, Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sobel, M. (1987), Light, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1988), Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution and Inference, Cambridge, MA, and London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. and Hitchcock, C. (2004), “Prediction Versus Accommodation and the Risk of Overfitting,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55: 1–34.Google Scholar
Solov'ev, Y. I. (1984), “D.I. Mendeleev and the English Chemists,” Journal of Chemical Education, 61: 1069–1071.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soyfer, V. (1994), Lysenko and the Tragedy of Soviet Science, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
Speelman, C. (1998), “Implicit Expertise: Do We Expect Too Much From Our Experts?,” in Kirsner, K., Speelman, C., Maybery, M., O'Brien-Malone, A., Anderson, M., MacLeod, C. (eds.), Implicit and Explicit Mental Processes, Mahwah, NJ, London: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publishers, pp. 135–148.Google Scholar
Spring, R. J. (1975), “Vindicating the periodic law,” Education in Chemistry, 12: 134–138.Google Scholar
Stanford, P. K. (2000), “An Anti-Realist Explanation of the Success of Science,” Philosophy of Science, 67: 266–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strathern, P. (2000), The Quest for the Elements, New York: St. Martin's Press.Google Scholar
Suppe, F. (1998), “The Structure of a Scientific Paper,” Philosophy of Science, 65 (3): 381–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thomason, N. (1992), “Could Lakatos, Even With Zahar's Criterion for Novel Fact, Evaluate the Copernican Research Programme?,” The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43: 161–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraassen, B. (1980), The Scientific Image, Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Fraassen, B.(1988), “The Problem of Old Evidence,” in Austin, D. F. (ed.)., Philosophical Analysis, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fraassen, B.(1989), Laws and Symmetry, Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velikovsky, I. (1950), Worlds in Collision, New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Velikovsky, I.(1955), Earth in Upheaval, New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Venable, F. P. (1896), The Development of the Periodic Law, Chemical Publishing Co., Easton, PA.Google Scholar
Spronson, J. W. (1969), The Periodic System of Chemical Elements: A History of the First Hundred Years, Amsterdam, London and New York: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Wagner, C. (1978), “Consensus Through Respect: A Model of Rational Group Decision Making,” Philosophical Studies, 34: 335–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, C.(1981), “The Formal Foundations of Lehrer's Theory of Consensus,” in Bogdan, R. U. (ed.) Profile: Keith Lehrer, Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Wagner, C.(1997), “Old evidence and new explanation,” Philosophy of Science, 64: 677–690.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, C.(1999), “Old evidence and new explanation II,” Philosophy of Science, 66: 283–288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, C.(2001), “Old evidence and new explanation III,” Philosophy of Science, 68: s165–s175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walton, D. (1997), Appeal to Expert Opinion: Arguments from Authority, University Park, Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
White, R. (2003), “The Epistemic Advantage of Prediction Over Accommodation,” Mind, 112: 448, 653–683.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, J. (1985), “Scientific Discovery and Theory Confirmation,” in Pitt, J. C. (ed.), Change and Progress in Modern Science, pp. 301–331, D. Reidel Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Worrall, J.(1989), “Fresnel, Poisson and the White Spot: The Role of Successful Predictions in the Acceptance of Scientific Theories,” printed in Gooding, D., Pinch, T. and Schaffer, S. (eds.), The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Worrall, J.(2002), “New Evidence for Old,” in Gardenfors, P., Wolenski, J., and Kihania-Placek, K. (eds.), In the Scope of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, vol. 1, pp. 191–209, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, J.(2005), “Prediction and the ‘Periodic Law’: A Rejoinder to Barnes,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 36: 817–826.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahar, E. (1973), “Why did Einstein's Programme supercede Lorentz's?,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 24: 95–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zahar, E.(1989), Einstein's Revolution, La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Bibliography
  • Eric Christian Barnes, Southern Methodist University, Texas
  • Book: The Paradox of Predictivism
  • Online publication: 22 September 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511487330.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Bibliography
  • Eric Christian Barnes, Southern Methodist University, Texas
  • Book: The Paradox of Predictivism
  • Online publication: 22 September 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511487330.010
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Bibliography
  • Eric Christian Barnes, Southern Methodist University, Texas
  • Book: The Paradox of Predictivism
  • Online publication: 22 September 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511487330.010
Available formats
×