Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-7479d7b7d-wxhwt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-10T02:32:37.142Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Appendix C - On schematic generalization

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 January 2010

Get access

Summary

The solution to liar-like paradoxes developed in Chapters 5 and 7 depends on a kind of context-sensitive limitation on the expressiveness of natural language. It has often been argued that the postulation of such limitations is self-defeating, since the theory being proposed cannot, by its own lights, be expressed with sufficient generality. I hope to show that this objection can be met by proposing a distinction between two kinds of generality: schematic and quantificational.

I begin with an objection to Burge' s solution posed by D. A. Martin. Although we cannot express higher-order liars in natural language, we certainly can do so by means of explicit quantification over Burgean propositions. We can, for instance, construct a self-referential proposition (λ1):

1) ¬ true11).

1) says, in effect, that (λ1) is not true1. This proposition is untrue1 and true2. Similarly, for each ordinal a, there is a liar proposition λa. We can introduce a function term ‘λ(x)’, designating, for each ordinal a, the liar λa. Now consider the token (A):

(A)∀x ∈ ON true(λ(x)).

Each liar λa is truea+1 but there is no level at which all are true. How, then, can we interpret the occurrence of the predicate ‘true’ in (A)?

The problem, of course, is that, in interpreting (A), we want to use a level that is the ordinal of the class of ordinals. The idea that there is an ordinal of the class of ordinals can be shown to be inconsistent; in fact, this was the first of the set-theoretic paradoxes to be discovered, the Burali–Forti paradox. Thus, in order to solve Martin's problem, something must be said about the solution to the set-theoretic paradoxes in intensional contexts.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1992

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×