Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-18T14:14:29.889Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

6 - Imagination and the arousal of the emotions in Greco-Roman rhetoric

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 December 2009

Susanna Morton Braund
Affiliation:
Royal Holloway, University of London
Christopher Gill
Affiliation:
University of Exeter
Ruth Webb
Affiliation:
Princeton University
Get access

Summary

The ability to arouse the emotions of an audience was vital to the ancient orator. To achieve persuasion, he had to be able to move his audience as well as convince them by reasoned argument. In this chapter, I take up one specific strand in Greco-Roman thinking on this subject: the use of ‘Vivid illustration’ or ‘imagination’ (enargeia or phantasia) to make the audience ‘see’ situations in their minds and respond accordingly. This topic is handled in the treatises of writers such as Quintilian, Longinus and Menander Rhetor in a way that presupposes a background of philosophical psychology as well as of rhetorical method. Moreover, the authors of these treatises were themselves readers. Their precepts are based on their knowledge of the practice of earlier orators and, most significantly for the present discussion, they occasionally reveal their own emotional responses to the compositions of others. What emerges both from these autobiographical comments and from their statements about the device of enargeia is the presumption that the emotional responses of a reader or audience are highly predictable. This assumption is also clearly present in the typology of emotional responses, and of kinds of audience, in Aristotle's Rhetoric 2, a discussion that contains much that is relevant to the understanding of the social and cultural background to ancient rhetoric. The Romantic idea that the powerof imagination on the part of the author and of the responding reader should be regarded as free, unlimited and unpredictable does not figure as part of this strand of ancient thought; and this fact, in itself, is relevant to the larger project of this volume, the understanding of the emotions in the ancient world.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×