Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-77c89778f8-5wvtr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-24T08:21:25.618Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

11 - Philosophers and human understanding

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 January 2010

Hilary Putnam
Affiliation:
Harvard University, Massachusetts
Get access

Summary

I find myself in the position that Jerome Bruner (1976) found himself in a few years before me. I agreed to give a Herbert Spencer lecture; I planned to give a lecture on the topic of scientific explanation; I intended to discuss a particular controversy in that field, the controversy about whether scientific theories are ‘incommensurable’, about whether there is any ‘convergence’ in scientific knowledge; but I felt increasing dissatisfaction with this entire idea as the day approached. Bruner's dissatisfaction led him to some reflections about the history and present state of psychology. I intend to follow his example and ruminate on the activity itself, the activity of philosophy of science, in my own case, and on certain dissatisfactions I feel with the way that activity has been pursued, rather than discuss a particular issue within it. However, the particular issue I mentioned will come up in the course of these ruminations.

Logical positivism is self-refuting

In the late 1920s, about 1928, the Vienna Circle announced the first of what were to be a series of formulations of an empiricist meaning criterion: the meaning of a sentence is its method of verification. A. J. Ayer's Language, Truth and Logic spread the new message to the English-speaking philosophical world: untestable statements are cognitively meaningless. A statement must either be (a) analytic (logically true, or logically false to be more precise) or (b) empirically testable, or (c) nonsense, i.e., not a real statement at all, but only a pseudostatement. Notice that this was already a change from the first formulation.

Type
Chapter
Information
Philosophical Papers , pp. 184 - 204
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 1983

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×