Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-84b7d79bbc-rnpqb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-07-25T16:21:20.361Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

References

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 September 2009

Samuel C. Rickless
Affiliation:
University of California, San Diego
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Plato's Forms in Transition
A Reading of the Parmenides
, pp. 251 - 256
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2006

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allen, Reginald E. 1960. “Participation and Predication in Plato's Middle Dialogues.” Philosophical Review 69: 147–164CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, Reginald E. 1965. Studies in Plato's Metaphysics. London: Routledge and Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Allen, Reginald E. 1983. Plato's Parmenides: Translation and Analysis. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Allen, Reginald E. 1997. Plato's Parmenides. Revised edition. New Haven: Yale University PressGoogle Scholar
Annas, Julia. 1974. “Forms and First Principles.” Phronesis 19: 257–283CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, Julia. 1981. An Introduction to Plato's Republic. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Baltzly, Dirk. 1997. “Knowledge and Belief in Republic Ⅴ.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79: 239–272CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, Hugh H. 2000. Socratic Wisdom: The Model of Knowledge in Plato's Early Dialogues. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Beversluis, John. 1993. “Vlastos's Quest for the Historical Socrates.” Ancient Philosophy 13: 293–312CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bluck, R. S. 1955. Plato's Phaedo. London: Routledge and Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Bostock, David. 1986. Plato's Phaedo. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Brown, Lesley. 1986. “Being in the Sophist: A Syntactical Inquiry.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 4: 49–70Google Scholar
Brumbaugh, Robert S. 1961. Plato on the One: The Hypotheses in the Parmenides. New Haven: Yale University PressGoogle Scholar
Burge, Evan L. 1971. “The Ideas as Aitiai in the Phaedo.” Phronesis 16: 1–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnet, John. 1911. Plato's Phaedo. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Cherniss, Harold. 1945. The Riddle of the Early Academy. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Cherniss, Harold. 1957. “The Relation of the Timaeus to Plato's Later Dialogues.” American Journal of Philology 78: 225–266CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S. Marc. 1971. “The Logic of the Third Man.” Philosophical Review 80: 448–475CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, John M. (ed.). 1997. Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis: HackettGoogle Scholar
Cornford, Francis M. 1939. Plato and Parmenides. London: Routledge and Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Cresswell, M. J. 1971. “Plato's Theory of Causality: Phaedo 95–106.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49: 244–249CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crombie, I. M. 1962–1963. An Examination of Plato's Doctrines. 2 vols. London: Routledge and Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Cross, R. C. and Woozley, A. D.. 1964. Plato's Republic: A Philosophical Commentary. London: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Dancy, R. M. 1984. “The One, The Many, and the Forms: Philebus 15b1–8.” Ancient Philosophy 4: 160–193CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dancy, R. M. 1991. Two Studies in the Early Academy. Albany: State University of New York PressGoogle Scholar
Dancy, R. M. 2004. Plato's Introduction of Forms. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Devereux, Daniel. 1994. “Separation and Immanence in Plato's Theory of Forms.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12: 63–90Google Scholar
Dorter, Kenneth. 1994. Form and Good in Plato's Eleatic Dialogues: The Parmenides, Theaetetus, Sophist, and Statesman. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1978. “Knowledge and Belief in Republic Ⅴ.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 60: 121–139. Reprinted in Fine 2003, 66–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1980. “The One over Many.” Philosophical Review 89: 197–240CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1984. “Separation.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 2: 31–87. Reprinted in Fine 2003, 252–300Google Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1985. “Separation: A Reply to Morrison.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 3: 159–165Google Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1990. “Knowledge and Belief in Republic Ⅴ–Ⅶ.” In Epistemology: Companions to Ancient Thought, vol. Ⅰ, edited by Everson, Stephen, 85–115. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in Fine 2003, 85–116Google Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1993. On Ideas: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Fine, Gail. 2003. Plato on Knowledge and Forms: Selected Essays. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Forrester, James W. 1972. “Plato's Parmenides: The Structure of the First Hypothesis.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 10: 1–14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frances, Bryan. 1996. “Plato's Response to the Third Man Argument in the Paradoxical Exercise of the Parmenides.” Ancient Philosophy 16: 47–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallop, David. 1975. Plato: Phaedo. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Gerson, Lloyd P. 2000. “Plato Absconditus.” In Who Speaks for Plato: Studies in Platonic Anonymity, edited by Gerald, A. Press, 201–210. Lanham: Rowman & LittlefieldGoogle Scholar
Gill, Mary Louise. 1996. “Introduction.” In Gill and Ryan 1996, 1–116
Gill, Mary Louise and Ryan, Paul (eds.). 1996. Plato: Parmenides. Indianapolis: Hackett. Reprinted, without the introduction, in Cooper 1997, 360–397Google Scholar
Gonzalez, Francisco. 1996. “Propositions or Objects? A Critique of Gail Fine on Knowledge and Belief in Republic Ⅴ.” Phronesis 41: 245–275CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gosling, Justin. 1960. “Republic Ⅴ: ta polla kala.” Phronesis 5: 116–128CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gosling, Justin. 1965. “Similarity in Phaedo 73bseq.” Phronesis 10: 151–161CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gosling, Justin. 1977. “Reply to White.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7: 307–314CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hackforth, R. 1955. Plato's Phaedo. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Hardie, W. F. R. 1936. A Study in Plato. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Harte, Verity. 2002. Plato on Parts and Wholes: The Metaphysics of Structure. Oxford: Clarendon PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hestir, Blake. 2000. “A Conception of Truth in Republic Ⅴ.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 17: 311–332Google Scholar
Irwin, Terence H. 1977a. Plato's Moral Theory: The Early and Middle Dialogues. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Irwin, Terence H. 1977b. “Plato's Heracliteanism.” Philosophical Quarterly 27: 1–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, Terence H. 1999. “The Theory of Forms.” In Plato Ⅰ: Metaphysics and Epistemology, edited by Fine, Gail, 143–170. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Kahn, Charles H. 1996. Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Kirwan, Christopher. 1974. “Plato and Relativity.” Phronesis 19: 112–129CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, Richard (ed.). 1992a. The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, Richard 1992a. The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge: 1992b. “Introduction to the Study of Plato.” In Kraut 1992a, 1–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, A. C. 1976. “The Principle that the Cause is Greater than Its Effect.” Phronesis 21: 146–156CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malcolm, John. 1991. Plato on the Self-Predication of Forms: Early and Middle Dialogues. Oxford: Clarendon PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthen, Mohan. 1984. “Forms and Participants in Plato's Phaedo.” NoÛs 18: 281–297CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCabe, , Mary, M. 1994. Plato's Individuals. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Meinwald, Constance C. 1991. Plato's Parmenides. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Meinwald, Constance C. 1992. “Good-bye to the Third Man.” In Kraut 1992a, 365–396
Miller, Mitchell H. Jr. 1986. Plato's Parmenides: The Conversion of the Soul. Princeton: Princeton University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mills, K. W. 1957–1958. “Plato's Phaedo, 74b7–c6.” Phronesis 2: 128–147 and 3: 40–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moravcsik, Julius. 1992. Plato and Platonism. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Morrison, D. R. 1985a. “Separation in Aristotle's Metaphysics.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 3: 31–89Google Scholar
Morrison, D. R. 1985b. “Separation: A Reply to Fine.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 3: 167–173Google Scholar
Nails, Debra. 1993. “Problems with Vlastos's Platonic Developmentalism.” Ancient Philosophy 13: 273–291CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nails, Debra. 2000. “Mouthpiece Schmouthpiece.” In Who Speaks for Plato: Studies in Platonic Anonymity, edited by Gerald, A. Press, 15–26. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander. 1975a. “Plato on the Imperfection of the Sensible World.” American Philosophical Quarterly 12: 105–117. Reprinted in Nehamas 1999, 138–158Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander 1975b. “Confusing Universals and Particulars in Plato's Early Dialogues.” Review of Metaphysics 29: 287–306. Reprinted in Nehamas 1999, 159–175Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander 1979. “Self-Predication and Plato's Theory of Forms.” American Philosophical Quarterly 16: 93–103. Reprinted in Nehamas 1999, 176–195Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander 1982. “Participation and Predication in Plato's Later Thought.” Review of Metaphysics 36: 343–374. Reprinted in Nehamas 1999, 196–223Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander 1999. Virtues of Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1953. “The Place of the Timaeus in Plato's Dialogues.” Classical Quarterly, N. S. 111: 79–95. Reprinted in Owen 1986, 65–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1957. “A Proof in the Peri Ideōn.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 77: 103–111. Reprinted in Owen 1986, 165–179Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1968. “Dialectic and Eristic in the Treatment of the Forms.” In Aristotle on Dialectic: The Topics (Papers of The Third Symposium Aristotelicum, Oxford: Oxford University Press), edited by Owen, G. E. L., 103–125. Reprinted in Owen 1986, 221–238Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1970. “Notes on Ryle's Plato.” In Ryle: A Collection of Critical Essays, edited by Oscar, P. Wood and Pitcher, George, 341–372. Reprinted in Owen 1986, 85–103CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1986. Logic, Science, and Dialectic: Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy. Ithaca: Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
Patterson, Richard. 1985. Image and Reality in Plato's Metaphysics. Indianapolis: HackettGoogle Scholar
Patterson, Richard 1999. “Forms, Fallacies, and the Functions of Plato's Parmenides.” Apeiron 32: 89–106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Penner, Terry. 1987. The Ascent From Nominalism: Some Existence Arguments in Plato's Middle Dialogues. Dordrecht: D. ReidelCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, Sandra. 1973. “A Reasonable Self-Predication Premise for the Third Man Argument.” Philosophical Review 82: 451–470CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, Sandra. 1981. “The Greatest Difficulty for Plato's Theory of Forms: The Unknowability Argument of Parmenides 133c–134c.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 63: 1–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, Sandra. 1996. “Plato's Parmenides: A Principle of Interpretation and Seven Arguments.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 34: 167–192CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, Sandra. 2000. “The Language Game in Plato's Parmenides.” Ancient Philosophy 20: 19–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, Sandra. 2003. “New Rounds of the Exercise in Plato's Parmenides.” Modern Schoolman 80: 245–278CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Press, Gerald A. 2000. “The Logic of Attributing Characters’ Views to Plato.” In Who Speaks for Plato: Studies in Platonic Anonymity, edited by Gerald, A. Press, 27–38. Lanham: Rowman & LittlefieldGoogle Scholar
Prior, William J. 1985. Unity and Development in Plato's Metaphysics. La Salle: Open CourtGoogle Scholar
Prior, William J. 2004. Review of Silverman 2002. Journal of the History of Philosophy 42: 97–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rickless, Samuel C. 1998a. “How Parmenides Saved the Theory of Forms.” Philosophical Review 107: 501–554CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rickless, Samuel C. 1998b. “Socrates' Moral Intellectualism.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 79: 355–367CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Richard. 1953. Plato's Earlier Dialectic. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Rohr, Michael David. 1980. “Empty Forms in Plato.” In Reforging the Great Chain of Being, edited by Knuuttila, Simo, 19–56. Dordrecht: D. ReidelGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1924. Aristotle's Metaphysics. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1951. Plato's Theory of Ideas. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Runciman, W. G. 1959. “Plato's Parmenides.” Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 64: 89–120. Reprinted in Allen 1965, 149–184CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert. 1939. “Plato's Parmenides.” Mind 48: 129–151 and 302–325. Reprinted in Allen 1965, 97–147CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert. 1966. Plato's Progress. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Sayre, Kenneth. 1983. Plato's Late Ontology: A Riddle Resolved. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Sayre, Kenneth. 1996. Parmenides’ Lesson: Translation and Explication of Plato's Parmenides. South Bend: University of Notre Dame PressGoogle Scholar
Schofield, Malcolm. 1996. “Likeness and Likenesses in the Parmenides.” In Form and Argument in Late Plato, edited by Gill, Christopher and Mary, M. McCabe, 49–77. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Scolnicov, Samuel. 2003. Plato's Parmenides. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Sedley, David. 1998. “Platonic Causes.” Phronesis 43: 114–132CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shorey, Paul. 1903. The Unity of Plato's Thought. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Shorey, Paul. 1933. What Plato Said. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Silverman, Allan. 2002. The Dialectic of Essence: A Study of Plato's Metaphysics. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Smith, J. A. 1917. “General Relative Clauses in Greek.” Classical Review 31: 69–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sonnenschein, E. A. 1918. “The Indicative in Relative Clauses.” Classical Review 32: 68–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, A. E. 1915–1916. “Parmenides, Zeno, and Socrates.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 16: 234–289CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teloh, Henry. 1981. The Development of Plato's Metaphysics. University Park: Pennsylvania State University PressGoogle Scholar
Turnbull, Robert. 1998. The Parmenides and Plato's Late Philosophy. Toronto: University of Toronto PressGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory. 1954. “The Third Man Argument in the Parmenides.” Philosophical Review 63: 319–349. Reprinted, with an addendum, in Vlastos 1995, 166–193CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory. 1965a. “A Metaphysical Paradox.” In Vlastos 1981, 43–57Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1965b. “Degrees of Reality in Plato.” In New Essays on Plato and Aristotle, edited by Bambrough, Renford, 1–19. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Reprinted in Vlastos 1981, 58–75Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1969. “Plato's ‘Third Man’ Argument (Parm. 132a1–b2): Text and Logic.” Philosophical Quarterly 19: 289–301. Reprinted in Vlastos 1981, 342–365CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1974. “A Note on ‘Pauline Predications’ in Plato.” Phronesis 19: 95–101. Reprinted in Vlastos 1981, 404–409CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1981. Platonic Studies. 2nd edition. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1987. “‘Separation’ in Plato.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 5: 187–196Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1991. Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Ithaca: Cornell University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1995. Studies in Greek Philosophy, vol. ii: Socrates, Plato, and Their Tradition. Edited by Graham, Daniel. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Wedberg, Anders. 1955. Plato's Philosophy of Mathematics. Stockholm: Almqvist and Wiksell. Chapter 3 reprinted in Plato: A Collection of Critical Essays, vol. Ⅰ: Metaphysics and Epistemology, edited by Vlastos, Gregory, 28–52. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday AnchorGoogle Scholar
White, F. C. 1977. “The ‘Many’ in Republic 475a–480a.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7: 291–306CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, F. C. 1978. “J. Gosling on ta polla kala.” Phronesis 23: 127–132CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, Nicholas P. 1987. “Forms and Sensibles: Phaedo 74B–C.” Philosophical Topics 15: 197–214CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, Nicholas P. 1992. “Plato's Metaphysical Epistemology.” In Kraut 1992a, 277–310
Wundt, Max. 1935. Platons Parmenides. Stuttgart and Berlin: W. KohlhammerGoogle Scholar
Allen, Reginald E. 1960. “Participation and Predication in Plato's Middle Dialogues.” Philosophical Review 69: 147–164CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, Reginald E. 1965. Studies in Plato's Metaphysics. London: Routledge and Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Allen, Reginald E. 1983. Plato's Parmenides: Translation and Analysis. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota PressGoogle Scholar
Allen, Reginald E. 1997. Plato's Parmenides. Revised edition. New Haven: Yale University PressGoogle Scholar
Annas, Julia. 1974. “Forms and First Principles.” Phronesis 19: 257–283CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, Julia. 1981. An Introduction to Plato's Republic. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Baltzly, Dirk. 1997. “Knowledge and Belief in Republic Ⅴ.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79: 239–272CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benson, Hugh H. 2000. Socratic Wisdom: The Model of Knowledge in Plato's Early Dialogues. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Beversluis, John. 1993. “Vlastos's Quest for the Historical Socrates.” Ancient Philosophy 13: 293–312CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bluck, R. S. 1955. Plato's Phaedo. London: Routledge and Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Bostock, David. 1986. Plato's Phaedo. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Brown, Lesley. 1986. “Being in the Sophist: A Syntactical Inquiry.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 4: 49–70Google Scholar
Brumbaugh, Robert S. 1961. Plato on the One: The Hypotheses in the Parmenides. New Haven: Yale University PressGoogle Scholar
Burge, Evan L. 1971. “The Ideas as Aitiai in the Phaedo.” Phronesis 16: 1–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnet, John. 1911. Plato's Phaedo. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Cherniss, Harold. 1945. The Riddle of the Early Academy. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Cherniss, Harold. 1957. “The Relation of the Timaeus to Plato's Later Dialogues.” American Journal of Philology 78: 225–266CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, S. Marc. 1971. “The Logic of the Third Man.” Philosophical Review 80: 448–475CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cooper, John M. (ed.). 1997. Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis: HackettGoogle Scholar
Cornford, Francis M. 1939. Plato and Parmenides. London: Routledge and Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Cresswell, M. J. 1971. “Plato's Theory of Causality: Phaedo 95–106.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49: 244–249CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crombie, I. M. 1962–1963. An Examination of Plato's Doctrines. 2 vols. London: Routledge and Kegan PaulGoogle Scholar
Cross, R. C. and Woozley, A. D.. 1964. Plato's Republic: A Philosophical Commentary. London: MacmillanGoogle Scholar
Dancy, R. M. 1984. “The One, The Many, and the Forms: Philebus 15b1–8.” Ancient Philosophy 4: 160–193CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dancy, R. M. 1991. Two Studies in the Early Academy. Albany: State University of New York PressGoogle Scholar
Dancy, R. M. 2004. Plato's Introduction of Forms. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Devereux, Daniel. 1994. “Separation and Immanence in Plato's Theory of Forms.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12: 63–90Google Scholar
Dorter, Kenneth. 1994. Form and Good in Plato's Eleatic Dialogues: The Parmenides, Theaetetus, Sophist, and Statesman. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1978. “Knowledge and Belief in Republic Ⅴ.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 60: 121–139. Reprinted in Fine 2003, 66–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1980. “The One over Many.” Philosophical Review 89: 197–240CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1984. “Separation.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 2: 31–87. Reprinted in Fine 2003, 252–300Google Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1985. “Separation: A Reply to Morrison.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 3: 159–165Google Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1990. “Knowledge and Belief in Republic Ⅴ–Ⅶ.” In Epistemology: Companions to Ancient Thought, vol. Ⅰ, edited by Everson, Stephen, 85–115. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in Fine 2003, 85–116Google Scholar
Fine, Gail. 1993. On Ideas: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Fine, Gail. 2003. Plato on Knowledge and Forms: Selected Essays. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Forrester, James W. 1972. “Plato's Parmenides: The Structure of the First Hypothesis.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 10: 1–14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frances, Bryan. 1996. “Plato's Response to the Third Man Argument in the Paradoxical Exercise of the Parmenides.” Ancient Philosophy 16: 47–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallop, David. 1975. Plato: Phaedo. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Gerson, Lloyd P. 2000. “Plato Absconditus.” In Who Speaks for Plato: Studies in Platonic Anonymity, edited by Gerald, A. Press, 201–210. Lanham: Rowman & LittlefieldGoogle Scholar
Gill, Mary Louise. 1996. “Introduction.” In Gill and Ryan 1996, 1–116
Gill, Mary Louise and Ryan, Paul (eds.). 1996. Plato: Parmenides. Indianapolis: Hackett. Reprinted, without the introduction, in Cooper 1997, 360–397Google Scholar
Gonzalez, Francisco. 1996. “Propositions or Objects? A Critique of Gail Fine on Knowledge and Belief in Republic Ⅴ.” Phronesis 41: 245–275CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gosling, Justin. 1960. “Republic Ⅴ: ta polla kala.” Phronesis 5: 116–128CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gosling, Justin. 1965. “Similarity in Phaedo 73bseq.” Phronesis 10: 151–161CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gosling, Justin. 1977. “Reply to White.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7: 307–314CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hackforth, R. 1955. Plato's Phaedo. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Hardie, W. F. R. 1936. A Study in Plato. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Harte, Verity. 2002. Plato on Parts and Wholes: The Metaphysics of Structure. Oxford: Clarendon PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hestir, Blake. 2000. “A Conception of Truth in Republic Ⅴ.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 17: 311–332Google Scholar
Irwin, Terence H. 1977a. Plato's Moral Theory: The Early and Middle Dialogues. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Irwin, Terence H. 1977b. “Plato's Heracliteanism.” Philosophical Quarterly 27: 1–13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Irwin, Terence H. 1999. “The Theory of Forms.” In Plato Ⅰ: Metaphysics and Epistemology, edited by Fine, Gail, 143–170. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Kahn, Charles H. 1996. Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Kirwan, Christopher. 1974. “Plato and Relativity.” Phronesis 19: 112–129CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, Richard (ed.). 1992a. The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, Richard 1992a. The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge: 1992b. “Introduction to the Study of Plato.” In Kraut 1992a, 1–50CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lloyd, A. C. 1976. “The Principle that the Cause is Greater than Its Effect.” Phronesis 21: 146–156CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malcolm, John. 1991. Plato on the Self-Predication of Forms: Early and Middle Dialogues. Oxford: Clarendon PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthen, Mohan. 1984. “Forms and Participants in Plato's Phaedo.” NoÛs 18: 281–297CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCabe, , Mary, M. 1994. Plato's Individuals. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Meinwald, Constance C. 1991. Plato's Parmenides. New York: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
Meinwald, Constance C. 1992. “Good-bye to the Third Man.” In Kraut 1992a, 365–396
Miller, Mitchell H. Jr. 1986. Plato's Parmenides: The Conversion of the Soul. Princeton: Princeton University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mills, K. W. 1957–1958. “Plato's Phaedo, 74b7–c6.” Phronesis 2: 128–147 and 3: 40–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moravcsik, Julius. 1992. Plato and Platonism. Oxford: BlackwellGoogle Scholar
Morrison, D. R. 1985a. “Separation in Aristotle's Metaphysics.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 3: 31–89Google Scholar
Morrison, D. R. 1985b. “Separation: A Reply to Fine.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 3: 167–173Google Scholar
Nails, Debra. 1993. “Problems with Vlastos's Platonic Developmentalism.” Ancient Philosophy 13: 273–291CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nails, Debra. 2000. “Mouthpiece Schmouthpiece.” In Who Speaks for Plato: Studies in Platonic Anonymity, edited by Gerald, A. Press, 15–26. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander. 1975a. “Plato on the Imperfection of the Sensible World.” American Philosophical Quarterly 12: 105–117. Reprinted in Nehamas 1999, 138–158Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander 1975b. “Confusing Universals and Particulars in Plato's Early Dialogues.” Review of Metaphysics 29: 287–306. Reprinted in Nehamas 1999, 159–175Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander 1979. “Self-Predication and Plato's Theory of Forms.” American Philosophical Quarterly 16: 93–103. Reprinted in Nehamas 1999, 176–195Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander 1982. “Participation and Predication in Plato's Later Thought.” Review of Metaphysics 36: 343–374. Reprinted in Nehamas 1999, 196–223Google Scholar
Nehamas, Alexander 1999. Virtues of Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1953. “The Place of the Timaeus in Plato's Dialogues.” Classical Quarterly, N. S. 111: 79–95. Reprinted in Owen 1986, 65–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1957. “A Proof in the Peri Ideōn.” Journal of Hellenic Studies 77: 103–111. Reprinted in Owen 1986, 165–179Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1968. “Dialectic and Eristic in the Treatment of the Forms.” In Aristotle on Dialectic: The Topics (Papers of The Third Symposium Aristotelicum, Oxford: Oxford University Press), edited by Owen, G. E. L., 103–125. Reprinted in Owen 1986, 221–238Google Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1970. “Notes on Ryle's Plato.” In Ryle: A Collection of Critical Essays, edited by Oscar, P. Wood and Pitcher, George, 341–372. Reprinted in Owen 1986, 85–103CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owen, G. E. L. 1986. Logic, Science, and Dialectic: Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy. Ithaca: Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
Patterson, Richard. 1985. Image and Reality in Plato's Metaphysics. Indianapolis: HackettGoogle Scholar
Patterson, Richard 1999. “Forms, Fallacies, and the Functions of Plato's Parmenides.” Apeiron 32: 89–106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Penner, Terry. 1987. The Ascent From Nominalism: Some Existence Arguments in Plato's Middle Dialogues. Dordrecht: D. ReidelCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, Sandra. 1973. “A Reasonable Self-Predication Premise for the Third Man Argument.” Philosophical Review 82: 451–470CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, Sandra. 1981. “The Greatest Difficulty for Plato's Theory of Forms: The Unknowability Argument of Parmenides 133c–134c.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 63: 1–16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, Sandra. 1996. “Plato's Parmenides: A Principle of Interpretation and Seven Arguments.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 34: 167–192CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, Sandra. 2000. “The Language Game in Plato's Parmenides.” Ancient Philosophy 20: 19–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, Sandra. 2003. “New Rounds of the Exercise in Plato's Parmenides.” Modern Schoolman 80: 245–278CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Press, Gerald A. 2000. “The Logic of Attributing Characters’ Views to Plato.” In Who Speaks for Plato: Studies in Platonic Anonymity, edited by Gerald, A. Press, 27–38. Lanham: Rowman & LittlefieldGoogle Scholar
Prior, William J. 1985. Unity and Development in Plato's Metaphysics. La Salle: Open CourtGoogle Scholar
Prior, William J. 2004. Review of Silverman 2002. Journal of the History of Philosophy 42: 97–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rickless, Samuel C. 1998a. “How Parmenides Saved the Theory of Forms.” Philosophical Review 107: 501–554CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rickless, Samuel C. 1998b. “Socrates' Moral Intellectualism.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 79: 355–367CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Richard. 1953. Plato's Earlier Dialectic. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Rohr, Michael David. 1980. “Empty Forms in Plato.” In Reforging the Great Chain of Being, edited by Knuuttila, Simo, 19–56. Dordrecht: D. ReidelGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1924. Aristotle's Metaphysics. 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Ross, W. D. 1951. Plato's Theory of Ideas. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Runciman, W. G. 1959. “Plato's Parmenides.” Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 64: 89–120. Reprinted in Allen 1965, 149–184CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert. 1939. “Plato's Parmenides.” Mind 48: 129–151 and 302–325. Reprinted in Allen 1965, 97–147CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert. 1966. Plato's Progress. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
Sayre, Kenneth. 1983. Plato's Late Ontology: A Riddle Resolved. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Sayre, Kenneth. 1996. Parmenides’ Lesson: Translation and Explication of Plato's Parmenides. South Bend: University of Notre Dame PressGoogle Scholar
Schofield, Malcolm. 1996. “Likeness and Likenesses in the Parmenides.” In Form and Argument in Late Plato, edited by Gill, Christopher and Mary, M. McCabe, 49–77. Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
Scolnicov, Samuel. 2003. Plato's Parmenides. Berkeley: University of California PressGoogle Scholar
Sedley, David. 1998. “Platonic Causes.” Phronesis 43: 114–132CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shorey, Paul. 1903. The Unity of Plato's Thought. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Shorey, Paul. 1933. What Plato Said. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
Silverman, Allan. 2002. The Dialectic of Essence: A Study of Plato's Metaphysics. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Smith, J. A. 1917. “General Relative Clauses in Greek.” Classical Review 31: 69–71CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sonnenschein, E. A. 1918. “The Indicative in Relative Clauses.” Classical Review 32: 68–69CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, A. E. 1915–1916. “Parmenides, Zeno, and Socrates.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 16: 234–289CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Teloh, Henry. 1981. The Development of Plato's Metaphysics. University Park: Pennsylvania State University PressGoogle Scholar
Turnbull, Robert. 1998. The Parmenides and Plato's Late Philosophy. Toronto: University of Toronto PressGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory. 1954. “The Third Man Argument in the Parmenides.” Philosophical Review 63: 319–349. Reprinted, with an addendum, in Vlastos 1995, 166–193CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory. 1965a. “A Metaphysical Paradox.” In Vlastos 1981, 43–57Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1965b. “Degrees of Reality in Plato.” In New Essays on Plato and Aristotle, edited by Bambrough, Renford, 1–19. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Reprinted in Vlastos 1981, 58–75Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1969. “Plato's ‘Third Man’ Argument (Parm. 132a1–b2): Text and Logic.” Philosophical Quarterly 19: 289–301. Reprinted in Vlastos 1981, 342–365CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1974. “A Note on ‘Pauline Predications’ in Plato.” Phronesis 19: 95–101. Reprinted in Vlastos 1981, 404–409CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1981. Platonic Studies. 2nd edition. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1987. “‘Separation’ in Plato.” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 5: 187–196Google Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1991. Socrates, Ironist and Moral Philosopher. Ithaca: Cornell University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vlastos, Gregory 1995. Studies in Greek Philosophy, vol. ii: Socrates, Plato, and Their Tradition. Edited by Graham, Daniel. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Wedberg, Anders. 1955. Plato's Philosophy of Mathematics. Stockholm: Almqvist and Wiksell. Chapter 3 reprinted in Plato: A Collection of Critical Essays, vol. Ⅰ: Metaphysics and Epistemology, edited by Vlastos, Gregory, 28–52. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday AnchorGoogle Scholar
White, F. C. 1977. “The ‘Many’ in Republic 475a–480a.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7: 291–306CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, F. C. 1978. “J. Gosling on ta polla kala.” Phronesis 23: 127–132CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, Nicholas P. 1987. “Forms and Sensibles: Phaedo 74B–C.” Philosophical Topics 15: 197–214CrossRefGoogle Scholar
White, Nicholas P. 1992. “Plato's Metaphysical Epistemology.” In Kraut 1992a, 277–310
Wundt, Max. 1935. Platons Parmenides. Stuttgart and Berlin: W. KohlhammerGoogle Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • References
  • Samuel C. Rickless, University of California, San Diego
  • Book: Plato's Forms in Transition
  • Online publication: 22 September 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511482618.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • References
  • Samuel C. Rickless, University of California, San Diego
  • Book: Plato's Forms in Transition
  • Online publication: 22 September 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511482618.011
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • References
  • Samuel C. Rickless, University of California, San Diego
  • Book: Plato's Forms in Transition
  • Online publication: 22 September 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511482618.011
Available formats
×