Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-thh2z Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-10T09:21:59.811Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Works cited

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  11 September 2009

Christopher McMahon
Affiliation:
University of California, Santa Barbara
Get access

Summary

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Chapter
Information
Reasonable Disagreement
A Theory of Political Morality
, pp. 195 - 199
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2009

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Anderson, Elizabeth, “What is the Point of Equality?Ethics 109 (1999), pp. 287–337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ankersmit, F. R., “Historiography and Postmodernism,” History and Theory 28 (May 1989), pp. 137–153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ankersmit, F. R., “Reply to Professor Zagorin,” History and Theory 29 (October 1990), pp. 275–296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Appleby, Joyce, Hunt, Lynn, and Jacob, Margaret, Telling the Truth about History (New York: Norton, 1994).Google Scholar
Barthes, Roland, “Historical Discourse,” in Lane, M., ed., Structuralism: A Reader (London: Jonathan Cape, 1970), pp. 145–155.Google Scholar
Blackburn, Simon, Ruling Passions (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998).Google Scholar
Boghossian, Paul, Fear of Knowledge: Against Relativism and Constructivism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, Richard, “How to Be a Moral Realist,” in Sayre-McCord, G., ed., Essays on Moral Realism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989), pp. 181–228.Google Scholar
Brandom, Robert B., Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000).Google Scholar
Brenner, Robert, “The Rises and Declines of Serfdom in Medieval and Early Modern Europe,” in Bush, M. L., ed., Serfdom and Slavery: Studies in Legal Bondage (London: Longman, 1996), pp. 247–276.Google Scholar
Bush, Michael, “Serfdom in Medieval and Modern Europe: A Comparison,” in Bush, M. L., ed., Serfdom and Slavery: Studies in Legal Bondage (London: Longman, 1996), pp. 199–224.Google Scholar
Callinicos, Alex, Theories and Narratives: Reflections on the Philosophy of History (Durham: Duke University Press, 1995).Google Scholar
Cervantes, Fernando, “Epilogue, the Middle Ground,” in Griffiths, N. and Cervantes, F., eds., Spiritual Encounters: Interaction between Christianity and Native Religions in Colonial America (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1999), pp. 276–285.Google Scholar
Chang, Ruth, “All Things Considered,” Philosophical Perspectives 18 (2004), pp. 1–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, David, “, Epistemology of Disagreement: The Good News,” The Philosophical Review 116 (2007), pp. 187–217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, G. A., “On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice,” Ethics 99 (1989), pp. 906–944.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, G. A., “Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 26 (1997), pp. 3–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Joshua, “Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy,” in Bohman, J. and Rehg, W., eds., Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997), pp. 67–91.Google Scholar
Cohen, Joshua and Sabel, Charles, “Extra Republicam Nulla Justitia,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (2006), pp. 147–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collingwood, R. G., The Idea of History (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1946).Google Scholar
Daniels, Norman, “Wide Reflective Equilibrium and Theory Acceptance in Ethics,” The Journal of Philosophy 76 (1979), pp. 256–282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Danto, Arthur, Narration and Knowledge (New York: Columbia University Press, 1985).Google Scholar
Davies, Wendy, “On Servile Status in the Early Middle Ages,” in Bush, M. L., ed., Serfdom and Slavery: Studies in Legal Bondage (London: Longman, 1996), pp. 225–246.Google Scholar
Derrida, Jacques, Of Grammatology, trans. Spivak, G. C. (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974).Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry, Concepts: Where Cognitive Science Went Wrong (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foucault, Michel, The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences (New York: Vintage Books, 1994).Google Scholar
Gareis, Iris, “Repression and Cultural Change: The ‘Extirpation of Idolatry’ in Colonial Peru,” in Griffiths, N. and Cervantes, F., eds., Spiritual Encounters: Interaction between Christianity and Native Religions in Colonial America (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1999), pp. 230–254.Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond, The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981).Google Scholar
Gibbard, Allan, Thinking How to Live (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003).Google Scholar
Goldman, Alvin I., Knowledge in a Social World (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1999).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodin, Robert, Reflective Democracy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, Nelson, Ways of Worldmaking (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1978).Google Scholar
Griffiths, Nicholas, “Introduction,” in Griffiths, N. and Cervantes, F., eds., Spiritual Encounters: Interaction between Christianity and Native Religions in Colonial America (Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1999).Google Scholar
Gutmann, Amy and Dennis, Thompson, Democracy and Disagreement (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996).Google Scholar
Gutmann, Amy and Dennis, Thompson, Why Deliberative Democracy? (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. I, trans. McCarthy, Thomas (Boston: Beacon, 1984).Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen “Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Program of Philosophical Justification,” in Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, trans. Lenhardt, C. and Nicholsen, S. W. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990), pp. 43–115.Google Scholar
Harman, Gilbert, “Inference to the Best Explanation,” The Philosophical Review 74 (1965), pp. 88–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, Gilbert, “Moral Relativism Defended,” The Philosophical Review 84 (1975), pp. 3–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartley, L. P., The Go-Between (New York: Knopf, 1954).Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl, “The Function of General Laws in History,” The Journal of Philosophy 39 (1942), pp. 35–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas, Leviathan, ed. Curley, E. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1994).Google Scholar
Horgan, Terry and Timmons, Mark, “Cognitivist Expressivism,” in Horgan, T. and Timmons, M., eds., Metaethics After Moore (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurley, S. L., Natural Reasons: Personality and Polity (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989).Google Scholar
Hurley, S. L., Justice, Luck, and Knowledge (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Julius, A. J., “Nagel's Atlas,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (2006), pp. 176–192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kelly, Thomas, “The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement,” in Gendler, T. and Hawthorne, J., eds., Oxford Studies in Epistemology, vol. I (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 167–196.Google Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine M., The Sources of Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul A., Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982).Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will, Multicultural Citizenship (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995).Google Scholar
Larmore, Charles, “Pluralism and Reasonable Disagreement,” in The Morals of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 152–174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John, The Second Treatise of Government, ed. MacPherson, C. B. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1980).Google Scholar
Mackie, J. L., Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1977).Google Scholar
Martin, Rex, Historical Explanation (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1977).Google Scholar
Marx, Karl, “Preface to A Critique of Political Economy,” in Karl Marx: Selected Writings, ed. McLellen, David (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), pp. 424–428.Google Scholar
McDowell, John, “Non-Cognitivism and Rule-Following,” in Mind, Value, and Reality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), pp. 198–218.Google Scholar
McDowell, John, “Values and Secondary Qualities,” in Mind, Value, and Reality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), pp. 131–150.Google Scholar
McMahon, Christopher, Collective Rationality and Collective Reasoning (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001).Google Scholar
McMahon, Christopher, “Why There is No Issue Between Habermas and Rawls,” The Journal of Philosophy 99 (2002), pp. 111–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahon, Christopher, “The Indeterminacy of Republican Policy,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (2005), pp. 67–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahon, Christopher, “Nondomination and Normativity,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88 (2007), pp. 319–327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahon, Christopher, “The Public Authority of the Managers of Private Corporations,” forthcoming in Brenkert, G. and Beauchamp, T., eds., The Oxford Handbook of Business Ethics.
Mill, John Stuart, Utilitarianism, ed. Sher, G. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2002).Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart, On Liberty, ed. Bromwich, David and Kateb, George (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2003).Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett, “Truth Rules, Hoverflies, and the Kripke–Wittgenstein Paradox,” The Philosophical Review 99 (1990), pp. 323–353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moody-Adams, Michelle, Fieldwork in Familiar Places (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1997).Google Scholar
Munslow, Alan, Deconstructing History (London: Routledge, 1997).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, The Last Word (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas, “The Problem of Global Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (2005), pp. 113–147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Patterson, Orlando, Slavery and Social Death: A Comparative Study (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982).Google Scholar
Peacocke, Christopher, The Realm of Reason (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip, The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society, and Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philip, A Theory of Freedom: From the Psychology to the Politics of Agency (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001).Google Scholar
Pettit, Philip, “The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 34 (2006), pp. 274–283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philip, “When to Defer to Majority Testimony – and When Not to,” Analysis 66 (2007), pp. 179–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin, Warrant and Proper Function (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary, Meaning and the Moral Sciences (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979).Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” The Philosophical Review 60 (1951), pp. 20–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabb, Theodore K., The Last Days of the Renaissance and the March to Modernity (New York: Basic Books, 2006).Google Scholar
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971).Google Scholar
Rawls, John, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Richardson, Henry S., Democratic Autonomy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).Google Scholar
Richter, Daniel, Facing East from Indian Country: A Native History of Early America (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001).Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, On the Social Contract, in Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, The Basic Political Writings, trans. Cress, D. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987).Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M., What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).Google Scholar
Schneewind, J. B., “The Divine Corporation and the History of Ethics,” in Rorty, R., Schneewind, J. B., and Skinner, Q., eds., Philosophy in History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), pp. 173–191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shafer-Landau, Russ, Moral Realism: A Defence (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sher, George, “Transgenerational Compensation,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (2005), pp. 181–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simmons, A. John, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978).Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin, “Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas,” History and Theory 8 (1969), pp. 3–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Michael, The Moral Problem (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994).Google Scholar
Sturgeon, Nicholas, “Moral Explanations,” in Sayre-McCord, G., ed., Essays on Moral Realism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989), pp. 229–255.Google Scholar
Sunstein, Cass, Legal Reasoning and Political Conflict (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996).Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles, Hegel (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Timmons, Mark, Morality Without Foundations: A Defense of Ethical Contextualism (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Turley, David, Slavery (Oxford: Blackwell, 2000).Google Scholar
Roojen, Mark, “Knowing Enough to Disagree: A New Response to the Moral Twin Earth Argument,” in Shafer-Landau, Russ, ed., Oxford Studies in Metaethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 161–193.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. David, “Narrative Explanation,” The Philosophical Review 112 (2003), pp. 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy, “Justice Revisited,” The Times Literary Supplement, no. 4707, June 18, 1993, pp. 5–6.
Waldron, Jeremy, “Rawls's Political Liberalism,” in Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 149–163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wedgwood, Ralph, “Conceptual Role Semantics for Moral Terms,” The Philosophical Review 110 (2001), pp. 1–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wedgewood, Ralph, “The Meaning of ‘Ought’,” in Shafer-Landau, Russ, ed., Oxford Studies in Metaethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006).Google Scholar
Wertheimer, Alan, “Internal Disagreements: Deliberation and Abortion,” in Macedo, Stephen, ed., Deliberative Politics: Essays on Democracy and Disagreement (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 170–183.Google Scholar
White, Hayden, Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth Century Europe (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1973).Google Scholar
Wikipedia, , “Assisted Living,” http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Assisted_living
Williams, Bernard, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985).Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, Truth and Truthfulness (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002).Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “Internal and External Reasons,” in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), pp. 101–113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, “Philosophy and the Understanding of Ignorance,” in Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006).Google Scholar
Young, Robert J. C., Postcolonialism: An Historical Introduction (Oxford: Blackwell, 2001).Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

  • Works cited
  • Christopher McMahon, University of California, Santa Barbara
  • Book: Reasonable Disagreement
  • Online publication: 11 September 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511596742.008
Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

  • Works cited
  • Christopher McMahon, University of California, Santa Barbara
  • Book: Reasonable Disagreement
  • Online publication: 11 September 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511596742.008
Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

  • Works cited
  • Christopher McMahon, University of California, Santa Barbara
  • Book: Reasonable Disagreement
  • Online publication: 11 September 2009
  • Chapter DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511596742.008
Available formats
×