Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-5c6d5d7d68-thh2z Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-08-13T07:20:12.193Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Intuitions, intuitionism, and moral judgment

from PART II - INTUITION, OBLIGATION, AND VIRTUE

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 May 2015

Robert Audi
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame, Indiana
Get access

Summary

Ethical intuitionism has now taken a place as a major position in contemporary ethical theory. But there is still a widespread impression that the view depends on concepts and theses that are insufficiently clear for the work they must do or, if clear enough to sustain the view, then not plausible. One question here is what constitutes an intuition. Another is how intuitive cognitions differ from inferential ones. There is also a need to address the question of just how ethical intuitionism depends on the answer. This paper addresses all three questions and, in the light of what we find in pursuing them, explores the resources of intuitionist ethical theory for providing an understanding of how moral judgments may be justified.

I The nature and varieties of intuitions

Intuitions are important not only for intuitionist ethical theories but also for philosophy in general. Indeed, even many philosophers who do not speak of intuitions theorize as if they were in part seeking to provide an account of shared intuitions, say intuitions about knowledge or obligation. They are what we might call intuitivists. An intuitivist must be responsive to intuitions, but need not be an intuitionist. The term ‘intuition’ is, in any case, not crucial for understanding intuitionism. The main point is that philosophy, like any theoretical enterprise, requires data, and intuitions are crucial philosophical data. For Rawls among many others, our data include the “considered judgments” that, when suitably placed in reflective equilibrium with principles of justice, confirm the latter. The judgments constituting our data at least roughly fit the characterization of (cognitive) intuitions to be given shortly.

I am taking intuitionism as an ethical theory to be, in outline and in a minimal version, the view that there is at least one moral principle that is non-inferentially and intuitively knowable. Historically, intuitionists have also posited what they consider an irreducible plurality of such principles, and I propose to call this stronger view, on which there is a group of at least several such moral principles (such as we find in W. D. Ross and others) generic intuitionism.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2015

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Audi, Robert (1986a) “Acting for Reasons,” Philosophical Review 95(4): 75–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert (1986b) “Belief, Reason, and Inference,” Philosophical Topics 14(1): 27–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert (1989) “The Separation of Church and State and the Obligation of Citizenship,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 18(3): 259–96.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert (1994) “Dispositional Beliefs and Dispositions to Believe,” Noûs 28(4): 419–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert (1995) “Memorial Justification,” Philosophical Topics 23(1): 31–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert (1997) “The Place of Testimony in the Fabric of Knowledge and Justification,” American Philosophical Quarterly 34(4): 404–42.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert (1999) “Self-Evidence,” Philosophical Perspectives 13: 205–28.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert (2000) Religious Commitment and Secular Reason. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert (2001a) The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and Substance of Rationality. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert (2001b) “A Kantian Intuitionism,” Mind 110(439): 601–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert (2004) The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. PrincetonUniversity Press.
Audi, Robert (2006a) “Ethical Generality and Moral Judgment,” in Dreier, James (ed.), Contemporary Debates in Ethical Theory. Oxford: Blackwell, 285–304.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert (2006b) Practical Reasoning and Ethical Decision. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert (2007) “Intuition, Reflection, and Justification,” in Timmons, Greco, and Mele, 201–21.CrossRef
Audi, Robert (2008) “Skepticism about the A Priori,” in Greco, John (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism. Oxford University Press, 149–75.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert (2010a) Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge. London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert (2010b) “Moral Perception and Moral Knowledge,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 84: 79–94.Google Scholar
Bealer, George (1998) “Intuition and the Autonomy of Philosophy,” in DePaul and Ramsey, 201–39.
Broad, C. D. (1930) Five Types of Ethical Theory. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Crisp, Roger (2006) Reasons and the Good. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DePaul, Michael, and Ramsey, William (eds.) (1998) Rethinking Intuition. Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Erlenbaugh, Joshua, and Molyneux, Bernard (2009) “Intuitions as Inclinations to Believe,” Philosophical Studies 145: 89–109.Google Scholar
Ewing, A. C. (1953) Ethics.New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Gert, Joshua (2006) “Review: Robert Audi's The Good in the Right,” Mind 115(457): 121–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hernandez, Jill Graper (2011) The New Intuitionism. London: Continuum.Google Scholar
Huemer, Michael (2005) Ethical Intuitionism. Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Kappel, Klemens (2002) “Challenges to Audi's Intuitionism,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 5: 391–413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, G. E. (1903) Principia Ethica. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mulgan, Tim (2006) Future People. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, John (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D. (1930) The Right and the Good. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ross, W. D (1939) Foundations of Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Sellars, Wilfrid (1956) “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind,” in Feigl, H. and Scriven, M. (eds.), The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychoanalysis, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. i. Minneapolis, Minn.: University of Minnesota Press. Reprinted in Sellars (1963), Science, Perception and Reality. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul; reissued in 1991 by Ridgeview Publishing Co., Atascadero, Calif., 127–96.Google Scholar
Sellars, Wilfrid (1975) “The Structure of Knowledge,” in Castañeda, Hector-Neri (ed.), Action, Knowledge and Reality: Essays in Honor of Wilfrid Sellars. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 295–347.Google Scholar
Shafer-Landau, Russ (2007) “Audi's Intuitionism,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74(1): 250–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry (1907) The Methods of Ethics. Seventh edn. London: Macmillan; Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962.Google Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2007) “Reflections on Reflection in Robert Audi's Moral Intuitionism,” in Timmons, Greco, and Mele, 19–30.CrossRef
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (ed.) (2008) Moral Psychology, vol. ii. The Cognitive Science of Morality: Intuition and Diversity. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sosa, Ernest (1998) “Minimal Intuitionism,” in DePaul and Ramsey, 257–69.
Stratton-Lake, Philip (2000) Kant, Duty and Moral Worth. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Timmons, Mark, Greco, John, and Mele, Alfred R. (eds.) (2007) Rationality and the Good: Critical Essays on the Ethics and Epistemology of Robert Audi. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tolhurst, William (1998) “Seemings,” American Philosophical Quarterly 35: 293–302.Google Scholar

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×